Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Robot. AI, 05 November 2024
Sec. Robot Learning and Evolution
This article is part of the Research Topic Autonomous (re)Production, Learning and Bio-inspired Robotics Workshop View all 5 articles

Evolutionary robotics as a modelling tool in evolutionary biology

  • Bristol Robotics Laboratory, UWE Bristol, Bristol, United Kingdom

The use of evolutionary robotic systems to model aspects of evolutionary biology is well-established. Yet, few studies have asked the question, “What kind of model is an evolutionary robotic system?” This paper seeks to address that question in several ways. First, it is addressed by applying a structured model description developed for physical robot models of animal sensorimotor systems, then by outlining the strengths and limitations of evolutionary robotics for modelling evolutionary biology, and, finally, by considering the deepest questions in evolution and which of them might feasibly be modelled by evolutionary robotics. The paper concludes that although evolutionary robotics faces serious limitations in exploring deeper questions in evolutionary biology, its bottom-up approach to modelling populations of evolving phenotypes and their embodied interactions holds significant value for both testing and generating hypotheses.

1 Introduction

Evolutionary algorithms (EAs) are typically used to discover novel solutions to difficult design problems. Perhaps the most famous real-world example is an evolved satellite antenna design (Hornby et al., 2006). EA and its application in robotics, evolutionary robotics (ER), are thus seen as a technique for search or optimisation. However, evolutionary robotics may also be used to explore questions in evolutionary biology.

The idea of robots as scientific instruments is not new: Grey Walter’s electromechanical robot tortoises, machina speculatrix, were designed and built to test ideas in neuroscience. There is no doubt that Walter’s robots were the first biologically inspired robots (Holland, 2003b). The use of robotics as a comparative method in ecology and biology is well-established (Krause et al., 2011; Lauder, 2022), and as the literature surveys of Trianni (2014) and Doncieux et al. (2015) show, ER systems have also been used to model a wide range of interesting questions in evolutionary biology, including, notably, the co-evolution of predator–prey behaviour (Floreano and Nolfi, 1997), brain–body co-evolution (Lipson and Pollack, 2000), the evolution of altruism (Waibel et al., 2011), and the evolution of task specialisation of social insects (Ferrante et al., 2015). However, few works have sought to ask what kind of model an ER system is.

This paper proceeds as follows: Section 2 introduces the idea that robots can be scientific instruments. Section 3 outlines notable examples of experimental evolutionary robotics that have shed new light on the evolution of fish backbones, altruism, and modularity, exploring, with model descriptions, how ER systems model aspects of evolutionary biology before developing a critique of these models. Section 4 concludes with a discussion of deeper questions in evolutionary biology and whether they can or cannot be reasonably modelled with ER, as well as a set of recommendations for roboticists interested in studying evolutionary biology.

2 Robots as scientific instruments

The idea of robots that are not designed for their real-world utility but instead as scientific instruments is not new. If not the first, then certainly, the best-known example is W. Grey Walter’s machina speculatrix. Between 1948 and 1949, Walter, a neurophysiologist, designed and built two autonomous robots, which he named Elmer and Elsie. Their design was motivated by his theory of brain function, in particular that “cerebral functions may derive not so much from the number of [neurons], as from the richness of their interconnections” (Walter, 1953). Walter designed the robots’ control system with, as he put it, “a simple two-cell nervous system.” The ‘cells’ were vacuum tubes, and by variously connecting the cells with the robot’s sensors and motors, the robots demonstrated four distinct behaviours: exploration, obstacle avoidance, and both positive and negative phototaxis (Holland, 2003a).

Figure 1 (left) shows two replicas of Walter’s robots built in the Bristol Robotics Laboratory by Ian Horsfield. In Figure 1 (right), we see one of Walter’s famous experiments, in which Elsie first moves toward a lamp, then ignores the lamp while avoiding an obstacle, and then shows positive phototaxis to move toward the lamp. When the robot gets close to the lamp, a combination of positive and negative phototaxis causes it to move around the lamp. Arguably, the two cells are equivalent to what we would now call a single-layer recurrent artificial neural network. The analogy is apt, given that Walter’s design fully exploited the non-linear properties of the vacuum tubes. He reportedly “…stressed the importance of using purely analogue electronics to simulate brain processes at a time when his contemporaries such as Turing and von Neumann were all turning toward a view of mental processes in terms of digital computation”1.

Figure 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Left: Amy and Ninja, replicas of Walter’s machina speculatrix. Right: a time-lapse photograph of one of Walter’s 1949–50 experiments with Elsie showing obstacle avoidance and both positive and negative phototaxis (image: archive of the Burden Neurological Institute).

The fact that Walter’s machina speculatrix are robots built with purely scientific aims is not an accident. Walter was well aware of the synthetic method, a term employed by the contemporary psychologist Kenneth Craik “to describe the process of testing behavioural theories through machine models” (Bisig et al., 2008). Walter himself wrote: “In general, it is legitimate to study a model of a mysterious process if three conditions are fulfilled: 1. several features of the mystery must be known. 2. The model must contain the absolute minimum of working parts to reproduce the known features. 3. The model must reproduce other features, either as predictions or as unexpected combinations” (Walter, 1953, 280).

In recent decades, the synthetic method, in which robots are used as working models, has become well-established in the study of both animal behaviour and physiology: an approach that has become known as either artificial ethology (Holland and McFarland, 2001) or simply biorobotics (notably, the term biorobotics also includes biologically inspired or biomimetic robots). Examples include the landmark work on cricket phonotaxis by Webb (1995) and the work on collective sorting and segregation by Melhuish et al. (1998). However, the use of evolutionary robotics for modelling aspects of evolutionary biology is much less well-established.

2.1 Related work

There are few works that critically examine the potential of ER as a tool for addressing questions in evolutionary biology, although the rationale for doing so was neatly articulated by Maynard Smith in 1992: “so far, we have been able to study only one evolving system, and we cannot wait for interstellar flight to provide us with a second. If we want to discover generalizations about evolving systems, we have to look at artificial ones” (Maynard Smith, 1992).

