
94% of researchers rate our articles as excellent or good
Learn more about the work of our research integrity team to safeguard the quality of each article we publish.
Find out more
OPINION article
Front. Psychol.
Sec. Perception Science
Volume 16 - 2025 | doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2025.1564251
The final, formatted version of the article will be published soon.
Select one of your emails
You have multiple emails registered with Frontiers:
Notify me on publication
Please enter your email address:
If you already have an account, please login
You don't have a Frontiers account ? You can register here
Aphantasia-the inability to consciously experience mental imagery-has emerged as one of the most intriguing phenomena in cognitive psychology and neuroscience (see e.g., Nanay, 2021;Zeman, 2024). Recently, we proposed an interoceptive model of aphantasia, suggesting that the condition arises from suboptimal processing in the insula (Silvanto & Nagai, 2025a).In this model, interoception contributes to imagery on two interrelated components: (1) the integration of interoceptive input with sensory information, which anchors imagined content in the bodily self and gives rise to a sense of embodiment, and (2) sense of agency, which enables the voluntary initiation and control of mental content. Here, we apply a predictive coding framework to aphantasia and propose that reduced interoceptive precision disrupts the brain's ability to generate high-gain top-down predictions about imagined content. As a result, predictive signals from the prefrontal cortex fail to sufficiently activate parietal and visual regions, preventing the formation of coherent sensory representations and leading to the failure of mental imagery to reach conscious awareness.The embodied nature of imagery (Murake et al., 2023), and the importance of integrating interoceptive input with sensory representations, have been discussed in detail (Silvanto & Nagai, 2025). In contrast, the mechanisms through which interoception contributes to the sense of agency in mental imagery have been less explored. The sense of self-often referred to as bodily self-consciousness-is composed of two main components: body ownership (the feeling that your body belongs to you; e.g., Tsakiris et al., 2010) and sense of agency (the feeling that you are in control of your own actions; Gallagher, 2007;Haggard, 2017). These experiences emerge from the integration of information from within the body (interoception), the external environment, and intentional actions (e.g., Blanke et al., 2015;Haggard et al., 2008). Interoception connects bodily sensations to intentional movements, grounding the sense of agency (Tsakiris, 2010). The experience of agency emerges from anticipatory mechanisms within the motor system. The brain generates an internal duplicate of a motor instruction-often referred to as an efference copy-which forecasts forthcoming bodily states and associated sensory feedback (Frith, 2005). This prediction is then evaluated against both the intended goal and the actual outcome, facilitating rapid motor adjustments and reinforcing the feeling of control. Within the comparator framework, when expected and actual results match, the sense of agency is affirmed; if discrepancies arise, the sensation of control diminishes. This mechanism aligns with predictive coding models, in which the brain continuously updates its predictions about sensory input to minimize error (Seth et al., 2015).The importance of agency is reflected in the fact that, while individuals with aphantasia are unable to generate voluntary mental images, they can still experience involuntary imagery, such as dreams. For instance, Zeman et al. (2015) reported that 17 of 21 individuals with weak or absent visual imagery experienced visual dreams. In a larger study by Zeman et al. (2020) found that 63.4% of 2,000 participants with aphantasia reported visual dreaming. While dreams are often less vivid and frequent in aphantasia, their preservation, despite the absence of voluntary imagery, suggests that volitional control is the primary factor disrupted in aphantasia (but see Krempel & Monzel, 2024, for an alternative view). During sleep, interoceptive input is suppressed (Wey & Van Someren, 2020) and interoceptive feelings during dreaming are uncommon (Mazza et al, 2012). The (at least partial) preservation of dreaming in aphantasia highlights the distinction of interoceptive involvement in voluntary vs involuntary imagery, with the former reflective of aphantasia.There is some initial evidence linking sense of agency to aphantasia (Silvanto & Nagai, 2025b).Individuals with stronger sense of general agency (a measure reflecting agency across various situations and circumstances) were more likely to report experiencing mental imagery (as measured with the Vividness of Visual Imagery Questionnaire). This indicates that a general bias towards interpreting events as self-generated facilitates mental imagery, particularly in individuals at the lower end of imagery spectrum. However, it is important to note that this study relied entirely on self-report