Skip to main content

CONCEPTUAL ANALYSIS article

Front. Psychol., 23 July 2021
Sec. Psychology for Clinical Settings

Hallucinations and Delusions as Low-Quality Attributions: Influencing Factors and Proposal for Their Analysis

  • 1Personality, Evaluation and Psychological Treatment Department, University of Seville, Seville, Spain
  • 2Department of Psychology, University of Cádiz, Puerto Real, Spain
  • 3Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Seville, Seville, Spain

Hallucinations and delusions, in keeping with the distress accompanying them, are major features in the diagnosis of psychosis in international classifications. In spite of their human and clinical importance, the concepts are unclear. The distinction between hallucinations and delusions in terms of perception-thought is not precise enough, causing problems in analyzing the patient’s words. Nor are the differentiations or variations within each precise enough. Continuing the long clinical tradition discussing the distinction between hallucinations and delusions while assuming their similarities, this study poses a concept integrating the two phenomena as attributions people make about themselves and their settings. Then the elements of any attribution can be used as guides for structuring significant literature on both, and reduce analytical ambiguity. Such attributions make more sense within the structure of two-way relationships with factors in a person’s own framework and setting. This structure is described with its variables and relationships as a guide to assessment, follow-up, and intervention. Two checklists are provided for orientation.

Introduction

Hallucinations and delusions are manifestations that cause those who experience them enormous suffering (Varese et al., 2016; Garety et al., 2020). They are major factors in the diagnosis of psychotic disorders in the most widely used classifications (American Psychiatric Association [APA], 2013; World Health Organization [WHO], 2018). Hallucinations are Esquirol’s classical “perception without object” (1817), and delusions are basically thoughts which do not fit reality (Jaspers, 1913).

In spite of their human and clinical significance, the concepts are problematic. The definitions in the literature are themselves unclear (Garety et al., 2020) and varied (Sheaves et al., 2020) leading to oversimplification. For example, a patient says he hears the voice of God. Although the reference to what he hears seems clear, it is not so clear why he says it is the voice of God, or what about that voice makes him identify it as such. Their distinction in terms of perception-thought is imprecise, making analysis of the patient’s words hard to examine. As discussed further below, it is often not clear if they really hear or see what they say they hear or see, or for example, as one woman said, “They talk and talk, but not like you or me. It’s different.” In this sense, many hallucinatory phenomena, such as orders and comments, can be considered intrusive thoughts (McCarthy-Jones et al., 2014), and the intrusive thoughts of patients with obsessive-compulsive disorder may have audible or visible characteristics (Moritz et al., 2018). Voices have both sound and thought (Woods et al., 2015), and hallucinations may have sensory elements related to thought (Jones and Luhrmann, 2016). For example, one patient we assessed said, “I realize I think those things…, but no, I don’t, it’s the voices that are telling me that, and they are very unpleasant.” This example includes another problem, because what this person at first identified as a thought, he later denies, or confuses with the hallucinations he experiences. Furthermore, around 10% of auditory hallucinations are inaudible (Moritz and Larøi, 2008), and some patients explain their hallucinations as voices heard with the mind more than with their ears (Henriksen et al., 2016).

Differentiations made within each phenomenon are also imprecise. Although some hallucinations may be identified as auditory, tactile, or visual, others are not described, such as “The speaker on TV is talking to me in a special way,” “I don’t know if I saw it or not, but it was there,” “A lot of people are saying bad things about me, that I should kill myself and that, but I don’t understand what they are saying, they don’t say it in words.” This may suggest that such sensory types are culturally molded expressions (Laroi et al., 2014). Delusions, in the phenomenological tradition, are separated into primary, that is unintelligible, or true delusions, and secondary delusions, those understandable as life experiences (like pathological jealousy or most of the persecutory delusions) (World Health Organization [WHO], 2018). Nevertheless, this distinction of secondary delusions as the patient’s effort at interpretation (Maher, 2006) is unnecessary, because of the difficulty in explaining an experience with no clear empirical referent in primary delusions (Cermolacce et al., 2010). For example, “I feel like I’m rotting,” “I feel like I don’t have a soul anymore,” or “I don’t have a body.” And, however, in this same line of research, the importance of the experiential or live nature of the delusion is emphasized (Feyaerts et al., 2021). That problem appears again in differentiating between autistic delusions, considered metaphors of the subjective experience, and therefore, similar to primary delusions, and empirical delusions (Parnas et al., 2010), which have a realistic referent. Other studies have relativized both the distinction between the two phenomena, and within them (Dudley et al., 2018; Maijer et al., 2018).