In ‘Evolutionary robotics: model or design?’ Trianni (2014) offered, perhaps, the first thorough review and critique of evolutionary robotics as a modelling tool for biology. Trianni makes the case that ER uniquely provides us with a bottom–up model of an evolving population of model organisms that allows us to “identify the causal relationship between selective pressures and adaptive traits, thanks to the possibility of having complete control over the evolutionary process.” In ‘Evolutionary robotics: what, why, and where to,’ Doncieux et al. (2015) asked the question “Evolutionary robotics, for whom?” and addressed biologists, asserting that “evolutionary robotics provides tools for modelling and simulating evolution with unique properties: considering embodied agents that are located in a realistic environment makes it possible to study hypotheses on the mechanistic constraints at play during evolution” that are “particularly relevant for modelling behaviours where complex interactions within the group and with the environment are at work.”

This paper aims to build upon and complement these works by addressing the question, “What kind of model is an ER system?” This question is explored by outlining three notable ER models of evolutionary biology alongside model descriptions using the approach proposed by Webb (2001) (introduced below), and by doing so, this paper addresses Eiben (2021)’s call for “instruments to formally describe and analyse evolutionary robot systems.” The subsidiary contributions are as follows: (i) a proposed extension to Webb’s model for ER, (ii) an analysis of the strengths and limitations of ER for modelling evolutionary biology, (iii) a review of the major transitions in evolution and which of these might be addressed by ER, and (iv) recommendations for roboticists proposing to model biology with ER.

3 What kind of model is an evolutionary robotic system?

In seeking to address this question, a good place to start is Barbara Webb’s paper titled ‘Can robots make good models of biological behaviour?’ (Webb, 2001), which focuses on building physical robot models of biological sensorimotor systems in order to investigate problems in biology. The paper sets out a framework with seven dimensions for comparing robot models of biological behaviour as a structured approach for evaluating and comparing different modelling approaches in the context of biological systems. Webb concluded that “a dimensional description should not be primarily considered as a means of ranking models as ‘better’ or ‘worse’ but rather as an elucidation of potential strategies,” with a strategy of “increasing relevance and commitment to really testing biological hypotheses; …aspiring to accuracy but concerned with building complete systems; looking for a closer behavioural match; and using real physical interaction as part of the medium.” Webb’s seven dimensions, the questions they each address, and a commentary/interpretation are given in Table 1.

Table 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Webb’s seven dimensions for describing models. The dimensions and questions are from Webb (2001). For each dimension, an interpretation has been added.

Let us now review three notable examples of artificial evolutionary systems that have addressed questions in evolutionary biology. These three case studies have been chosen to represent very different levels of generality, abstraction, and structural accuracy. They also cover a very broad range of targets: physical traits of aquatic vertebrae, collective behaviour within a model ecosystem, and the evolution of modularity. For each of these studies, a description using Webb’s dimensions is made in order to compare and contrast the three models.

3.1 The evolution of fish biomechanics

John Long is well known for his use of evolutionary robotics to investigate the biomechanics of fish (Long, 2012). We consider his work using ER to test the hypothesis that vertebrae in ancient fish “evolved as a locomotor adaptation, stiffening the body axis and enhancing swimming performance” (Long et al., 2006). Long and his team extended biomimetic evolutionary analysis (BEA), which builds physical simulations of extinct systems, to include the use of autonomous robots as models of early vertebrates competing in a foraging task. They designed a biomimetic tadpole robot, called Tadro, with a biomimetic tail. Tadro has a single eyespot (photoresistor), a flapping tail, and a controller that converts the light intensity at the eyespot into a turning angle at the tail.

In this work, three physical Tadro robots compete to reach and encircle a light source (the food target) in a water tank. The robots’ fitness, called navigational prowess (NP), was rewarded by four measures: short time to reach the target, small orbital radius, fast swimming speed, and low robot wobble. The genome coded for two parameters, the robot’s flapping tail bending modulus and length, which together determine stiffness. Following selection, crossover, and mutation, the next-generation robot’s tails (biomimetic notochords) were fabricated by hand with cylindrical hydro-gels formed from gelatine (analogous to individual vertebrae), which were then connected by a flexible glue (analogous to inter-vertebral discs). Long et al. (2006) concluded that “we see evidence to support the classical hypothesis that vertebrae stiffen the body and that increased tail stiffness increases thrust production and steady swimming speed,” although interestingly adding the rider that “this formulation, however, avoids a central evolutionary question: under what ecological and selective conditions might vertebrae evolve?”.

Table 2 describes Long’s model using Webb’s dimensions. Here, we see that the biological relevance is high with a clearly identified target: the evolution of vertebrae in ancient fish. The level, or unit, of the model is very specific: a backbone with variable stiffness. The model is not abstract and has relatively low complexity, yet it has sufficient structural accuracy to model the effect of vertebrae stiffness on swimming, thus both supporting the classical hypothesis and providing a good performance match.

Table 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Description of Long et al. (2006) using Webb’s model dimensions of Table 1.

3.2 The evolution of cooperation and altruism

Next, we consider the work of Waibel, Floreano, and Keller, which made use of the miniature ALICE robots to evolve cooperative and altruistic behaviours (Waibel et al., 2009; Waibel et al., 2011). In these experiments, a group of robots forage by finding and collecting physical tokens and moving them to a nest area. The experimental arena contained two kinds of tokens: small tokens that can be pushed by a single robot and larger tokens too heavy to be pushed by a single robot. The fitness of each robot was based on its success in foraging for tokens. In one experiment, the arena contained only large tokens, and the robots successfully evolved the ability to cooperatively push these tokens to the nest.

