Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 10 October 2022
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology
This article is part of the Research Topic Physical Time Within Human Time View all 20 articles

From illusion to reality and back in time perception

  • 1Department of Criminology, Bar-Ilan University, Ramat Gan, Israel
  • 2The Leslie and Susan Gonda (Goldschmied) Multidisciplinary Brain Research Center, Bar-Ilan University, Ramat Gan, Israel

Assuming that time perception is, indeed, a form of perception (Glicksohn, 2001)—an area acknowledged as such, now and again, in textbooks on perception (Murch, 1973; Chap. 7; Coren et al., 2004; Chap. 11)—one can address what Gruber et al. (2022) refer to as the “two times problem”, as a problem for perception, and not one whose resolution must necessarily span between psychology and physics. Indeed, in agreement with Smythies (2003, p. 53), who suggests that “if one wants to account for our psychological impression that there is a ‘now’ in time and moreover that time in some way flows, we must look elsewhere than contemporary physics, whether Newtonian or Relativity, to find it”, it would be instructive to return to the Gestalt psychologist Kurt Koffka, who posed the classic question for theorists of perception, namely “why do things look as they do?” (Koffka, 1935; p. 76). In the present context, this can be rephrased as “why do we perceive time the way we do?” While Gruber et al. (2022) draw a distinction between “the veridical and illusory nature of time”, for the Gestalt psychologists, as Epstein and Hatfield (1994, p. 166) stress, “phenomenal experience is real … it is not illusory or suspect in any way.” Hence, even if the flow of time is considered to be illusory (Gruber et al., 2015), while time estimation might well be “real” (Gruber et al., 2020), both need to be addressed by psychology.

In a recent paper (Glicksohn and Ben-Soussan, under review)1, it has been suggested that “While a minority of researchers … accepted that subjective time could be neither veridical nor linear… the majority embraced … [the] view that subjective time could be both veridical and linear.” Either way, for Gruber et al. (2022) this would imply that subjective time (or, apparent duration, psychological time, or estimated time; Glicksohn, 2001; Buhusi and Meck, 2009) would be “real” (veridical, or not), to be contrasted with the flow of time (or, temporal flow, passage of time judgment, or perceived speed of time; Larson and von Eye, 2006; Wearden, 2015; Droit-Volet, 2018; Thönes et al., 2018; Vogel et al., 2020; Martinelli and Droit-Volet, 2022), which is “illusory”. And yet illusions (flow of time?), as Zavagno et al. (2015) have argued, “can be effective tools in studying the brain in reference to perception and also to cognition in a much broader sense.” Hence, even if the flow of time is an illusory construct, it might still be either correlated with subjective time (Eisler and Eisler, 2009) or dissociated from this (Wittmann et al., 2015; Droit-Volet and Wearden, 2016; Hancock et al., 2019). Of particular significance is the fact that the flow of time can be indicative of a state of flow (Larson and von Eye, 2006; Hancock et al., 2019; Kent et al., 2022) or a state of absorption (Woodrow, 1951; Glicksohn and Lipperman-Kreda, 2007; Glicksohn and Berkovich-Ohana, 2012; Mohr, 2018) in an ongoing activity.

Maybe, however, the flow of time is not an illusory construct. Koffka would probably disagree with Gibson's (1979) answer to his question, “that things look as they do because the information in proximal stimulation is what it is” (Epstein, 1994; p. 176).In turn, Gibson (1975) himself would probably argue against the very notion of time perception, and that time itself “is ‘real’ and can be directly perceived” (Larson and von Eye, 2006, p. 114). Nevertheless, it is still the case that the optic flow (Rogers, 2021) with which Gibson was primarily concerned might well be a ready source for the flow of time. Consider the case when your plane is descending toward the airport, and from the vantage of your window the optic flow is in continual flux. If the velocity were constant, your perceptual experience would be very different from the usual case wherein the plane is decelerating. One would not be surprised if the corresponding flow of time was also altered. In a recent study, a group of researchers looked at the flow of time on exposure to a starfield environment, and reported that “Passage of time experience was increased for faster stars and more dense starfields, but was not as much affected by the actual duration of the interval or the task difficulty. This shows that the salience of moment-to moment differences between individual frames is more directly associated with the experience of passage of time than is the actual duration of the interval” (Jording et al., 2022; p. 12). This comes in support of the suggestion made here that changes in optic flow might very well affect the flow of time. If that were the case, would both be considered to be illusory?