Continuing the discussion of the problems already mentioned above, a long clinical tradition argues for the hallucination-delusion distinction. Séglas (1982) referred to hallucinations as thoughts audible only to the person himself. Building on the works of Jaspers (1913), hallucinations have been described as objectification of inner speech, spatialization of experience, or perception of consciousness (Sass and Parnas, 2003), as a cognitive phenomenon (Handest et al., 2016) not exclusively perceptive-sensory. This is the case of a patient who said she recognized her husband’s mistress, was completely convinced that she had finally found out who she was, and that she had seen her, and at the same time, mentioned that it was raining at the time and she could not see her face because of the umbrella, and all the while insisted she did not know who the woman was. Another patient was not sure if he knew or saw two policemen in a helicopter, saying they were smiling because they were going to trap him (while he was on a bus). The doubts about what patients hear are found in Bleuler (1960), and in Clérambault (1926) who described mental automatism as beginning without sensory reference. So, the problem in distinguishing between thought and perception may come from analyzing and later elaborating on cognitive phenomena. This again makes perception-thought an oversimplified and imprecise distinction. Alternatively, hallucinations and delusions have been considered on a continuum (Strauss, 2014) between two extremes related to the attenuated sense of self (Rosen et al., 2016), or similar processes (Bentall, 1990), as a single dimension distorting reality (Barch et al., 2013) and extensive to any positive symptom (Moritz et al., 2017). The first objective of this study was therefore to contribute a concept with parameters that can integrate the findings recognized in the literature as hallucinations and delusions, enabling both to be understood as different cases of that single concept.

Nevertheless, some models have emphasized factors that are significant in the disorders discussed here. Some are about the person. Cognitive models have underlined the importance that unfulfilled basic human needs, such as affiliation, security, or care have on altered functioning (Gilbert, 2001; Campbell and Morrison, 2012), development of one’s own schemas (about the self, the world around us, and the future) (Beck et al., 2019), avoidance or escape behaviors, or interpretations of the symptoms themselves (Birchwood et al., 2000; Tully et al., 2017). Family therapy models suggest that deficient communication, coping, and self-control are important to symptoms (Palazzoli et al., 1977; Liotti and Gumley, 2009). Other factors refer to the setting. Finnish intervention in psychosis suggests the importance of conditions favoring recovery, such as care and its immediacy, dialogue, trust, and tolerance to uncertainty by the patient’s support networks (Seikkula et al., 2006; Lakeman, 2014), and lack of family warmth as the best predictor of relapse (Bucci et al., 2016). Other models emphasize factors related to highly stressful situations, such as mourning or abuse (Varese et al., 2012) or chronic stress, social isolation, and social inequality (Read et al., 2013; Bentall et al., 2014). Such factors alter the patient’s emotional state and thoughts about their self-worth (Garety and Freeman, 2013), leading to hallucinations and delusions in response to chronic, highly intense stress (Geekie et al., 2012; Pienkos et al., 2019). Current phenomenological perspectives also consider factors related to personal experience, such as loss of familiarity and continuity in inner experiences linked to identity. This affects loss of automatic cognitive, motor, and emotional processes, involving loss of agency, experience of vitality, integration, and sense of belonging (Henriksen and Parnas, 2017). Loss of continuity or speed of thought favors voicing of thought, personification, or spatialization of inner speech (Parnas and Zandersen, 2018). Given the significance of these factors in hallucinations and delusions, they should be considered in the integrating concept sought. Thus, the second objective of this study was to construct a model that could achieve this.

Moreover, both concept and model had to be delimited precisely and clearly differentiated from each other, assembling the aspects of the phenomena under study and the factors mentioned in the literature discussed above.

Integrating Concept Proposed

This study integrates hallucinations and delusions by classifying them both as attributions people make about their settings and themselves. Then, the elements of any attribution may be used as guides for analyzing significant literature on both, and reduce the current ambiguity.

Attribution is therefore defined here as a person’s interpretation of content or meaning assigned to someone or something, and involves the following elements: Reference, the content or meaning assigned; referral, the person or thing the content of the reference is assigned to, and referent, the agent or generator of the reference. Thus, the reference is the product of the referent with mediation of the referral (see Figure 1). This analysis was developed based on the hypotheses of Wilkinson and Bell (2016) on agency in hallucinations and delusions.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Structure of the components of any attribution.