However, when the arena contained both large and small tokens, the group ‘kin structure,’ i.e., the genetic relatedness of the individuals, influenced the evolved behaviours. Groups of genetically unrelated robots evolved toward pushing the small tokens because this was the best way to maximize their own fitness. In contrast, related robots evolved altruistic behaviours—cooperating to push the large tokens at the expense of their own individual fitness. The result quantitatively confirms Hamilton’s rule that altruistic behaviours will evolve when the relatedness of individuals multiplied by the fitness benefit to the receiver of the altruistic behaviour is greater than the fitness cost of performing the behaviour (Bourke, 2014). See Table 3 for a description of Waibel et al. (2009)’s model using Webb’s dimensions, in Table 1.

Table 3
www.frontiersin.org

Table 3. Description of Waibel et al. (2009) against Webb’s model of Table 1.

In contrast with Table 2, here, Waibel et al. (2009)’s model is abstract, with a lower level of biological relevance as no specific animals are modelled. Instead, in Table 3, the general class of cooperative groups, or social animals, is modelled. The level (or unit) of the model is a simple model ecosystem, in which each individual is modelled with a mobile robot. In common with Long et al. (2006)’s model in Table 2, the generality, structural accuracy, and performance match are all high, demonstrating that lower biological relevance and higher abstraction do not limit the value of the model.

3.3 The evolution of modularity

Our third case study is concerned not with the evolution of particular traits but instead the evolution of modularity. It is well known that biological evolution is highly modular. Complex organisms are assemblages of pre-evolved components; cells are ubiquitous building blocks for evolution; and organs such as eyes, hearts, and livers or sub-systems such as vascular or digestive systems are themselves modules that are re-used with often surprisingly little change across species within a given taxonomic class (e.g., Mammalia) (von Dassow and Munro, 1999).

With an elegant application of the evolutionary algorithm, Clune et al. challenged the sole focus on selective forces as the origin of biological modularity (Clune et al., 2013). Unlike the two previous works outlined in this section, Clune et al. are not concerned with physical robots. Instead, they evolve the controller, an artificial neural network, of a conceptual creature in simulation. The ANN evolves to recognize patterns (objects) in a simple eight-pixel retina. Importantly, the problem is modularly decomposable because whether an object exists on the left or right sides can be separately determined before combining that information to determine whether objects exist on both sides. Evolving the ANN with selection for performance alone resulted in non-modular networks that are slow to adapt to new environments. However, the simple addition of a second selection pressure to reduce connectivity in the ANN led to the evolution of modular networks that show faster adaptation in new environments than the non-modular networks, as illustrated in Figure 2.

Figure 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Two evolutionary processes: upper, based on performance alone; lower, based on both performance and connectivity costs. Diagram from Clune et al. (2013), with permission.

The biological relevance of Clune et al. (2013)’s model in Table 4 using Webb’s classification is arguably low as no general class of animals is modelled here. Yet, the model remains highly relevant as even the simplest animals exhibit modularity, and the model has the highest generality of all three: the evolution of evolvability, which is “the ability of a biological system to produce phenotypic variation that is both heritable and adaptive” (Payne and Wagner, 2019). This model is highly abstract with a low structural accuracy, yet, in common with all three models, it shows a good performance match.

Table 4
www.frontiersin.org

Table 4. Description of Clune et al. (2013) using Webb’s model dimensions.

3.4 Extending Webb’s model description for evolutionary robotics

It is clear that the example model descriptions in Tables 24 are incomplete. There are several important dimensions present in ER models that are not covered by Webb’s model description. This is hardly surprising, given that Webb’s model description was developed primarily with single-robot models in mind. ER also has robot models, but as Figure 3 shows, it additionally evolves a population of phenotypes, which involves genotype to phenotype mapping, selection, and fitness evaluation.

Figure 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. Four-stage process of evolutionary robotics, which depicts a quadrupedal robot where the length of the upper and lower leg segments of each leg is evolved; from Winfield (2012).

Table 5 proposes several additional dimensions, which, together with Webb’s model, would allow us to provide a more complete description of ER models. The first three dimensions in Table 5 simply provide the number of gene pools, population sizes, and the number of generations in a run of the ER model. In the study of Long et al. (2006) of Section 3.1, there is one gene pool, with a population of three phenotypes, and the ER model was run for 10 generations. In contrast, the study of Waibel et al. (2009) of Section 3.2 has a population of 1,000 organised into teams of 10 robots each, and the model was run for 300 generations. These details should be included in the model description.

Table 5
www.frontiersin.org

Table 5. Proposed set of additional ER model dimensions.

The mapping dimension in Table 5 concerns the mapping from genotype to phenotype, which may be direct or indirect. If indirect, then the description should provide the details. Doncieux et al. (2015) provided a good description of genotype to phenotype mapping. Brain/body very simply describes whether the ER model evolves the controller alone, the body morphology alone, or both. Our sixth proposed new dimension specifies the fitness function (or functions if there is more than one co-evolving species). For a survey of fitness functions in ER, see Nelson et al. (2009). Selection strategy specifies the method used to select the fittest individuals. For a survey of selection strategies, see Fernández Pérez et al. (2014).

The final dimension is concerned with evolutionary developmental biology, known by the shorthand ‘evo-devo’ (Nuño de la Rosa and Müller, 2020). In recent years, evo-devo has become important in ER, and some argue that “if it evolves, it needs to learn” (Eiben and Hart, 2020). There have been a number of very elegant experimental studies in artificial evo-devo. Kriegman et al. (2018), for instance, evolved, in simulation, a population of soft-bodied robots each consisting of a 4 x 4 x 3 grid of voxels. The soft robots evolved the ability to move over a flat terrain as quadrupeds, but, interestingly, sometimes, they learnt a new rolling morphology during their lifetime. Although not modelling biology, Kriegman et al. (2018) showed that “development, under the right conditions, can increase evolvability.” Should such evo-devo systems be developed to model evo-devo in biology, then the final dimension in Table 5 evo-devo will be needed in the model description.

