Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 19 May 2022
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology
This article is part of the Research Topic Credition - An Interdisciplinary Approach to the Nature of Beliefs and Believing View all 42 articles

Believing and Appraising in Context: Cognizing Experiences as Events

  • 1Department of Religious Studies, University of California, Santa Barbara, Santa Barbara, CA, United States
  • 2Department of Psychology, Westmont College, Santa Barbara, CA, United States

It is clear that schemas and expectations unconsciously affect how people interpret their experience in real time (van Elk and Aleman, 2017; Van Leeuwen and van Elk, 2019). It is also clear that cultural beliefs as manifest in worldviews and ways of life affect how people consciously reflect on and reappraise their experiences (Kelly, 1955; Saroglou and Cohen, 2011, 2013). How these two processes are linked is not so clear. Here we argue that event cognition not only supplies a promising bridge between unconscious and conscious information processing, but allows us to further integrate research on unconscious appraisal processes (Scherer et al., 2001), conscious attributions (Kelley and Michela, 1980; Malle, 1999, 2004), and multi-level approaches to meaning making (Park and Folkman, 1997; Park, 2010; Markman et al., 2013) and believing (for an overview, see Seitz and Angel, 2020)1.

What Is an Event?

The Oxford English Dictionary defines events simply as things that happen. Philosophers tend to begin with this general definition when discussing events, noting that “this definition merely shifts the burden [of definition] to clarifying the meaning of ‘happen”’ (Casati and Varzi, 2020). For scientific purposes, it is important to distinguish between things that happen regardless of whether there is a living organism to perceive them and happenings that living organisms perceive. Molecules move and stars collide regardless of whether living organisms are present. In doing so happenings generate information. Because far more information is generated than any organism can perceive and process, organisms have evolved to perceive and process the information that they need to survive. Humans and some other animals do so by segmenting information, that is, by a cognitive process that divides it into chunks with a beginning and an end (Baldwin and Kosie, 2021; Ross and Easton, 2022).

Researchers who study this cognitive process define an event more technically as “a segment of time at a given location conceived by an observer to have a beginning and an end” (Zacks and Tversky, 2001, p. 3). This means that an event is spatially and temporally located and is perceived from the point of view of the subject. An event is constructed as the brain chunks the dynamic flow of incoming information into segments. Most researchers also agree that the extracted segment is perceived as coherent and causally related, which points to the basis on which we chunk the flow of information (Hohwy et al., 2021).

The cognitive definition of an event has implications for how we think about experience (an uncountable noun) and experiences (a plural noun). The former designates the flow of information of which we are aware. The latter are self-reported events that have a beginning and an end; this means that from a cognitive perspective, experiences are events regardless of whether they are externally verifiable or not (for fuller discussion, see Taves and Asprem, 2017). Treating experiences as events allows us to investigate how the flow of information of which we are aware (experience) is transformed cognitively into structured units (experiences) with a beginning and end that we can describe, remember, and recount if and when we attend to them. Doing so allows us to link subpersonal and personal levels of analysis and integrate several lines of research in psychology, including multi-level approaches to meaning making and believing.

What then is not an event? Although philosophers debate this issue, they generally agree that physical objects in isolation are not events and that events occur when things change or interact (Shipley, 2008; Casati and Varzi, 2020). If we extend the criterion of change to mental things, such as ideas, beliefs, concepts, and goals, then beliefs all by themselves are not events. Events occur when beliefs change or interact, i.e., in the process of believing. How then do we cognize events?

Working Models as Probabilistic Representations

Most researchers understand the processes by which events are initially cognized within a predictive processing framework (Hohwy et al., 2021).

Bottom-up input is weighed against a top-down prediction of what is happening based on prior experience. The prediction of what is happening is represented in a working model of an event. The working model is, thus, is a probabilistic assessment (i.e., appraisal) of incoming information in light of prior experience. The model is retained as long as it more or less fits with the incoming information. If there is a significant change in the input, an error signal is generated, which leads to a new or revised event model (Radvansky and Zacks, 2014, 2017; Zacks, 2020). The process of assessing the incoming information can be viewed as a meaning making process and the probabilistic assessment as an appraisal. The working model that is generated based on this assessment is a representation of the event. It can also be viewed as an implicit belief regarding what happened (Seitz et al., 2017, 2018; Paloutzian et al., 2021).