Each attribution element includes several parameters with different cases or possibilities, as summarized in Table 1. Location is a parameter for both the referent and the referral. The referent may be the person who makes the attribution, as in “I am dead,” but could also be someone else, or something that makes the attribution, as in “God hates me” or “Those antennas are watching me.” The same is true of the referral, as in “They’re watching me” or “They’re watching my father,” respectively, and those others could be located within the person, as in “I have another person moving inside my body.” There are two groups of reference parameters. The first is the content of the attribution and includes two parameters. One is the theme, with possibilities mentioned in the literature: paranoid, passionate, somatic, etc. Another parameter is the purpose identifiable in the content. These could be advice, compliments, and so forth, grouped in three types: Imposition (e.g., “It was when I looked him in the eye that I knew he was going to kill me”), suggestion (e.g., “I was really annoyed because they said I should buy a lottery ticket, but I didn’t want to, because I don’t have any money.”), or neutral (e.g., “I don’t care, I don’t pay any attention to them,” when the voices say they are going to kill him). The second group of parameters, composition, includes structure and modality. Structure may be relational if the attribution consists of some reasoning which connects ideas, and non-relational if it consists of a mere cluster of ideas. Examples of each are, “They want to kill me because I am a spy” and “I am a spy, the Pope, and I like to eat with my fingers.” In modality, the possibilities consist of expressing the attribution reference as a thought or as sensory perception, as in delusions and hallucinations, respectively, or a combination of the two, as well as the ambiguity mentioned in the literature. An example of the combination of attributions, with or without sensory reference, would be one of the more common clinical expressions. For instance, a patient who says he has been worried for a long time because he has stopped helping his father in his bar, and that his father had gotten so angry that he was harassing him (which is not what his family says); that he started to hear the neighbors criticizing him, and later, how he clearly sees how he is shot in the head, from which he deduces that Basque terrorists are behind all his father’s insistence.

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Parameters of the elements of attributions.

Two last groups of parameters refer to the attribution as a whole. One is the oral, written, and body language used to express it. The other is the quality of its meaning and expression. Its parameters include the criteria of scientific validity (Martínez and Moreno, 2014). The first is precision or clarity. Some attributions are imprecise in meaning, but precise in how they are expressed, usually known as formal alterations of thought, but with understandable words and syntax, such as “Turning backward first is intelligent and keeps another crazy person with criminal instincts from eating”; “How is it my fault that I have six senses and I was born with a heart and you were not? The drunkard understands me, I am crazy, I am the Supreme Judge, I, Honoris Rex.” However, attributions that could be called a “word salad” would be imprecise in both their meaning and how they are expressed. The second quality parameter is differentiation, what makes each attribution different from others, as one patient says: “I really thought I was going to get married when the bells rang, I thought it was like a prize for me (I was in a public square and I heard church bells),” and then she thought they were recording all her telephone conversations. On the contrary, the following example shows overlapping or repeating, and therefore, lack of differentiation, “Then they’re coming to see me?. (…), Are they coming to see me?” And later, “Tomorrow they’re coming to see me?” This does not refer to expressions that include formal alterations, such as perseveration or palilalia. The third parameter of quality is fit or how well each attribution corresponds to the external criteria that evaluate it, its different parts, their sequence, and the expression as a whole. For example: “I felt really terrible because a man driving a car insulted me with the letters BCH” (which for her meant bitch), where formal linguistic expression is not the problem, but the attribution of the illogical meaning is based on external parameters. Thus, failure to fit is sometimes due to lack of or insufficient meaning, as in alogia and in expression with telegraphic-type speech, such as “Sick help, …call father,” understandable only in certain conversations. Other failures are from excessive meaning, as in derailing and logorrhea. Other attributions fail to fit due to absence or excess, such as those that are tangential and can be qualified as incoherent or illogical.

Attribution Framework Factors

The usefulness of attributions increases when their two-way relationships with factors that influence them or are modified by them are considered. That combination of attributions and their framework factors is described here as a field model. This type of model, suggested in various branches of physics, health (Laframboise, 1973; Lalonde, 1974), and psychology (Lewin, 1936; Kantor and Smith, 1975; Ribes, 2018) interprets its subject matter as an inseparable structure of variables and relationships that make mutual sense. The model proposed here is the result of reiterative fitting to a large sample of literature, only partly referenced due to space limitations.

The many possible framework factors of an attribution are grouped below (Table 2) by person and setting.

TABLE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Attribution framework factors.

By person, emotions or feelings, behaviors or activities, and thoughts or ideas are included, either as such, or indirectly and implicitly in variables such as age, gender, or education. Another significant factor is personal needs, or a mere threat to them: physiological, such as breathing, eating, or drinking, and avoiding pain, and so forth; or psychological, such as security, affiliation, recognition, and self-realization, as described by Maslow (1943) and adapted by Self-Determination Theory (Deci and Ryan, 2000) or by Liotti and Gilbert (2011). Other also numerous factors in the setting may be classified as family, work, leisure, and other areas, which could also include the therapist, when applicable.

Effects of Attributions on the Framework Factors

These relationships refer to changes in the framework factors by attributions. They may be personal, such as changes in emotions, behaviors, thoughts, or needs. The resulting emotions may be grouped by their valence as pleasant, such as joy, pride, or wellbeing (e.g., “I didn’t want to take the pills because then I wouldn’t hear the voice of Jesus Christ telling me things that I liked to hear”), or unpleasant, such as sadness, anxiety, anger, disgust, perplexity, shame, or guilt, although both could be present (e.g., “I hate my father, but I love him so much,”), and an indefinite valence is also possible. The estimated intensity of the emotion identified is also important.

