Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 04 February 2020
Sec. Cognition

Enactive Memory

  • EPSYLON Laboratory (EA 4556), University Paul Valéry, Montpellier, France

Since its birth in 1953, cognitive psychology has been dominated by a conception of cognition as computations of mental representations of the world (see Fodor, 1983). But in the last three decades a radical change has occurred: cognition is now viewed as emerging from cognitive processes closely intertwined with actions performed in a specific environment (Varela et al., 1991).

The first consequence of this view is that the ultimate aim of cognitive processes is not to recover representations or to construct new representations of a pre-existent world, but rather to create the world in which people act. According to this view the perceived world is a construction linked to the mutual dependence between a cognitive agent and the world in which s/he evolves; that is to say, the world is enacted by one's actions. The second consequence is that for the enactive approach, perception, action, and cognition are in substance intrinsically linked. Indeed, it emphasizes the interdependence of two points: (a) perception consists of perceptually guided action; and (b) cognitive structures emerge from recurrent sensorimotor patterns that guide the action perceptually (Varela et al., 1991, p. 173).

The idea that perception, action, and cognition are intrinsically linked was already supported by the ecological theory of perception (Gibson, 1979), for which action is performed through the exploratory activity of vision. The sensorimotor approach to perception (for a review, O'Regan, 2011) establishes the same link between perception, action, and cognition. The action is essential for perceiving invariants, updating it through what are called sensorimotor contingencies.

If the idea that our perceptions are enacted is relatively easy to conceive, it is otherwise with memory. Indeed, considering that our memories may be enacted is to say that they are the product of the actions we take to account for them in a given situation. In other words, this means accepting that our memories are no longer considered as the recovery, sensu stricto, of an event that happened in the past, but rather as the product of a cognitive elaboration constructed here and now. To paraphrase Neisser (1996), memories are a kind of reflection of the dynamics of cognition; they emerge from this dynamic. So, memories are not static; based on the synergy between previous experiences and present experience, they are continuously revised. Adopting this point of view would be tantamount to breaking with the conception of memory that is widely shared and defended by classical models of memory (from the Atkinson and Shiffrin's model, 1968, up until the SPI model, Tulving, 1995).

Nevertheless, alternative models of memory, proposed since 1980s, appear to be compatible with an enactive approach to memory. These models, called single memory models, postulate that the experiences of our interactions with the environment are stored in a multi-sensory way and distributed across the entire brain (Hintzman, 1986; Whittlesea, 1987; Versace et al., 2014). Here, memory traces reflect the processing episode and retrieval is the result of a coupling between the recovery situation and a set of episodic traces activated on the basis of their similarity to the characteristics of the recovery episode (see, the synergistic ecphory process modeled in MINERVA, Hintzman, 1986). The consequence, the memories are not recovered; they emerge in the present situation.

By including an integration process, considered as a dynamic mechanism, the Act-In model (Versace et al., 2014) has enhanced the MINERVA model. In Act-In, activations occur continuously in parallel with the computation of similarities; and while the integration mechanism is running, traces are modified both in a proactive manner (the content of a trace depends on the content of previous traces that are activated), and in a retroactive manner (the content of a trace modifies the content of previous traces). Therefore, storage and recovery cannot be considered separately. Moreover, since the integration mechanism is dynamic and non-linear, this means that memories are not simply the sum of the components that make up the activated traces; they are a new entity in its own right, which contains more information than the sum of its components.

More recently, the ATHENA model (Briglia et al., 2018), referring to the enactivist idea that the experience of seeing occurs when an organism perceives sensorimotor regularities or sensorimotor contingencies, proposes that what is learned are the covariances between the present sensorimotor information processing and past sensorimotor information processing. Consequently, in ATHENA, memory does not remember recoverable contents but reusable processes (Brouillet and Versace, 2019). So, the ATHENA model shares the radical enactive account of memory that assumes that remembering is not access to or retrieval of contents (Hutto and Peeters, 2018).

In addition to these models suggesting that an enactive approach of memory is a viable option, there are some experimental studies that support the role of action in the recovery of memories1.

Using a categorization task, Camus et al. (2018) showed that the action performed in a categorization task affected the results, and that the effect depended on the type of action performed. In addition to demonstrating a classic motor compatibility effect, the results showed that the amplitude of this effect depended on the relationship between stimulus and response acquired during the acquisition phase. This result is particularly interesting for our purpose because it confirms, on the one hand, that there is a memory of the consequences of our actions (see also Brouillet et al., 2015); and on the other, that the action one takes here and now to provide an answer has an effect on memory performance.