The working model is generated in working memory and thus is fleeting (like the dream you can't remember) unless transferred to long-term memory (Zacks, 2020, pp. 172–177). If the event is stored in long-term memory, we can remember it, narrate it, and reflect on it. In other words, the working model links what we consciously experience as happening with underlying cognitive processes and, if retained in long-term memory, allows us to recall and reflect on past events. Each time we recall an event, we construct a new event model in working memory with its own new spatio-temporal context.

In sum, the sensory input from the body, environment, and prior experience interact to form a working model of what is happening. Insofar as we are conscious of the contents of working memory, we are conscious of the contents of the working model. That is how we experience the event and come to believe—at least implicitly—that an event occurred (Seitz et al., 2022). If our experience is stored in long-term memory, we can remember and recount it. But these are separate events with their own working models of what is happening.

Working Models and Prior Experience

The working model is based on a probabilistic assessment of incoming information in light of prior experience (Zacks, 2020, pp. 177–180). In psychological terms, the brain assesses incoming information in light of schemas and expectations. Schemas and expectations, although likely built on shared, reliably developing templates, are typically elaborated in culturally specific ways and acquired through cultural learning. Each component of a working model—time, space, objects, sensations, relations, and causes—draws on prior experience. With respect to time, schemas provide an expected time frame for the event. With respect to space, schemas identify the specific place or type of space in which the event is occurring. Schemas and expectations determine the types of agents—visible and invisible—that may be involved, identify who is involved, what they are doing and why. They allow us to recognize the objects involved and assess what is happening to them. They allow us to identify what we are sensing or feeling. Finally, overall event schemas help us understand how all these things are related and what is causing it to happen. Because working models rely on prior experience, we would expect infants, foreigners, and experts to have representations of an event that differ from those of the average culturally literate adult.

Evolved and Cultural Knowledge

Although people's representations of an event differ based on their prior knowledge, human's evolved capacity to chunk the flow of information into events means that everyone—including infants—can recognize that something has happened. Thus, there is growing evidence that infants can attend to structured patterns in goal-directed activity and that these patterns provide a basic sense of where to segment the dynamic flow (Levine et al., 2019; Zacks, 2020). When we confront a new situation, we draw on those basic capabilities. Then, as we grow and develop in a particular time and place, we become able to comprehend and recall events with greater ease and accuracy. We become more “fluent.” We learn to pick out the relevant details of events that allow us to efficiently predict what is happening and guide us in deciding what to do. We do so in the context of particular culturally distinct ways of life. The event models of fluent adults are culture specific; they include appraisals and beliefs guided by and adapted to the culture in which one is imbedded (Baldwin and Kosie, 2021).

To illustrate, imagine a cultural event such as going to a Catholic Mass. A young child would understand that the event had a beginning and an end and contained any number of subevents, such as entering and leaving the church, walking to the front the church with their parents, and returning to their seats. When a bell was rung, the child's attention might be drawn to the altar and the man who is doing something there. An adult who knew nothing of Catholic ritual would also recognize these and other subevents. If they had experienced other rituals, they would likely recognize it as such, without knowing much else. Culturally fluent Catholics, however, would have internalized an event model of the Mass as a ritual that recapitulates Jesus' death and resurrection and his promise to be present in the sharing of bread and wine. They would know that the words of the priest over the bread and wine make Christ present and, thus, why the bell draws their attention to that point in the service.

Re-Appraising Events

Events, as they initially surface to awareness, can take many forms. Most are routine; we give them little thought. Some events, however, stand out because they are puzzling, surprising, disturbing, or life-changing. These are the events we tend to remember, recount, and in some cases reappraise. If an experience does not fit with what we have learned to expect or believe, we return to it to try to figure out what happened or how to cope with what we know or believe happened. This process of making meaning out of ambiguity, appraising it, remaking meaning, reappraisal, and so on has been well researched and documented as a series of events (Park and Folkman, 1997; Park, 2010; Markman et al., 2013).