As an example, Table 6 shows an extended model description for the work of Long et al. (2006), as outlined in Section 3.1 above, demonstrating the value of extending Webb’s model description for ER in providing a much more complete picture.

Table 6
www.frontiersin.org

Table 6. Description of Long et al. (2006) using the extended model description proposed here.

3.5 Observations, strengths, and limitations

Consider the schematic description of a complete ER system in Figure 3. All three of the case studies above follow the broad approach of Figure 3. The work of Long et al. (2006) in Section 3.1 evolves the robot morphology, as in Figure 3, whereas the works of Waibel et al. (2011) and Clune et al. (2013) evolve only the robots’ controller ANNs, so the genomes specify connection weights rather than physical properties.

Figure 3 prompts two important observations. The first is that the model depicted here is a high-level macro model, with several sub-models. The three Darwinian operators: selection, variation, and heredity are modelled here. Stages (1) and (2) model selection, stage (3) models variation, and stage (4) models heredity. All evolution requires a population of conspecifics, and this population is modelled in all four stages. Another sub-model present here is the model genome, and the phenotype instantiated from a single genome is—if we are modelling biology—a model of an animal. Notably, in this illustration, the genotype (complete set of genetic material) consists of just one genome (or more correctly, an allele) as the phenotype is fixed, with the exception of only the eight upper and lower leg segment lengths.

A second and key observation is that ER does not model natural selection. As Eiben and Smith (2015) put it, “evolutionary algorithms are not faithful models of natural evolution.” Rather, ER models artificial selection. This is neither surprising, given that the whole idea of ER is to discover novel robot designs, nor is it a bad thing. The first four chapters of On the Origin of Species lay out Darwin’s case that selection in nature, driven by the struggle for existence, is analogous to the selection of variations under domestication (Darwin, 1859). Human farmers and herders have been successfully cultivating improved varieties of grains, vegetables, and animals for at least 10,000 years; a process that was very well-understood in Darwin’s time. Figure 3 is thus more accurately described as a process of robot husbandry, and therefore, it is a putative model of animal husbandry. The case studies above clearly demonstrate that an artificial selection/animal husbandry model can be used to test hypotheses in evolutionary biology.

Open-ended evolution has been the subject of investigation of several studies in ER. Bianco and Nolfi (2004), for instance, proposed a framework for an open-ended evolutionary process in hardware, noting that, “In the case of natural evolution, there are no selection criteria that determine whether individuals can or cannot reproduce aside from the ability to reproduce itself.” Bredeche and Montanier (2012) described an experimental work in simulation and with real robots that demonstrates environmental-driven, distributed, and open-ended evolution. Although of great interest, this work is not offered as an ER model of natural selection in biology, which remains a very significant challenge.

We now consider the strengths and limitations of ER, as specified in Figure 3, as a model of evolutionary biology.

3.5.1 Strengths

1. When modelling is the only option: as Trianni (2014) and Doncieux et al. (2015) argue, ER models allow us to explore questions in evolutionary biology that would not be possible with living animals or ecosystems. Trianni (2014) stated that “ER is especially fruitful when it is impossible or unpractical to run experiments directly with the biological system, either as laboratory or field work.”

2. Multiple ‘species’: ER allows us to co-evolve the behaviours of different ‘species’ within a single ER model by providing two (or potentially more) gene pools. It is important to stress that these are separate species by design, when, in the model, we do not allow interbreeding across the gene pools. One example is given in Section 3.2 above, with the evolution of cooperation and altruism. Another great example is the work of Floreano and Nolfi (1997), which demonstrates the co-evolution of predator–prey behaviour. Note that two or more species in a single ER model also requires two or more corresponding fitness functions. Floreano and Nolfi (1997) maintained a population of 100 predators and 100 prey, which were subject to selection for successful predation and predator evasion, respectively.

3. The richness of matter: when ER systems make use of real physical robots for fitness testing, as in the first two case studies above, the ER model benefits in two important ways. (i) Real robots must contend with the physics of the real world. This is especially relevant in Long et al. (2006)’s work, as outlined in Section 3.1 above. The real robots have to float and swim in water, the same medium as the fish the robots are modelling. Any effort to simulate the same swimming robots would invariably suffer a loss of fidelity, given the difficulty of simulating the complex dynamics of the interactions between the tail and water. With real robots in a real medium, all of that complexity comes for free. (ii) When several real robots interact during fitness testing, as in the work of Waibel et al. (2009) outlined in Section 3.2 above, the model benefits because each robot is slightly different. The small heterogeneities of robots that have slightly different motors, wheels that might not be precisely aligned, and sensors that are not identical, etc., add a degree of stochasticity that, although not identically, models the heterogeneities of animal conspecifics. This adds valuable richness to these ER models.

4. Controllable conditions: a clear benefit of an ER model is that the initial conditions of the model are fully specified, which include the initial phenotype(s), selection, crossover and mutation processes, fitness function(s), and the fitness testing environment. This provides a high degree of repeatability. Inevitably, if fitness testing makes use of real robots, then, as outlined above, the stochasticity of the environment and the physical robots will likely alter the course of evolution across successive runs from identical starting conditions. Arguably, this is a feature of an ER model rather than a bug, given that biological evolution is both contingent and “surprisingly repeatable among closely related lineages” (Blount et al., 2018).