measures. Future experiments should complement these findings with behavioural paradigms (e.g., intentional binding) and neuroimaging techniques to test causal relationships clarify the underlying neural mechanisms.A large network of brain regions has been linked to the sense of agency, including the premotor cortex, supplementary motor areas (SMA and pre-SMA), insula, posterior parietal cortex (PPC), and the cerebellum (e.g., Haggard, 2017). One key challenge has been to distinguish neural activity related to sensory input from that associated with subjective experiences of the bodily self. Harduf et al. (2023) addressed this challenge using the rubber hand illusion, a phenomenon where individuals perceive a fake rubber hand as part of their body (Ehrsson et al., 2004). They found that while multisensory integration in occipital and fronto-parietal regions encoded sensory inputs, participants who experienced heightened agency during the illusion exhibited stronger connectivity between the insula, left occipital cortex, and somatosensory regions. Greater illusory body ownership was associated with increased connectivity between the insula and somatosensory cortices, underscoring the insula's critical role in integrating sensory and interoceptive signals.The insula is thought to support agency by integrating interoceptive and sensory inputs to align predicted and actual bodily states. It plays a central role in integrating autonomic, visceral, and somatic information to support emotional awareness and self-representation (Critchley et al., 2005). The insula is also part of the default mode network, a system active during self-directed thought and introspection (Uddin, 2015). By facilitating interoceptive awareness and anchoring internal states within the broader framework of self-referential cognition, the insula helps create an embodied sense of self. From a predictive coding perspective, the sense of agency arises as the brain generates top-down predictions about the sensory consequences of actions and refines them based on interoceptive and sensory feedback (Seth, 2013). The insula contributes by integrating interoceptive priors, which provide a physiological foundation for agency by aligning internal bodily states with motor and sensory predictions. The anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) further refines these predictions by monitoring prediction errors, ensuring coherence between expected and actual outcomes.Predictive coding offers a broad explanatory framework for conscious experience by proposing that the brain constructs reality by integrating exteroceptive and interoceptive priors to minimize prediction error (Seth, 2012(Seth, , 2015)). Conscious experiences arise when top-down expectations are precise enough to successfully predict incoming input, thereby minimizing error. When errors are too large, perception becomes unstable or fragmented; when too small, experience becomes overly rigid, dominated by inflexible priors. In this framework, mental imagery involves the generation of high-level predictions that are both precise and embodied, even in the absence of external input. Interoceptive priors provide affective and bodily grounding, while motor-based forward models (internal predictions of the sensory consequences of self-generated actions) confer a sense of agency; both are essential for internally generated simulations to become conscious.Mental imagery relies on internally generated top-down predictions to activate sensory representations in the absence of external input. When imagery is voluntarily initiated, prefrontal regions generate predictions which activate sensory areas such as the visual cortex.For these predictions to give rise to imagery, they must be assigned sufficient gain-a process modulated by the insula, which evaluates the relevance and reliability of internal bodily states.The insula estimates the precision of interoceptive input and modulates the gain of top-down predictions, thereby influencing whether internally generated representations are treated as reliable and permitted to shape sensory inference. This gain modulation depends on two functions supported by the insula that are essential to imagery: agency, the capacity to initiate and control mental content, and embodiment, the integration of imagined content with bodily self-awareness. When either of these components is weakened, imagery becomes unstable and fails to reach conscious awareness.In this framework, agency depends on the brain's ability to predict the sensory consequences of self-generated mental actions, analogous to motor control systems in which efference copies anticipate the outcomes of movement (Frith, 2005). When interoceptive precision is low, the insula downregulates the gain of these top-down signals, leading to diminished confidence in the initiation of mental acts. As a result, imagery-related predictions fail to sufficiently activate visual cortex or stabilize coherent internal representations, leaving mental images incomplete, unstable, or absent from awareness. This same mechanism also applies embodiment. By aligning interoceptive priors