Resulting behaviors could even be the absence of any at all, such as in freeze, catatonic inhibition, and classic conversion paralysis (e.g., “I stopped moving because they made my brain feel like wood. They were playing with me. And they have no right!”). Others are attempts to neutralize or reduce the attribution or its influence (e.g., “I couldn’t say anything, because then I would really have gone crazy. I didn’t dare think about anything,”) such as flight and fight behavior (Corr, 2013), or self-harm or playing very loud music as incompatible elements. A third type tries to maintain or increase the attribution (e.g., “At first, I was scared to death, but then I liked to listen to them, because they said, ‘You’re such a good person,’ or ‘you are looking great today!”’). All the behaviors could be either intentional or involuntary, and even include sleeping, eating, anesthesia or hypersensitivity without any organic origin, and sexual appetite. Behaviors should also be considered as help-seeking or autonomous.

The resulting cognitions are ways individuals have of understanding their own attributions, or even their absence. They are self-judgments, not made by an outside analyst like the rest of the model’s components. There are two groups: Characterization of the attributions and their quality (see Table 3). Characterization includes: Origin assigned, in which the attributions may be understood on their own or imposed by someone or something (e.g., “Understood, I’ll shut up,” and the patient clarifies afterward that when the psychologist cleared his throat during the conversation it was an order to keep quiet immediately); privacy of the attributions, whether only known to the one who makes them (e.g., “He’s the one (Jesus Christ) who only says things to me”), or by someone else, as in diffusion or thought theft; controllability, or the possibility of the attribution somehow being interfered with, thoughts being inserted in their absence (e.g., “It’s the only way,” making a strange repetitive sound, “It’s how they stop bothering me,” referring to the voices); and the sense they make of attributions as beneficial, harmful, or neutral (e.g., “Some bricklayers started to work across the way, and then I knew that everything was wrong and I had to throw everything out the window”). The quality or validity they grant their own attributions is considered with the same criteria as the precision, differentiation, and fit applicable by the analysist and summarized in Table 1, but modified to emphasize that they are the individual’s own opinion. Clarity granted the meaning of the attribution itself, whether sharp or ambiguous (e.g., “I say it is something like, as if they grabbed you from behind and held you back, but I’m not sure if it’s that or what”); distinction from other attributions they have is whether they are distinct or overlap with others; and credibility of the attributions themselves, which could be convincing or question whether they are true, whether by outside inference or without it as in saying, “I am the son of the Count of Peñaflor… What a dumb thing I just said!” Personal needs resulting from the attributions, satisfying or reducing, maintaining or increasing them, are all possible. Changes in setting factors, such as the person being treated differently in the family or work environment after the delusions or hallucinations, are also possible.

TABLE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Table 3. Effects of the framework factors.

Influence of the Framework Factors on Attributions

These relationships are changes in the parameters of the attributions as a result of changes in the person’s framework factors or setting. Some influence attributions of needs not met, such as insecurity favoring paranoid themes, lack of recognition favoring manic themes, affiliation favoring passionate themes, need for security, somatic themes or self-realization and affiliation, and depression (Gilbert et al., 2007; Carvalho et al., 2013). An example of the influence of the setting would be invalidating environments (Lungu and Linehan, 2017).

Relationships Between Framework Factors

In the relationships discussed above, attributions affect framework factors and these in turn influence the attributions, as shown in Figure 2, with heavy and fine continuous lines, respectively. In addition, the relationships of the framework factors should be considered, whether personal, in the setting, or of one type with the other. When the attributions are not included, they are considered of secondary importance and are shown in Figure 2 as dashed lines.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Attributions and their framework factors.

Diachronic Perspective

The synchronic or current perspective of the relationships described above is matched with a diachronic or longitudinal perspective. This adds additional information. The unit of analysis is expanded from an attribution to a set or episode of attributions, or even a series of episodes, with a conventionally identified beginning and end. New parameters of the attributions and framework factors now make sense, mainly: Frequency of attributions over a certain time and intervals between two in a row, in addition to trends, such as changes or stability of these parameters over time. The series of reciprocal relationships formed by successive influences and effects of framework factors on the attributions also enter the analysis. This happens, for example, when the work-climate framework favors an attribution, which then leads to changes in the person’s behavior and interaction with the family. This is represented in Figure 2 by the order of these relationships.

Checklist for Model Application to Clinical Practice

In addition to conceptualizing hallucinations and delusions, the model can describe an individual with synchronic and diachronic analyses of the variables and relationships, which assists in the assessment, follow-up, and intervention in clinical practice, testing the ecological validity, and therefore, the usefulness of our proposal. Two checklists are provided below as a guide, the first for a cross-sectional description (see Table 4), which is filled in following the parameters and cases summarized in Tables 1–3, 5.

TABLE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Table 4. Checklist of the synchronic perspective of an attribution.

TABLE 5
www.frontiersin.org

Table 5. Influences of framework factors on attributions.