Understanding the meaning making process as a series of events, therefore, implies that the initial appraisal of meaning takes place as part of the initial event. This generates what Park (2010) refers to as the “situational” meaning of the event. But when someone consciously assesses their initial sense of what happened in light of their overall set of beliefs and goals, that constitutes a subsequent event, and the processes of coping with discrepancies between the situational and global meanings generates a whole series of additional events with their modified beliefs.

The working model of what is happening now, thus, allows us to think in two directions. We can (1) think about change over time as an initial event that is reappraised in the context of subsequent events, or we can (2) think about the levels of processing that give rise to an event model in the context of a single event. The first is an explicit reflective cultural process; the second relies on culturally learned expectations and schemas that function as priors in the probabilistic assessment of what is happening at any given moment. Treating experiences as events allows us to consider the components that interact to generate an experience and compare the interaction of schemas and expectations with phenomenological features of experiences in a variety of different cultural contexts (for a full discussion, see Taves and Barlev, 2022).

Author Contributions

AT conceptualized the concept of events and how minds cognize events as related to the chunking and perception of things happening in real time. RP added their relationship to the processes of believing. Both authors contributed to the article and approved the submitted version.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's Note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Elliott Ihm, Rüdiger Seitz, and Hans-Ferdinand Angel for feedback on earlier drafts of this manuscript.

Footnotes

1. ^Psychological interest in events emerged within both clinical and experimental psychology to produce lines of research that focus on differences levels of analysis. In clinical psychology, Kelly's (1955) personal construct theory, which is centrally concerned with the role of constructs in the interpretation of events, was influenced by hermeneutic approaches in the humanities (Butt and Warren, 2016). In experimental psychology, the focus has been on the perceptual processes (i.e., mechanisms) involved in cognizing events (Shipley, 2008; Zacks, 2020).

References

Baldwin, D. A., and Kosie, J. E. (2021). How does the mind render streaming experience as events? Top. Cogn. Sci. 13, 79–105. doi: 10.1111/tops.12502

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Butt, T., and Warren, B. (2016). “Personal construct theory and philosophy.” in The Wiley Handbook of Personal Construct Psychology, eds. D. A. Winter and N. Reed. New York: John Wiley and Sons. doi: 10.1002/9781118508275.ch2

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Casati, R., and Varzi, A. (2020). “Events.” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. N. Zalta. Available online at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/events/

Google Scholar

Hohwy, J., Hebblewhite, A., and Drummond, T. (2021). Events, event prediction, and predictive processing. Top. Cogn. Sci. 13, 252–255. doi: 10.1111/tops.12491

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kelley, H. H., and Michela, J. L. (1980). Attribution theory and research. Ann. Rev. Psychol. 31, 457–501. doi: 10.1146/annurev.ps.31.020180.002325

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kelly, G. A. (1955). Psychology of Personal Constructs: Theory and personality. New York: Norton.

Google Scholar

Levine, D., Buchsbaum, D., Hirsh-Pasek, K., and Golinkoff, R. M. (2019). Finding events in a continuous world: a developmental account. Develop. Psychobiol. 61, 376–389. doi: 10.1002/dev.21804

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Malle, B. F. (1999). How people explain behavior: a new theoretical framework. Personal. Social Psychol. Rev. 3, 23–48. doi: 10.1207/s15327957pspr0301_2

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Malle, B. F. (2004). How the Mind Explains Behavior: Folk Explanations, Meaning, and Social Interaction. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/3586.001.0001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Markman, K. D., Proulx, T., and Lindberg, M. J. (Eds.) (2013). The Psychology of Meaning. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association. doi: 10.1037/14040-000

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Paloutzian, R. F., Seitz, R. J., and Angel, H.-F. (2021). “The processes of believing and communicating with the unseen.” in Human interaction with the divine, the sacred, and the deceased: Psychological, scientific, and theological perspectives, eds. T. G. Plante and G. E. Schwartz (1st ed.) (New York: Routledge), 213–233. doi: 10.4324/9781003105749-14