A reviewer of this commentary has questioned whether the issue of temporal continuity is ever directly addressed in passage of time judgments. Gruber et al. (2022) refer to the question asked of observers of “how fast time went”—namely, whether time was felt to pass quickly or slowly. As the reviewer astutely notes, that type of judgment can be affected by such a factor as boredom. Hence, the less or more bored one feels will affect the subsequent change in passage of time judgment, irrespective of the impact of the change in optic flow (as suggested here). My suggestion would be, therefore, to employ a question referring to the present, ongoing, subjective experience of the flow of time. For example, in a study employing virtual reality (Glicksohn and Avnon, 1997–1998), the experimenter lightly tapped the shoulder of the participant during the session, signaling the request for an introspective report. In a similar manner, one could send a text message to the participant asking for a current rating of the subjective experience of the flow of time. While this is certainly feasible, one should also consider the fact that in doing so, one is actually momentarily disrupting the ongoing experience of that participant. Sometimes, this can be fatal for the subjective experience under investigation. Nonetheless, in order to make a stronger argument regarding the suggestion made here relating change in optic flow with change in reported passage of time, this would be a necessary requirement for a future study in this domain.

A second way in which the flow of time might be affected can be derived from the multiplicative model for apparent duration (Glicksohn, 2001). According to this model, time production is a multiplicative function of two components: The size of the subjective time unit (which varies with context), and the number of these subjective time units. Kent et al. (2019) have recently applied this model in their discussion of time dilation, especially that related to depression. They suggest that “the mode of prospective time judgment in production tasks changes as intervals increase from around 1 s of the experienced moment into the 30 s range of mental presence” (p. 80). Specifically, “if it is assumed that the size of Glicksohn's (2001) time units can vary within the same interval, then units at the end of the interval will be relatively small compared to intervals at the beginning of the interval” (p. 78). This would suggest that “time accelerates as intervals increase, an effect which in itself may not be unique to depression. It may be a general feature of time perception that is simply more pronounced for depressed individuals” (p. 78). Hence, a reported change in flow of time might well be related to a discontinuity in time-production data [Glicksohn et al., 2017; Glicksohn and Ben-Soussan, under review (see text footnote 1)]. Indeed, as Martinelli and Droit-Volet (2022, p. 528) have recently suggested, the passage of time judgment curve “might not be as linear as observed” in their study, given extreme conditions. Perhaps, as Gruber et al. (2022, p. 1) argue, “the veridical system is a reflection of accepted spacetime cosmologies and through natural selection begets the illusory system for functional purposes”. What this means for the “two times problem” discussed by Gruber et al. (2022) is that one needs to consider not only the question of temporal continuity, which they believe to be an illusory experience, but also that of temporal discontinuity. It is not, however, clear to me whether such temporal discontinuity would also be considered to be an illusory experience.

Perhaps, as Conway et al. (2016) suggest, “humans should have a psychological mechanism for slowing time down as motion speeds up”—what they refer to as a “spacetime processor”. Who knows? Gruber et al. (2022) have certainly given us plenty of food for thought.

Author contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Footnotes

1. ^Glicksohn, J., and Ben-Soussan, T. D. (under review). Discontinuity in time perception, or inadequacy of psychophysical fit?

References

Buhusi, C. V., and Meck, W. H. (2009). Relativity theory and time perception: single or multiple clocks? PLoS ONE 4, e6268. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0006268

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Conway, L. G., Repke, M. A., and Houck, S. C. (2016). Psychological spacetime: Implications of relativity theory for time perception. SAGE Open 6, 1–14. doi: 10.1177/2158244016674511

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Coren, S., Ward, L. M., and Enns, J. T. (2004). Sensation and perception. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons.

Google Scholar

Droit-Volet, S. (2018). Intertwined facets of subjective time. Curr. Direct. Psychol. Sci. 27, 422–428. doi: 10.1177/0963721418779978

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Droit-Volet, S., and Wearden, J. (2016). Passage of time judgments are not duration judgments: evidence from a study using experience sampling methodology. Front. Psychol. 7, 176. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00176

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Eisler, A. D., and Eisler, H. (2009). Experienced speed of time in durations of known and unknown length. NeuroQuantology 7, 66–76. doi: 10.14704/nq.2009.7.1.208

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Epstein, W. (1994). “Why do things look as they do?”: What Koffka might have said to Gibson, Marr and Rock,” in Gestalt Psychology: Its Origins, Foundations and Influence, ed S. Poggi (Firenze: Leo S. Oschki Editore), 175–189.

Google Scholar

Epstein, W., and Hatfield, G. (1994). Gestalt psychology and the philosophy of mind. Philos. Psychol. 7, 163–181. doi: 10.1080/09515089408573118

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gibson, J. J. (1975). “Events are perceivable but time is not,” in The Study of Time II, eds J. T. Fraser, and N. Lawrence (New York: Springer-Verlag), 295–301.

Google Scholar

Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

Google Scholar

Glicksohn, J. (2001). Temporal cognition and the phenomenology of time: a multiplicative function for apparent duration. Consc. Cognit. 10, 1–25. doi: 10.1006/ccog.2000.0468

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glicksohn, J., and Avnon, M. (1997–1998). Explorations in virtual reality: absorption, cognition and altered state of consciousness. Imag. Cognit. Person. 17, 141–151. doi: 10.2190/FTUU-GLC5-GBT8-9RUW

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glicksohn, J., and Berkovich-Ohana, A. (2012). “Absorption, immersion, and consciousness,” in Video Game Play and Consciousness, ed J. Gackenbach (New York: Nova Science Publishers, Inc.), 83–99.