By applying the checklist above to the successive fields analyzed in an episode or series of attributions, sets can be described. A second checklist for this is given below (Table 6).

TABLE 6
www.frontiersin.org

Table 6. Checklist for a diachronic perspective of the attributional field.

Discussion and Conclusions

The objective of this study was to integrate hallucinations and delusions as particular cases of attributions, differentiated by whether or not sensory perception is involved only when it is of interest and their expression allows it. The model proposed synchronically and diachronically delimits the parameters of any attribution, which makes sense in relation to the person’s framework factors and settings, enabling significant studies in the literature to be outlined.

In this approach, the meanings of the attributions that hallucinations and delusions correspond to, or the way they are expressed, are low-quality, because they are not precise enough, are not differentiated enough from each other, nor do they fit to evaluative criteria, and frequently occur in one or more episodes or series of episodes, with short intervals between them. The fewer of those characteristics present in the attributions, the more likely they are to be merely errors in interpretation. Therefore, those characteristics enable attribution quality to be graded, from the most common, which could be considered subthreshold, to those involving the clinical problems dealt with here.

The rest of the parameters and relationships discussed form the qualitative type of any attribution. They may be classified by the location of referents and referral, theme and structure of the references, language, origin, privacy, controllability, and the sense they make to the person, as well as by their effects and influences on the framework factors by specifying those involved in each relationship. This can reveal the formation and development of the attributions, identifying more framework factors for clinical attributions and those that modify these framework factors the most. Thus, due to their mutual relationships with personal and setting factors found in the literature, attributions would be accompanied by emotions of a certain intensity, changes in behavior, and characterizations and credibility granted by the person.

The various components of the concept of attribution and framework factors are explained precisely and are sufficiently differentiated to be understood and used in clinical practice for assessment and follow-up, and more indirectly, for intervention in these important manifestations, with the checklists provided here. We also think that this concept of attribution and of the framework factor structures is faithful to the most relevant literature on hallucinations and delusions.

These qualities should be tested by clinicians using the checklists to detect insufficient precision and thoroughness of the attribution components and framework factors included. It would not be surprising that limitations would then appear that would have to be corrected in the model’s design. We are aware that the number of components could make it hard to use in clinical practice. However, that large number is necessary to reflect as much of the extensive literature as possible.

In brief, the structure provided by the model proposed organizes the field of low-quality attributions at the same time it enables them to be differentiated from others involving less impairment. This suggests a gradation from phenomena that are not necessarily pathological, such as self-references, overvalued ideas, or depersonalization (Reininghaus et al., 2016; Baumeister et al., 2017; Bell and O’Driscoll, 2018), not discussed here for reasons of space. This gradation would enable validation of the study of low-quality attributions under the conceptual umbrella of the extended psychotic phenotype (Van Os and Reininghaus, 2016). It would also help adjust the relationship between the different phenomena under study in determining the onset and maintenance of the psychotic process.

Author Contributions

JR-T and RM were fully involved at all stages in the writing of the manuscript. CS-C managed the literature searches. All authors contributed to and have approved the final manuscript.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s Note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

American Psychiatric Association [APA]. (2013). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM 5). Arlington, VA: APA.

Google Scholar

Barch, D. M., Bustillo, J., Gaebel, W., Gur, R., Heckers, S., Malaspina, D., et al. (2013). Logic and justification for dimensional assessment of symptoms and related clinical phenomena in psychosis: relevance to DSM-5. Schizophr. Res. 150, 15–20. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2013.04.027

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baumeister, D., Sedgwick, O., Howes, O., and Peters, E. (2017). Auditory verbal hallucinations and continuum models of psychosis: a systematic review of the healthy voice-hearer literature. Clin. Psychol. Rev. 51, 125–141. doi: 10.1016/j.cpr.2016.10.010

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Beck, A. T., Himelstein, R., and Grant, P. M. (2019). In and out of schizophrenia: activation and deactivation of the negative and positive schemas. Schizophr. Res. 203, 55–61. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2017.10.046

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bell, V., and O’Driscoll, C. (2018). The network structure of paranoia in the general population. Soc. Psychiatry Psychiatr. Epidemiol 53, 737–744. doi: 10.1007/s00127-018-1487-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bentall, R. P. (1990). The Illusion of Reality: a Review and Integration of Psychological Research on Hallucinations. Psychol. Bull. 107, 82–95. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.107.1.82

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bentall, R. P., De Sousa, P., Varese, F., Wickham, S., Sitko, K., Haarmans, M., et al. (2014). From adversity to psychosis: pathways and mechanisms from specific adversities to specific symptoms. Soc. Psychiatry Psychiatr. Epidemiol. 49, 1011–1022. doi: 10.1007/s00127-014-0914-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Birchwood, M., Meaden, A., Trower, P., Gilbert, P., and Plaistow, J. (2000). The power and omnipotence of voices: subordination and entrapment by voices and significant others. Psychol. Med. 30, 337–344. doi: 10.1017/S0033291799001828

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bleuler, E. (1960). Demencia Precoz. EL grupo de las esquizofrenias [Dementia praecox. The group of schizophrenias]. Buenos Aires: Paidós.