3.5.2 Limitations

1. Sparse environment: Most animals evolve in a complex and dynamic environment that goes through cyclic changes: day–night and seasonal changes plus occasional traumatic variations. Yet, in ER fitness evaluation, step (1) in Figure 3 typically takes place in a static test arena, with simple features designed to test the robots’ fitness. Only when co-evolving cooperative or antagonistic behaviours is there a semi-dynamic environment, in that one ‘species’ of moving robot(s) provides an environment for the other(s), but this falls far below the level of richness of real-world ecological niches. We know that the environment strongly influences natural selection, but we know little about how it does so (Payne and Wagner, 2019). There have, however, been ER studies that focus on the way the environment influences robot morphology. Miras et al. (2020), for instance, evolved multi-segmented modular robots for locomotion on both flat and tilted surfaces, and Corucci et al. (2018) evolved soft robots in simulation for both terrestrial and aquatic environments and the transition between them while also varying the material properties of the soft robots. Although not offered as a model of evolutionary biology, the latter work does offer potentially valuable insights. Corucci et al. (2018) reported an asymmetry in the effects of moving between land and water: “while moving from land to water resulted to be detrimental for the evolution of swimming, the opposite transition (land to water) pointed out some benefits for the evolution of walking.”

2. Small evolutionary distance: If, as suggested above, ER is a process of robot husbandry, then it is axiomatic that there needs to be an initial population of robots from which better (or different) robots can be bred. We, therefore, need to hand design the phenotype(s) of the first generation with properties, including sensing, actuation, and a control system, that appropriately model the kinds of animals that are the subject of our inquiry. This means that there is typically a very small evolutionary distance, as a result of the small population size and number of generations (relative to biological evolution), between the initial designed population and the final population at the point we choose to halt the ER model. One important corollary is that evolutionary branching, the “spontaneous transition from a unimodal trait distribution into a bimodal one,” is almost impossible when the “effective population size or mutational effect is sufficiently small” (Wakano and Iwasa, 2012). As the example from Long et al. (2006) outlined in Section 3.1 above shows, ER cannot model the evolution of a backbone but only the evolution of a better backbone.

3. Weak genotype to phenotype mapping: In evolutionary biology, it is now well known that the ‘genes as blueprint’ metaphor is not only inadequate but also misleading (Pigliucci, 2010). In an excellent survey of open issues in ER, Silva et al. (2016) reported that the majority of ER studies use direct encoding; they also make the important point that indirect encodings “enable representational efficiency … by incorporating concepts from evolutionary developmental biology.” In recent years, compositional pattern-producing networks (CPPNs) have become popular (Cheney et al., 2013). For an analysis of the strengths and weaknesses of CPPNs, see Silva et al. (2016). CPPNs, although more biologically plausible than direct mapping, do not constitute a model of genotype to phenotype mapping in evolutionary biology. For a recent account of genetic representations for co-evolving behaviour and morphology in ER, see De Carlo et al. (2024).

4. The reality gap: Given the time and resource cost of physically building robot phenotypes for fitness testing, a popular approach in ER has been to simulate multiple generations of evolution in software until robots judged fit enough have evolved, and then to build and test those. This strategy, known as ‘simulate and transfer to real,’ is efficient but suffers from the well-known reality gap (Jakobi et al., 1995). For a very good overview of the many subsequent approaches to crossing the reality gap, see Silva et al. (2016). When ER is modelled entirely in hardware, as in Long et al. (2006), there is no gap. However, a hardware-only ER model is not only very costly in time and resources but also reduces the evolutionary distance (limitation 2) still further. Thus, hybrid software ER models into which hardware phenotype instantiation and fitness testing are periodically intercalated are preferred (Eiben et al., 2021). Evolution is an extremely energy and resource-intensive process (Winfield, 2014), and thus, it should come as no surprise that ER models are also costly in time and resources.

4 Concluding discussion

Clearly, we can use ER to ask interesting but straightforward questions relative to the complexity of many questions in evolutionary biology, as shown in the case studies in Section 3 above. However, what questions in evolutionary biology are too difficult to address with an ER model?

Consider Maynard Smith and Szathmáry’s seminal work, The Major Transitions in Evolution (Maynard Smith and Szathmáry, 1995). Might ER be able to model any of the eight transitions set out in that work? The first three transitions: (1) from replicating molecules to populations of molecules in proto-cells, (2) from independent replicators to chromosomes, and (3) from RNA to DNA, are clearly out of scope of ER, in which we hand-design the replicator. Transition (4) from prokaryotes to eukaryotes is also out of scope, given that this transition is concerned with the evolution of the structure of single-celled organisms. Transition (5) is the evolution of sex, from asexual clones to sexual organisms (most single-celled eukaryotes reproduce sexually). Modelling this transition is problematic because sexual reproduction remains a mystery in evolutionary biology, described as both a paradox and the “queen of problems” (Bell, 1982; MacPherson et al., 2023). However, a recent work describing a real-robot ER system with mutable diploid genes, which models death, rebirth, and breeding in a stochastically varying landscape, hints at the potential of ER for modelling the emergence of sexual reproduction (Wang et al., 2022)2.

Transition (6), the evolution of multicellularity, could, in principle, be modelled by combining modular robotics (in which robot modules model cells) and ER. The Symbrion project, for instance, did combine collective, modular, and evolutionary robotics within a single framework (Schlachter et al., 2008). In Symbrion, individual modules, when acting as a swarm, represented stem cells. When triggered by one robot encountering an environmental cue (such as an obstacle too high to climb), that robot initiates the formation of a ‘multi-cellular’ organism, in which each “cell” differentiates in order to behave in a specific way, according to its physical location in the organism (Liu and Winfield, 2010). However, this process of autonomous morphogenesis was programmed, and the technical complexity meant that modelling the evolutionary emergence of multicellularity was impossible. The first two limitations outlined in section 3.5 above, the sparse environment and short evolutionary distance, will almost certainly thwart any efforts to model the evolution of multicellularity. Evolutionary developmental soft robots may, however, provide a pathway to modelling transition (6) (Corucci et al., 2017).

The same two limitations may also prevent ER from feasibly modelling transition (7), the evolution of eusociality (colonies with non-reproductive castes). However, one evolutionary swarm robotics study has notably demonstrated the emergence of one aspect of eusociality: task specialisation in social insects. Ferrante et al. (2015) reported a surprising result that division of labour “could be achieved merely by selecting on overall group performance and without pre-specifying how the global task of retrieving items would best be divided into smaller subtasks.” In addition to advancing the field of evolutionary swarm robotics, the work of the paper offers a possible explanation for the origin of division of labour in social insects.