Google Scholar

Glicksohn, J., Berkovich-Ohana, A., Mauro, F., and Ben-Soussan, T. D. (2017). Time perception and the experience of time when immersed in an altered sensory environment. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 11, 487. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2017.00487

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glicksohn, J., and Lipperman-Kreda, S. (2007). Time, thought, and consciousness. J. Mind Behav. 28, 289–305.

Google Scholar

Gruber, R. P., Bach, M., and Block, R. A. (2015). Perceiving two levels of the flow of time. J. Consc. Stud. 22, 7–22.

Google Scholar

Gruber, R. P., Block, R. A., and Montemayor, C. (2022). Physical time within human time. Front. Psychol. 13, 718505. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.718505

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gruber, R. P., Montemayor, C., and Block, R. A. (2020). From physical time to a dualistic model of human time. Found. Sci. 25, 927–954. doi: 10.1007/s10699-020-09670-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hancock, P. A., Kaplan, A. D., Cruit, J. K., Hancock, G. M., MacArthur, K. R., and Szalma, J. L. (2019). A meta-analysis of flow effects and the perception of time. Acta Psychol. 198, 102836. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2019.04.007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jording, M., Vogel, D. H., Viswanathan, S., and Vogeley, K. (2022). Dissociating passage and duration of time experiences through the intensity of ongoing visual change. Sci. Rep. 12, 1–15. doi: 10.1038/s41598-022-12063-1

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kent, L., Nelson, B., and Northoff, G. (2022). Can disorders of subjective time inform the differential diagnosis of psychiatric disorders? A transdiagnostic taxonomy of time. Early Intervent. Psychiatry. doi: 10.1111/eip.13333

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kent, L., Van Doorn, G., and Klein, B. (2019). Time dilation and acceleration in depression. Acta Psychol. 194, 77–86. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2019.02.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Gestalt Psychology. New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace and World.

Google Scholar

Larson, E., and von Eye, A. (2006). Predicting the perceived flow of time from qualities of activity and depth of engagement. Ecol. Psychol. 18, 113–130. doi: 10.1207/s15326969eco1802_3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Martinelli, N., and Droit-Volet, S. (2022). What factors underlie our experience of the passage of time? Theoretical consequences. Psychol. Res. 86, 522–530. doi: 10.1007/s00426-021-01486-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mohr, C. (2018). Are there varying depths in flow? Altered states of consciousness, absorption, and the brain. J. Consc. Stud. 25, 115–130.

Google Scholar

Murch, G. M. (1973). Visual and Auditory Perception. New York, NY: The Bobbs-Merrill Company.

Google Scholar

Rogers, B. (2021). Optic flow: perceiving and acting in a 3-D world. i-Perception 12, 1–25. doi: 10.1177/2041669520987257

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smythies, J. (2003). Space, time and consciousness. J. Consc. Stud. 10, 47–56.

Google Scholar

Thönes, S., Arnau, S., and Wascher, E. (2018). Cognitions about time affect perception, behavior, and physiology: a review on effects of external clock-speed manipulations. Consc. Cognit. 63, 99–109. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2018.06.014

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vogel, D. H., Jording, M., Kupke, C., and Vogeley, K. (2020). The temporality of situated cognition. Front. Psychol. 11, 546212. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.546212

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wearden, J. H. (2015). Passage of time judgements. Consc. Cognit. 38, 165–171. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2015.06.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wittmann, M., Otten, S., Schötz, E., Sarikaya, A., Lehnen, H., Jo, H.-G., et al. (2015). Subjective expansion of extended time-spans in experienced meditators. Front. Psychol. 5, 1586. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01586

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Woodrow, H. (1951). “Time perception,” in Handbook of Experimental Psychology, ed S. S. Stevens (New York, NY: Wiley), 1224–1236.

Google Scholar

Zavagno, D., Daneyko, O., and Actis-Grosso, R. (2015). Mishaps, errors, and cognitive experiences: on the conceptualization of perceptual illusions. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 9, 190. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2015.00190

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: time perception, Gestalt psychology, flow of time, illusion, time estimation

Citation: Glicksohn J (2022) From illusion to reality and back in time perception. Front. Psychol. 13:1031564. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.1031564

Received: 30 August 2022; Accepted: 23 September 2022;
Published: 10 October 2022.

Edited by:

Carlos Montemayor, San Francisco State University, United States

Reviewed by:

Anne Giersch, Institut National de la Santé et de la Recherche Médicale (INSERM), France

Copyright © 2022 Glicksohn. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Joseph Glicksohn, gliksoj@biu.ac.il

ORCID: Joseph Glicksohn orcid.org/0000-0001-5584-177X

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.