Google Scholar

Bucci, S., Berry, K., Barrowclough, C., and Haddock, G. (2016). Family Interventions in Psychosis: a Review of the Evidence and Barriers to Implementation. Aust. Psychol. 51, 62–68. doi: 10.1111/ap.12172

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Campbell, M. L. C., and Morrison, A. P. (2012). “Subjective experiences of delusion and paranoia,” in Experiencing Psychosis: Personal and Professional Perspectives, eds J. Geekie, D. Randal, D. Lampshire, and J. Read (East Sussex: Routledge).

Google Scholar

Carvalho, S., Pinto-Gouveia, J., Pimentel, P., Maia, D., Gilbert, P., and Mota-Pereira, J. (2013). Entrapment and Defeat Perceptions in Depressive Symptomatology: through an Evolutionary Approach. Psychiatry 76, 53–67. doi: 10.1521/psyc.2013.76.1.53

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cermolacce, M., Sass, L., and Parnas, J. (2010). What is bizarre in bizarre delusions? A critical review. Schizophr. Bull. 36, 667–679. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbq001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clérambault, G. G. (1926). El Automatismo Mental [Mental Automatism]. Madrid: Dor.

Google Scholar

Corr, P. J. (2013). Approach and avoidance behaviour: multiple systems and their interactions. Emot. Rev. 5, 285–290. doi: 10.1177/1754073913477507

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Deci, E. L., and Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and “why” of goal pursuits: human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychol. Inq. 11, 227–268. doi: 10.1207/S15327965PLI1104_01

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dudley, R., Aynsworth, C., Cheetham, R., McCarthy-Jones, S., and Collerton, D. (2018). Prevalence and characteristics of multi-modal hallucinations in people with psychosis who experience visual hallucinations. Psychiatry Res. 269, 25–30. doi: 10.1016/j.psychres.2018.08.032

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Feyaerts, J., Henriksen, M. G., Vanheule, S., Myin-Germeys, I., and Sass, L. A. (2021). Delusions beyond beliefs: a critical overview of diagnostic, aetiological, and therapeutic schizophrenia research from a clinical-phenomenological perspective. Lancet Psychiatry 8, 237–249.

Google Scholar

Garety, P. A., and Freeman, D. (2013). The past and future of delusions research: from the inexplicable to the treatable. Br. J. Psychiatry J. Ment. Sci. 203, 327–333. doi: 10.1192/bjp.bp.113.126953

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Garety, P. A., Ward, T., and Rus-Calafell, M. (2020). “Beyond Belief—New Approaches to the Treatment of Paranoia,” in A Clinical Introduction to Psychosis, eds C. J. Badcock and G. Paulik (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Academic Press), 591–613. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-12-815012-2.00025-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Geekie, J., Randal, P., Lampshire, D., and Read, J. (2012). Experiencing Psychosis: Personal and Professional Perspectives. East Sussex, England: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Gilbert, P. (2001). Evolutionary approaches to psychopathology: the role of natural defences. Aust. N. Z. J. Psychiatry 35, 17–27. doi: 10.1046/j.1440-1614.2001.00856.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gilbert, P., McEwan, K., Hay, J., Irons, C., and Cheung, M. (2007). Social rank and attachment in people with a bipolar disorder. Clin. Psychol. Psychother. 14, 48–53. doi: 10.1002/cpp.508

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Handest, P., Klimpke, C., Raballo, A., and Larøi, F. (2016). From Thoughts to Voices: understanding the Development of Auditory Hallucinations in Schizophrenia. Rev. Philos. Psychol. 7, 595–610. doi: 10.1007/s13164-015-0286-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G., and Parnas, J. (2017). Clinical Manifestations of Self-disorders in Schizophrenia Spectrum Conditions. Curr. Probl. Psychiatry 18, 177–183. doi: 10.1515/cpp-2017-0014

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G., Raballo, A., and Parnas, J. (2016). The Pathogenesis of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations in Schizophrenia: a Clinical–Phenomenological Account. Philos. Psychiatry Psychol. 22, 165–181. doi: 10.1353/ppp.2015.0041

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jaspers, K. (1913). Psicopatología general [General Psychopathology]. Buenos Aires: Editorial Beta.

Google Scholar

Jones, N., and Luhrmann, T. M. (2016). Beyond the sensory: findings from an in-depth analysis of the phenomenology of “auditory hallucinations” in schizophrenia. Psychosis 8, 191–202. doi: 10.1080/17522439.2015.1100670

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kantor, J., and Smith, N. W. (1975). The science of psychology: An interbehavioral survey. Chicago, ILL: Principia Press.