Transition (8) is the evolution of culture from primate societies to human societies with language and culture. Since this transition concerns behavioural or memetic evolution, it does not require an ER model as the phenotype does not need to evolve. A relatively simple model in which a group of real robots demonstrate the evolution of new behavioural traditions has been developed (Winfield and Blackmore, 2022). In this model, the three Darwinian operators of selection, mutation, and heredity are present, but rather than genes, it is behaviours (memes) that are selected and mutated across successive generations of meme.

Consider also niche construction. Biological complexity apparently arises from an evolutionary arms-race, in which organisms both adapt to and exploit niches in their ecosystem and, in doing so, co-create that ecosystem. As Levins and Lewontin (1985) pointed out, the organism is both the subject and the object of evolution. Niche construction is the process by which organisms continuously modify their own and others’ niches; from a niche construction perspective, “evolution consists of mutual and simultaneous processes of natural selection and niche construction” (Laland et al., 2000). The sparse environment limitation almost certainly rules out ER as a model of niche construction.

The discussion above appears to rule out ER as a method for modelling the deepest questions in evolutionary biology. However, provided that we fully understand their limitations, ER models can, and have already, addressed interesting questions in evolutionary biology. Within the scope are questions on how particular traits evolve in particular kinds of animals. It also includes questions on how interaction between different ‘species’ might evolve. In addition to the predator–prey behaviour of Floreano and Nolfi (1997) and cooperative behaviours of Waibel et al. (2011), we might be able to model symbiosis, mutualism, or even parasitism. More abstract questions that might also be within scope include the dynamics of brain–body evolution or the trade-offs between morphological and computational intelligence (Zahedi and Ay, 2013). As Trianni (2014) writes, “In the ER context, considerable caution is needed, given that artificial evolution is a very simplified model of natural evolution:” he also suggests that it is “…wrong to a priori proscribe ER as a modelling tool, but it is necessary to evaluate case by case whether the proposed ER model can be of some value.”

To that end, several recommendations follow. Roboticists proposing to use ER to study aspects of evolutionary biology should ideally:

1. Have a reasonable understanding of evolutionary biology3.

2. Given that framing research questions in evolutionary biology is itself not straightforward, roboticists should work with evolutionary biologists, either as member(s) of the research team or as advisor(s). In particular, the biologist(s) would guide the framing of the research question and its context within evolutionary biology.

3. Following Trianni (2014), adopt a hypothesis-driven rather than exploratory approach, in which the whole experimental design is conceived for the purpose of testing or generating hypotheses4.

4. Take great care to fully understand the properties and limitations of the model they are building using, for instance, the case studies of Section 3 and Webb’s extended model description in Section 3.5 above.

5. Employ the principle of ceteris paribus by fixing all but one of the subsystems of an ER system and their parameters. The only parameters that should be allowed to vary are coded in the genome, the very parameters that are evolving.

6. Resist the temptation to use the same ER system to evolve real-world-useful robots while also seeking answers to questions in evolutionary robotics. ER systems cannot be used as scientific instruments and discoverers of novel robots for the real world at the same time.

In conclusion, it is clear that ER is a weak model of evolutionary biology. Its primary weakness is that essentially, ER models artificial selection not natural selection. This combined with sparse model environments, typically small population sizes and number of generations leading to a small evolutionary distance and weak genotype to phenotype mapping, mean that the level of abstraction of ER models is often high. These weaknesses impose serious limitations on the bigger questions in evolutionary biology that can be feasibly explored in a way that has value. Despite these manifest weaknesses, ER’s bottom–up approach of modelling populations of evolving phenotypes and their embodied interactions with each other and their environment does have considerable value for biologists for both testing and generating hypotheses.

Using evolutionary robotics to rigorously address research questions in evolutionary biology is without doubt the most challenging application of robots as scientific instruments to date. Rising to this challenge is certainly a worthy goal.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article; further enquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

AW: Writing–original draft.

Funding

The author(s) declare that financial support was received for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. The work of this paper has been conducted within the EPSRC project Autonomous Robot Evolution; grant reference EP/R035679/1.

Acknowledgments

The bare bones of this paper were presented at the Autonomous (re)Production, Learning, and Bio-inspired Robotics workshop at the University of York in October 20225, and the author is very grateful for the discussion and encouragement to develop those ideas into this paper. The author is also deeply grateful to the reviewers for their thorough and insightful comments, from which many improvements followed.

Conflict of interest

The author(s) declared that they were an editorial board member of Frontiers, at the time of submission. This had no impact on the peer review process and the final decision.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors, and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Footnotes

1https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Elmer_and_Elsie_(robots)

2The authors propose that “diploid gene robots can act as avatars of diploid mammalian cells to explore novel programs of administration of drugs.”

3For recommended reading on evolution, see https://www.sciencefocus.com/books/best-evolution-books/

4Trianni (2014) warns that “exploratory studies (in which experiments are conducted to understand the possibilities offered by robotics and ER as a modelling tool) are the most susceptible to find themselves in the limbo between modelling and design.”

5https://www.york.ac.uk/robot-lab/are/workshop/#tab-3

References

Bell, G. (1982). The masterpiece of nature: the evolution and genetics of sexuality. 1st ed. USA: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Bianco, R., and Nolfi, S. (2004). Toward open-ended evolutionary robotics: evolving elementary robotic units able to self-assemble and self-reproduce. Connect. Sci. 16, 227–248. doi:10.1080/09540090412331314759

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bisig, D., Geiser, R., and Pfeifer, R. (2008). Understanding by design. the synthetic approach to intelligence, Explorations in Architecture. Boston: Birkauser.