Brouillet et al. (2016) investigated whether the action performed at the recovery stage, could affect memory performance. The results showed an effect of motor compatibility. The memory judgment was based on the motor compatibility between on the one hand the actual gesture performed to respond, and on the other, the potential gesture initiated by the visual stimulus. Thus, the resonance of the actual gesture performed to respond with the potential gesture related to the stimulus, or more precisely their directional compatibility, influenced memory performance.

Brouillet et al. (2017) went on to test the idea that it might be the motor resonance itself that was behind their results, independent of any link that might exist between the action to be performed and the item to be recognized. For this, they used the well know effect of laterality (i.e., easiness performing a movement in ipsilateral space than contralateral space). The results showed an effect of motor resonance that was heightened in the right index finger condition (all the participants were right-handed). Thus, when the action to type the two stimuli that appeared before the word to be recognized, required a movement toward the space corresponding to their ipsilateral space, the participants had a recognition score higher than their contralateral space. This effect was observed for both old and new words. The authors concluded that it was subjective perception of the motor resonance (so-called motor fluency) linked to the action and the space of its realization that was the cause of the results observed.

If the action carried out by a limb enact memory, several studies showed that another part of our body that makes movements, without our being aware of it, the eyes, also enact memory.

The study by Kosslyn (1994), showed that eye movements are motor information that can be used to remember images. Christman et al. (2003) showed that performance on a recognition test was dependent on the eye movements made just before the task. Participants were better able to discriminate between old and new words after horizontal eye movements than after vertical eye movements or no eye movement. In a subsequent study, the authors observed that for memory of autobiographical events, horizontal eye movements almost doubled participants' discrimination abilities by increasing the rate of correct recognitions and decreasing the rate of false hits. Brunyé et al. (2009) found similar results using shapes and spatial positions in a recognition task. In addition, the authors showed that this effect was observed only where the movements occurred before the recovery phase and not before the learning phase. Moreover, the effect was amplified when the participants were right-handed. Demichelis et al. (2013) investigated whether, when attempting to restore walking a path learned on a map from our memory, we remember it by simulating the ocular exploration that we originally used to learn it. In one hand the results showed that horizontal movements being more efficient than vertical ones, in other hand, they suggest that the participants had mentally repeated their previous ocular exploration of the map, and that it is this oculomotor memory that was used to perform the locomotor memory task.

In our view, all these findings constitute a strong argument in favor of enacted memory. Indeed, they share with what is the core of enactivism (see, Di Paolo et al., 2010, p. 36–44): the sensorimotor couplings, the role of body and agent, the generation of cognition through action, the emerging character of knowledge, the importance experience (past and present).

But this is not without consequences firstly for our way of conceiving both memory and cognition, secondly for our approach to aging and handicap generally. On the one hand, memory is not a library of memories, even if they are episodic; on the other, memory is not the memory of information that enters the system, but the memory of our actions. However, this does not mean the memory of our actions, strictly speaking, but rather the traces of what has been enacted by our actions. That is to say, the enacted process itself, its phenomenological consequences and its product. Finally, the enactive approach had led questioning the conception of aging considered as only a decline of cognitive functions. Less efficient sensory and motor skills can explain several effects linked to aging, in particular those on memory (Vallet, 2015; Costello and Bloesch, 2017). Moreover, consideration of body specificity can affect clinical evaluation. For example, Turo et al. (2019) showed that spatial working memory (Corsi task) is sensible to manuospatial compatibility (i.e., compatibility between the hand used to the practioner to point the blocs and the dominant hand of the patient).

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Footnotes

1. ^This is the role of action; that is, how memories are dependent on action and not the memory of actions, which is very well-documented (see Zimmer et al., 2001).

References

Atkinson, R. C., and Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). “Human memory: A proposed system and its control processes,” in The Psychology of Learning and Motivation: Advances in Research and Theory, Vol. 2, eds K. W. Spence, and J. T. Spence (New York, NY: Academic Press, 89–195.

Google Scholar

Briglia, J., Servajean, P., Michalland, A. H., Brunel, L., and Brouillet, D. (2018). Modeling an enactivist multiple-trace memory. ATHENA: a fractal model of human memory. J. Math. Psychol. 82, 97–110. doi: 10.1016/j.jmp.2017.12.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brouillet, D., Brouillet, T., Milhau, A., Heurley, L., Vagnot, C., and Brunel, L. (2016). Word-to-picture recognition is a function of motor components mappings at the stage of retrieval. Int. J. Psychol. 51, 397–402. doi: 10.1002/ijop.12210