Google Scholar

Laframboise, H. L. (1973). Health policy?: breaking the problem down into more manageable segments. Can. Med. Assoc. J. 108, 388–393.

Google Scholar

Lakeman, R. (2014). The Finnish open dialogue approach to crisis intervention in psychosis: a review. Psychother. Aust. 20, 28–35.

Google Scholar

Lalonde, M. (1974). A New Perspective on the Health of Canadians. Ottawa, Ontario, Canada: Information Canada.

Google Scholar

Laroi, F., Luhrmann, T. M., Bell, V., Christian, W. A., Deshpande, S., Fernyhough, C., et al. (2014). Culture and hallucinations: overview and future directions. Schizophr. Bull. 40, 213–220. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbu012

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lewin, K. (1936). Principles of topological psychology. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Google Scholar

Liotti, G., and Gilbert, P. (2011). Mentalizing, motivation, and social mentalities: theoretical considerations and implications for psychotherapy. Psychol. Psychother. Theory Res. Pract. 84, 9–25. doi: 10.1348/147608310X520094

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Liotti, G., and Gumley, A. (2009). “An Attachment Perspective on Schizophrenia: The Role of Disorganized Attachment, Dissociation and Mentalization,” in Psychosis, Trauma and Dissociation: Emerging Perspectives on Severe Psychopathology, eds A. Moskowitz, I. Schäfer, and M. J. Dorahy (Chichester: John Wiley & Sons), 117–131. doi: 10.1002/9780470699652.ch9

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lungu, A., and Linehan, M. M. (2017). “Dialectical behavior therapy: Overview, characteristics, and future directions,” in The Science of Cognitive Behavioral Therapy, eds S. Hofmann and G. Asmundson (New York: Academic Press), 429–459. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-12-803457-6.00018-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maher, B. A. (2006). The relationship between delusions and hallucinations. Curr. Psychiatry Rep. 8, 179–183. doi: 10.1007/s11920-006-0021-3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maijer, K., Begemann, M. J. H., Palmen, S. J. M. C., Leucht, S., and Sommer, I. E. C. (2018). Auditory hallucinations across the lifespan: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Psychol. Med. 48, 879–888. doi: 10.1017/s0033291717002367

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Martínez, R., and Moreno, R. (2014). Cómo Plantear Y Responder Preguntas De Manera Científica [How To Raise And Answer Questions Scientifically]. Madrid: Síntesis.

Google Scholar

Maslow, A. H. (1943). A Theory of Human Motivation. Psychol. Rev. 50, 370–396.

Google Scholar

McCarthy-Jones, S., Trauer, T., MacKinnon, A., Sims, E., Thomas, N., and Copolov, D. L. (2014). A new phenomenological survey of auditory hallucinations: evidence for subtypes and implications for theory and practice. Schizophr. Bull. 40, 225–235. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbs156

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Moritz, S., and Larøi, F. (2008). Differences and similarities in the sensory and cognitive signatures of voice-hearing, intrusions and thoughts. Schizophr. Res. 102, 96–107. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2008.04.007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Moritz, S., Pfuhl, G., Lüdtke, T., Menon, M., Balzan, R. P., and Andreou, C. (2017). A two-stage cognitive theory of the positive symptoms of psychosis. Highlighting the role of lowered decision thresholds. J. Behav. Ther. Exp. Psychiatry 56, 12–20. doi: 10.1016/j.jbtep.2016.07.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Moritz, S., Purdon, C., Jelinek, L., Chiang, B., and Hauschildt, M. (2018). If it is absurd, then why do you do it? The richer the obsessional experience, the more compelling the compulsion. Clin. Psychol. Psychother. 25, 210–216. doi: 10.1002/cpp.2155

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Palazzoli, M. S., Boscolo, L., Cecchin, G. F., and Prata, G. (1977). Family Rituals A Powerful Tool in Family Therapy. Fam. Process 16, 445–453. doi: 10.1111/j.1545-5300.1977.00445.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., Nordgaard, J., and Vargas, S. (2010). The concept of psychosis: a clinical and theoretical analysis. Clin. Neuropsychiatry 7, 32–37.

Google Scholar

Parnas, J., and Zandersen, M. (2018). Self and schizophrenia: current status and diagnostic implications. World Psychiatry 17, 221–222. doi: 10.1002/wps.20528

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pienkos, E., Giersch, A., Hansen, M., Humpston, C., McCarthy-Jones, S., Mishara, A., et al. (2019). Hallucinations Beyond Voices: a Conceptual Review of the Phenomenology of Altered Perception in Psychosis. Schizophr. Bull. 45, S67–S77. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sby057

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Read, J., Johnstone, L., and Taitimu, M. (2013). “Models of Madness,” in Psychological, Social and Biological Approaches to Psychosis, eds J. Read and J. Dillon (Sussex: Routledge), 191–209.