with exteroceptive and higher-order predictions, the insula contributes to the embodied and self-referential quality of mental imagery. Through its interactions with parietal regions, it further shapes the affective salience and bodily relevance of perceptual priors, allowing imagined content to be experienced as personally meaningful. In this view, aphantasia reflects a failure to generate internally consistent predictions that are sufficiently grounded in bodily and volitional signals (see Figure 1).In perceptual processing, continuous bottom-up sensory input helps to constrain and update predictive models by providing real-time information about both the external environment and the internal bodily state. This input stabilizes perceptual inference, even in the presence of imprecise or underspecified top-down predictions. In contrast, mental imagery lacks such external sensory input and must rely exclusively on internally generated predictions; under these conditions, interoceptive input has a heightened role. When interoceptive signals are degraded or assigned low precision, top-down predictions lack sufficient gain to overcome prediction error and are downweighted; consequently, internally generated simulations fail to reach conscious experience. This framework helps to explain why disruptions to interoceptive processing may disproportionately impair mental imagery; whereas perception can be corrected and stabilized through external feedback, imagery depends entirely on the precision of top-down models. Consistent with this model, there is evidence for impaired top-down connectivity from prefrontal to visual cortices in aphantasia (Milton et al., 2021;Liu et al., 2024). Moreover, these impairments appear to extend beyond visual imagery, affecting cross-modal processes that rely on top-down feedback, such as the integration of auditory and visual information.Furthermore, Montañés de la Cruz et al. (2024) found that, in aphantasia, decoding of auditory scenes was preserved in auditory and multisensory cortices but reduced in early visual cortex, indicating that integration-based deficits in aphantasia apply not only to visual imagery but also to the broader coordination of information across sensory modalities. These findings can be readily accommodated within the insula-based model of aphantasia (cf. Silvanto & Nagai, 2025) by extending it to include impaired integration of not only nteroceptive and exteroceptive signals, but also within exteroceptive modalities themselves. The role of the insula as a central hub for multisensory integration is well established; it receives input from the thalamus and multiple cortical regions, allowing it to combine information from external senses such as vision, audition, touch, taste, and smell (e.g., Gogolla, 2017;Craig, 2009;Garfinkel & Critchley, 2016). Moreover, although not a primary processor of proprioceptive input, the insula contributes to constructing an internal model of the body's state by integrating interoceptive, exteroceptive, and proprioceptive signals, supporting cross-modal binding across these sensory domains in both perception and imagery. However, while the insula contributes to multisensory integration in both imagery and perception, imagery is more dependent on its modulatory function because it lacks bottom-up sensory input to stabilize cross-modal predictions. In contrast, perceptual systems can rely on externally driven prediction errors to align sensory modalities, making them less vulnerable to disruptions in interoceptive precision. As a result, when insular function is compromised, imagery-related processes are more likely be severly affected.In the interoceptive theory of imagery, aphantasia arises from disrupted processing in the insula (Silvanto & Nagai, 2025a). Two core components are affected: agency, the capacity for voluntary control over actions and mental states; and embodiment, the sense that mental content belongs to the self, arising from impaired integration of internal bodily states with sensory information. Predictive coding provides a mechanistic framework for understanding the role of the insula in aphantasia, specifically its function in modulating the precision of interoceptive signals and regulating the gain of top-down predictions originating from the prefrontal cortex, processes that are critical for generating consciously accessible mental imagery. It is important to acknowledge, however, that this model remains a theoretical proposal, as direct empirical evidence linking interoception and imagery in aphantasia is currently limited.
Keywords: aphantasia, Mental Imagery, interoception, insula, agency, predictive coding
Received: 21 Jan 2025; Accepted: 14 Apr 2025.
Copyright: © 2025 Silvanto. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
* Correspondence: Juha Silvanto, Center for Cognitive Brain Sciences, University of Macau, Taipa, 999078, Macau Region, China
Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.
Supplementary Material
Research integrity at Frontiers
Learn more about the work of our research integrity team to safeguard the quality of each article we publish.