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Park, C. L. (2010). Making sense of the meaning literature: an integrative review of meaning making and its effects on adjustment to stressful life events. Psychol Bull. 136, 257–301. doi: 10.1037/a0018301

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Park, C. L., and Folkman, S. (1997). Meaning in the context of stress and coping. Rev. General Psychol. 1, 115–144. doi: 10.1037/1089-2680.1.2.115

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Radvansky, G. A., and Zacks, J. M. (2014). Event cognition. New York: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199898138.001.0001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Radvansky, G. A., and Zacks, J. M. (2017). Event boundaries in memory and cognition. Curr Opin Behav. Sci. 17, 133–140. doi: 10.1016/j.cobeha.2017.08.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ross, T. W., and Easton, A. (2022). The Hippocampal Horizon: Constructing and Segmenting Experience for Episodic Memory. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 132, 181–196. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2021.11.038

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Saroglou, V., and Cohen, A. B. (2011). Psychology of culture and religion: introduction to the JCCP special issue. J. Cross Cult. Psychol. 42, 1309–1319. doi: 10.1177/0022022111412254

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Saroglou, V., and Cohen, A. B. (2013). “Cultural and cross-cultural psychology of religion.” in Handbook of the Psychology of Religion and Spirituality, eds. R. F. Paloutzian and C. L. Park (Second Edition) (New York: Guilford Press), 330–354.

Google Scholar

Scherer, K. R., Schorr, A., and Johnstone, T. (eds.), (2001). Appraisal Processes in Emotion: Theory, Methods, Research (1 edition) (New York: Oxford University Press).

Google Scholar

Seitz, R. J., and Angel, H.-F. (2020). Belief formation—A driving force for brain evolution. Brain Cogn. 140, 105548. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2020.105548

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seitz, R. J., Angel, H.-F., and Paloutzian, R. F. (2022). Bridging the Gap Between Believing and Memory Functions.

Google Scholar

Seitz, R. J., Paloutzian, R. F., and Angel, H.-F. (2017). Processes of believing: where do they come from? What are they good for? F1000Research. 5, 2573. doi: 10.12688/f1000research.9773.2

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seitz, R. J., Paloutzian, R. F., and Angel, H.-F. (2018). From believing to belief: a general theoretical model. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 30, 1254–1264. doi: 10.1162/jocn_a_01292

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Shipley, T. F. (2008). “An invitation to an event.” in Understanding Events: From Perception to Action, T. eds. F. Shipley and J. M. Zacks (New York: Oxford University Press), 3–30.

Google Scholar

Taves, A., and Asprem, E. (2017). Experience as event: event cognition and the study of (religious) experiences. Religion, Brain, and Behavior 7, 43–62. doi: 10.1080/2153599X.2016.1150327

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Taves, A., and Barlev, M. (2022). A Feature-Based Approach to the Comparative Study of “Nonordinary” Experiences. American Psychologist. doi: 10.1037/amp0000990

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

van Elk, M., and Aleman, A. (2017). Brain mechanisms in religion and spirituality: an integrative predictive processing framework. Neurosci Biobehav Rev, 73, 359–378. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2016.12.031

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Van Leeuwen, N., and van Elk, M. (2019). Seeking the supernatural: the interactive religious experience model. Religion Brain Behav. 9, 221–251. doi: 10.1080/2153599X.2018.1453529

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zacks, J. M. (2020). Event perception and memory. Ann. Rev. Psychol. 71, 165–191. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-010419-051101

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zacks, J. M., and Tversky, B. (2001). Event structure in perception and conception. Psychol. Bull. 127, 3–21. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.127.1.3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: belief, believing, credition, event, event cognition, meaning making

Citation: Taves A and Paloutzian RF (2022) Believing and Appraising in Context: Cognizing Experiences as Events. Front. Psychol. 13:913603. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.913603

Received: 05 April 2022; Accepted: 02 May 2022;
Published: 19 May 2022.

Edited by:

Douglas A. MacDonald, University of Detroit Mercy, United States

Reviewed by:

Harris Friedman, University of Florida, United States

Copyright © 2022 Taves and Paloutzian. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Ann Taves, anntaves@ucsb.edu

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.