Google Scholar

Reininghaus, U., Kempton, M. J., Valmaggia, L., Craig, T. K. J., Garety, P., Onyejiaka, A., et al. (2016). Stress sensitivity, aberrant salience, and threat anticipation in early psychosis: an experience sampling study. Schizophr. Bull. 42, 712–722. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbv190

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ribes, E. (2018). ). El estudio científico de la conducta individual: Una introducción a la Teoría de la Psicología. [The scientific study of individual behavior: An introduction to the Theory of Psychology]. México: Manual moderno.

Google Scholar

Rosen, C., Chase, K. A., Jones, N., Grossman, L. S., Gin, H., and Sharma, R. P. (2016). Listening to Schneiderian Voices: a Novel Phenomenological Analysis. Psychopathology 49, 163–171. doi: 10.1159/000446546

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sass, L. A., and Parnas, J. (2003). Schizophrenia. Consciousness and the Self. Schizophr. Bull. 29, 427–444. doi: 10.1093/oxfordjournals.schbul.a007017

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Séglas, J. (1982). “Las alucinaciones verbales en clínica mental [Verbal hallucinations in mental clinic],” in Delusion in the French Clinic, eds F. Colina and J. M. Álvarez (Madrid: Dor), 167–193.

Google Scholar

Seikkula, J., Aaltonen, J., Alakare, B., Haarakangas, K., Keränen, J., and Lehtinen, K. (2006). Five-year experience of first-episode nonaffective psychosis in open-dialogue approach: treatment principles, follow-up outcomes, and two case studies. Psychother. Res. 16, 214–228. doi: 10.1080/10503300500268490

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sheaves, B., Johns, L., Griffith, L., Isham, L., The McPin Hearing Voices Lived Experience Advisory Panel, Kabir, T., et al. (2020). Why do patients with psychosis listen to and believe derogatory and threatening voices? 21 reasons given by patients. Behav. Cogn. Psychother. 48, 631–645. doi: 10.1017/S1352465820000429

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Strauss, J. (2014). Reconceptualizing schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 40, 97–100. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbt156

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tully, S., Wells, A., Pyle, M., Hudson, J., Gumley, A., Kingdon, D., et al. (2017). Measuring common responses to psychosis: assessing the psychometric properties of a new measure. Schizophr. Res. 181, 131–136. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2016.10.015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Van Os, J., and Reininghaus, U. (2016). Psychosis as a transdiagnostic and extended phenotype in the general population. World Psychiatry 15, 118–124. doi: 10.1002/wps.20310

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Varese, F., Morrison, A. P., Beck, R., Heffernan, S., Law, H., and Bentall, R. P. (2016). Experiential avoidance and appraisals of voices as predictors of voice-related distress. Br. J. Clin. Psychol. 55, 320–331. doi: 10.1111/bjc.12102

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Varese, F., Smeets, F., Drukker, M., Lieverse, R., Lataster, T., Viechtbauer, W., et al. (2012). Childhood adversities increase the risk of psychosis: a meta-analysis of patient-control, prospective-and cross-sectional cohort studies. Schizophr. Bull. 38, 661–671. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbs050

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilkinson, S., and Bell, V. (2016). The Representation of Agents in Auditory Verbal Hallucinations. Mind Lang. 31, 104–126. doi: 10.1111/mila.12096

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Woods, A., Jones, N., Alderson-Day, B., Callard, F., and Fernyhough, C. (2015). Experiences of hearing voices: analysis of a novel phenomenological survey. Lancet Psychiatry 2, 323–331. doi: 10.1016/S2215-0366(15)00006-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

World Health Organization [WHO]. (2018). Schizophrenia or other primary psychotic disorders. Available Online at: https://icd.who.int/browse11/l-m/en#/http%3A%2F%2Fid.who.int%2Ficd%2Fentity%2F405565289 (accessed March 4, 2020).

Google Scholar

Keywords: delusions, hallucinations, attributions, field model, psychosis

Citation: Rodríguez-Testal JF, Senín-Calderón C and Moreno R (2021) Hallucinations and Delusions as Low-Quality Attributions: Influencing Factors and Proposal for Their Analysis. Front. Psychol. 12:533795. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2021.533795

Received: 03 April 2020; Accepted: 02 July 2021;
Published: 23 July 2021.

Edited by:

Sarah Bendall, University of Melbourne, Australia

Reviewed by:

Clara S. Humpston, University of Birmingham, United Kingdom
Mary V. Seeman, University of Toronto, Canada

Copyright © 2021 Rodríguez-Testal, Senín-Calderón and Moreno. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Juan F. Rodríguez-Testal, testal@us.es

ORCID: Juan F. Rodríguez-Testal, orcid.org/0000-0002-7346-5656; Cristina Senín-Calderón, orcid.org/0000-0002-7604-8487

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.