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brouillet, D., Milhau, A., Brouillet, T., and Servajean, P. (2017). Effect of an unrelated fluent action on word recognition: a case of motor discrepancy. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 24, 894–900. doi: 10.3758/s13423-016-1160-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brouillet, D., Vagnot, C., Milhau, A., Brunel, L., Versace, R., and Rousset, S. (2015). Sensory-motor properties of past actions bias memory in a recognition task. Psychol. Res. 79, 678–686. doi: 10.1007/s00426-014-0600-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brouillet, D., and Versace, R. (2019). The nature of the traces and the dynamics of memory. Psychol. Behav. Sci. 8, 151–157. doi: 10.11648/j.pbs.20190806.12

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brunyé, T. T., Mahoney, C. R., Augustyn, J. S., and Taylor, H. A. (2009). Horizontal saccadic eye movements enhance the retrieval of landmark shape and location information. Brain Cogn. 70, 279–288. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2009.03.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Camus, T., Hommel, B., Brunel, L., and Brouillet, T. (2018). From anticipation to integration: the role of integrated action-effects in building sensorimotor contingencies. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 25, 1059–1065. doi: 10.3758/s13423-017-1308-6

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Christman, S. D., Garvey, K. J., Propper, R. E., and Phaneuf, K. A. (2003). Bilateral eye movements enhance the retrieval of episodic memories. Neuropsychology 17, 221. doi: 10.1037/0894-4105.17.2.221

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Costello, M. C., and Bloesch, E. K. (2017). Are older adults less embodied? A review of age effects through the lens of embodied cognition. Front. Psychol. 8:267. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00267

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Demichelis, A., Olivier, G., and Berthoz, A. (2013). Motor transfer from map ocular exploration to locomotion during spatial navigation from memory. Exp. Brain Res. 224, 605–611. doi: 10.1007/s00221-012-3336-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Di Paolo, E., Rohde, M., and De Jaegher, H. (2010). “Horizons for the enactive mind: values, social interaction, and play,” in Enaction: Towards a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science, eds J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, and E. A. Di Paolo (London: Bradford Book; Cambridge MIT Press, 32–87.

Google Scholar

Fodor, J. (1983). The Modularity of Mind. Boston, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception., Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.

Google Scholar

Hintzman, D. L. (1986). “Schema abstraction” in a multiple-trace memory model. Psychol. Rev. 93, 411–428. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.93.4.411

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hutto, D. D., and Peeters, A. (2018). “The roots of remembering: Radically enactive recollecting,” in New Directions in the Philosophy of Memory, eds K. Michaelian, D. Debus, and D. Perrin (New York, NY: Routledge, 97–118.

Google Scholar

Kosslyn, S. M. (1994). Image and Brain. The Resolution of the Imagery Debate. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Neisser, U. (1996). Remembering as doing. Behav. Brain Sci. 19, 203–204. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X00042308

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

O'Regan, J. K. (2011). Why Red Doesn't Sound Like a Bell: Understanding the Feel of Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Tulving, E. (1995). “Organization of memory: Quo vadis?,” in The Cognitive Neurosciences, ed M. S. Gazzaniga (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 753–847.

Google Scholar

Turo, S., Collin, F., and Brouillet, D. (2019). “The importance of the body-specificity in the evaluation of visuospatial working memory. aging, neuropsychology and cognition,” in Agir pour connaître, ed D. Brouillet (Grenoble: Presses Universitaires de France), 79.

Google Scholar

Vallet, G. T. (2015). Embodied cognition of aging. Front. Psychol. 6:463. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00463

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Mind. Boston, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Versace, R., Vallet, G. T., Riou, B., M, L., Labeye, E., and Brunel, L. (2014). ACT-IN: an integrated view of memory mechanisms. J. Cogn. Psychol. 26, 280–306. doi: 10.1080/20445911.2014.892113

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Whittlesea, B. W. A. (1987). Preservation of specific experiences in the representation of general knowledge. Cognition 13, 3–17. doi: 10.1037/0278-7393.13.1.3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zimmer, H. D., Cohen, R. L., Guynn, M. J., Engelkamp, J., Kormi-Nouri, R., and Foley, M. A. (2001). Memory for Action: A Distinct Form of Episodic Memory? New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Keywords: cognition, memory, enaction, limb movements, oculomotor movements

Citation: Brouillet D (2020) Enactive Memory. Front. Psychol. 11:114. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00114

Received: 07 November 2019; Accepted: 15 January 2020;
Published: 04 February 2020.

Edited by:

Claudia Repetto, Catholic University of the Sacred Heart, Italy

Reviewed by:

Pia Tikka, Tallinn University, Estonia

Copyright © 2020 Brouillet. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Denis Brouillet, ZGVuaXMuYnJvdWlsbGV0JiN4MDAwNDA7dW5pdi1tb250cDMuZnI=

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.