Google Scholar

Blount, Z., Lenski, R., and Losos, J. (2018). Contingency and determinism in evolution: replaying life’s tape. Science 362, 362. doi:10.1126/science.aam5979

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bourke, A. F. G. (2014). Hamilton’s rule and the causes of social evolution. Phil Trans. R. Soc. Lond B Biol. Sci. 369, 20130362. doi:10.1098/rstb.2013.0362

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bredeche, N., and Montanier, J.-M. (2012). Environment-driven open-ended evolution with a population of autonomous robots. Evol. Phys. Syst. Workshop (East Lansing, United States).

Google Scholar

Cheney, N., MacCurdy, R., Clune, J., and Lipson, H. (2013). “Unshackling evolution: evolving soft robots with multiple materials and a powerful generative encoding,” in Proceedings of the 15th Annual Conference on Genetic and Evolutionary Computation, New York, NY, USA, July 6 - 10, 2013 (New York, NY: Association for Computing Machinery), 167–174. doi:10.1145/2463372.2463404

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clune, J., Mouret, J.-B., and Lipson, H. (2013). The evolutionary origins of modularity. Proc. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 280, 20122863. doi:10.1098/rspb.2012.2863

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Corucci, F., Cheney, N., Giorgio-Serchi, F., Bongard, J., and Laschi, C. (2018). Evolving soft locomotion in aquatic and terrestrial environments: effects of material properties and environmental transitions. Soft Robot. 5, 475–495. doi:10.1089/soro.2017.0055

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Corucci, F., Cheney, N., Kriegman, S., Bongard, J., and Laschi, C. (2017). Evolutionary developmental soft robotics as a framework to study intelligence and adaptive behavior in animals and plants. Front. Robotics AI 4, 34. doi:10.3389/frobt.2017.00034

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species by means of natural selection. USA: John Murray.

Google Scholar

De Carlo, M., Ferrante, E., Zeeuwe, D., Ellers, J., and Eiben, A. E. (2024). Heritability of morphological and behavioural traits in evolving robots. Evol. Intell. 17, 1733–1749. doi:10.1007/s12065-023-00860-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Doncieux, S., Bredeche, N., Mouret, J.-B., and Eiben, A. E. G. (2015). Evolutionary robotics: what, why, and where to. Front. Robotics AI 2. doi:10.3389/frobt.2015.00004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eiben, A. (2021). Real-World Robot evolution: why would it (not) work? Front. Robotics AI 8, 696452. doi:10.3389/frobt.2021.696452

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eiben, A., and Smith, J. (2015). From evolutionary computation to the evolution of things. Nature 521, 476–482. doi:10.1038/nature14544

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eiben, A. E., and Hart, E. (2020) “If it evolves it needs to learn,”Proceedings of the 2020 Genetic and Evolutionary Computation Conference Companion, New York, NY, USA, July 6 - 10, 2013, 20. New York, NY: Association for Computing Machinery, 1383–1384. doi:10.1145/3377929.3398151

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eiben, A. E., Hart, E., Timmis, J., Tyrrell, A. M., and Winfield, A. F. (2021). Towards autonomous robot evolution. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 29–51. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-66494-7_2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fernández Pérez, I., Boumaza, A., and Charpillet, F. (2014). “Comparison of selection methods in on-line distributed evolutionary robotics,” in The Fourteenth International Conference on the Synthesis and Simulation of Living Systems of Artificial Life Conference Proceedings, China, 2017-01-24, 282–289. doi:10.1162/978-0-262-32621-6-ch046

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ferrante, E., Turgut, A. E., Duéñez-Guzmán, E., Dorigo, M., and Wenseleers, T. (2015). Evolution of self-organized task specialization in robot swarms. PLoS Comput. Biol. 11, e1004273. doi:10.1371/journal.pcbi.1004273

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Floreano, D., and Nolfi, S. (1997). “Adaptive behavior in competing co-evolving species,” in In Proc. 4th European Conference on Artificial Life, China, July 23, 1997, 378–397.

Google Scholar

Holland, O. (2003a). Exploration and high adventure: the legacy of Grey Walter. Philosophical Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 361, 2085–2121. doi:10.1098/rsta.2003.1260

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Holland, O. (2003b). The first biologically inspired robots. Robotica 21, 351–363. doi:10.1017/S0263574703004971

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Holland, O., and McFarland, D. (2001). Artificial ethology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Hornby, G., Globus, A., Linden, D., and Lohn, J. (2006). Automated antenna design with evolutionary algorithms. Space 2006. doi:10.2514/6.2006-7242

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jakobi, N., Husbands, P., and Harvey, I. (1995). “Noise and the reality gap: the use of simulation in evolutionary robotics,” in Advances in artificial life. Editors F. Morán, A. Moreno, J. J. Merelo, and P. Chacón (Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg), 704–720.

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Krause, J., Winfield, A. F., and Deneubourg, J.-L. (2011). Interactive robots in experimental biology. Trends Ecol. and Evol. 26, 369–375. doi:10.1016/j.tree.2011.03.015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kriegman, S., Cheney, N., and Bongard, J. (2018). How morphological development can guide evolution. Sci. Rep. 8, 13934. doi:10.1038/s41598-018-31868-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, J., and Feldman, M. W. (2000). Niche construction, biological evolution, and cultural change. Behav. Brain Sci. 23, 131–146. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00002417

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lauder, G. V. (2022). Robotics as a comparative method in ecology and evolutionary biology. Integr. Comp. Biol. 62, 721–734. doi:10.1093/icb/icac016

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Levins, R., and Lewontin, R. (1985). The dialectical biologist. Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Lipson, H., and Pollack, J. B. (2000). Automatic design and manufacture of robotic lifeforms. Nature 406, 974–978. doi:10.1038/35023115

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Liu, W., and Winfield, A. F. T. (2010). “Autonomous Morphogenesis in Self-assembling Robots using IR-Based sensing and local communications,” in Swarm intelligence. Editors M. Dorigo, M. Birattari, G. A. Di Caro, R. Doursat, A. P. Engelbrecht, D. Floreanoet al. (Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg), 107–118.

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Long, J. (2012). Darwin’s devices. New York: Basic Books.

Google Scholar

Long, J. J. H., Koob, T. J., Irving, K., Combie, K., Engel, V., Livingston, N., et al. (2006). Biomimetic evolutionary analysis: testing the adaptive value of vertebrate tail stiffness in autonomous swimming robots. J. Exp. Biol. 209, 4732–4746. doi:10.1242/jeb.02559

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

MacPherson, B., Scott, R., and Gras, R. (2023). Using individual-based modelling to investigate a pluralistic explanation for the prevalence of sexual reproduction in animal species. Ecol. Model. 475, 110191. doi:10.1016/j.ecolmodel.2022.110191

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maynard Smith, J. (1992). Byte-sized evolution. Nature 355, 772–773. doi:10.1038/355772a0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maynard Smith, J., and Szathmáry, E. (1995). The major transitions in evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Melhuish, C., Holland, O., and Hoddell, S. (1998). “Collective sorting and segregation in robots with minimal sensing,” in From animals to animats: proc. 5th int. Conf. On simulation of adaptive behaviour (USA: MIT Press), 456–470.

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Miras, K., Ferrante, E., and Eiben, A. E. (2020). Environmental influences on evolvable robots. PLOS ONE 15, 02338488–e233923. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0233848

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nelson, A. L., Barlow, G. J., and Doitsidis, L. (2009). Fitness functions in evolutionary robotics: a survey and analysis. Robotics Aut. Syst. 57, 345–370. doi:10.1016/j.robot.2008.09.009

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nuño de la Rosa, L., and Müller, G. B. (2020). A reference guide to evo-devo. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 1–10. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-33038-9_194-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Payne, J. L., and Wagner, A. (2019). The causes of evolvability and their evolution. Nat. Rev. Genet. 20, 24–38. doi:10.1038/s41576-018-0069-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pigliucci, M. (2010). Genotype–phenotype mapping and the end of the ‘genes as blueprint’ metaphor. Philosophical Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 365, 557–566. doi:10.1098/rstb.2009.0241

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schlachter, F., Meister, E., Kernbach, S., and Levi, P. (2008). “Evolve-ability of the robot platform in the Symbrion project,” in 2008 Second IEEE International Conference on Self-Adaptive and Self-Organizing Systems Workshops, 20-24 Oct. 2008 (China), 144–149. doi:10.1109/SASOW.2008.31

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Silva, F., Duarte, M., Correia, L., Oliveira, S. M., and Christensen, A. L. (2016). Open issues in evolutionary robotics. Evol. Comput. 24, 205–236. doi:10.1162/EVCO_a_00172

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Trianni, V. (2014). Evolutionary robotics: model or design? Front. Robotics AI 1. doi:10.3389/frobt.2014.00013

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

von Dassow, G., and Munro, E. M. (1999). Modularity in animal development and evolution: elements of a conceptual framework for EvoDevo. J. Exp. zoology 285 (4), 307–325. doi:10.1002/(sici)1097-010x(19991215)285:4<307::aid-jez2>3.0.co;2-v

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Waibel, M., Floreano, D., and Keller, L. (2011). A quantitative test of Hamilton’s rule for the evolution of altruism. PLOS Biol. 9, e1000615–e1000617. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1000615

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Waibel, M., Keller, L., and Floreano, D. (2009). Genetic team composition and level of selection in the evolution of cooperation. IEEE Trans. Evol. Comput. 13, 648–660. doi:10.1109/TEVC.2008.2011741

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wakano, J. Y., and Iwasa, Y. (2012). Evolutionary branching in a finite population: deterministic branching vs. stochastic branching. Genetics 193, 229–241. doi:10.1534/genetics.112.144980

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Walter, W. G. (1953). The living brain. New York: W. W. Norton.

Google Scholar

Wang, G., Phan, T. V., Li, S., Wang, J., Peng, Y., Chen, G., et al. (2022). Robots as models of evolving systems. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 119, e2120019119. doi:10.1073/pnas.2120019119

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Webb, B. (1995). Using robots to model animals: a cricket test. Robotics Aut. Syst. 16, 117–134. doi:10.1016/0921-8890(95)00044-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Webb, B. (2001). Can robots make good models of biological behaviour? Behav. Brain Sci. 24, 1033–1050. doi:10.1017/S0140525X01000127

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Winfield, A. (2012). Robotics: a very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Winfield, A. F. (2014). “Estimating the Energy cost of (artificial) evolution,” in Proc. 14th conf. On the synthesis and simulation of living systems (ALIFE 14) (USA: MIT Press), 726–733.

Google Scholar

Winfield, A. F. T., and Blackmore, S. (2022). Experiments in artificial culture: from noisy imitation to storytelling robots. Philosophical Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 377, 20200323. doi:10.1098/rstb.2020.0323

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zahedi, K., and Ay, N. (2013). Quantifying morphological computation. Entropy 15, 1887–1915. doi:10.3390/e15051887

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: evolutionary robotics, evolutionary biology, synthetic method, robots as scientific instruments, model description

Citation: Winfield AFT (2024) Evolutionary robotics as a modelling tool in evolutionary biology. Front. Robot. AI 11:1278983. doi: 10.3389/frobt.2024.1278983

Received: 17 August 2023; Accepted: 06 September 2024;
Published: 05 November 2024.

Edited by:

Vito Trianni, Institute of Cognitive Sciences and Technologies, Italy

Reviewed by:

Eric Medvet, University of Trieste, Italy
Tom Wenseleers, KU Leuven, Belgium

Copyright © 2024 Winfield. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Alan F. T. Winfield, YWxhbi53aW5maWVsZEBicmwuYWMudWs=

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.