- Laboratorio de Neurociencia Cognitiva y Social, Facultad de Psicología, Universidad Diego Portales, Santiago, Chile
When closely examined, several biological mechanisms reveal themselves as implementing a physical and dynamical two-way link or coupling between the organism and the world. In these cases, some mechanisms' components can either physically cross the body-world boundary or are brought by the organism's motor actions onto specific sensory surfaces. As with any biological phenomenon, the historical contingencies of these sensorimotor activities generate plastic changes within the organism, that in turn determine its capacities at any given time. Body-world coupling instances are evident in examples that we will describe later, such as breathing, sensori-motor activities, and others. In the present piece, we attempt to position social cognitive phenomena as the result of the mechanisms involved in the organism's coupling history with its world. This coupling constitutes one of the cornerstones of the so called 4E approach to cognition (Newen et al., 2018), from which we will also draw concepts and distinctions in our effort to relate coupling mechanisms with social phenomena. Even though reviewing the 4E approach to cognition escapes the scope of the present piece, we can briefly state that the 4E cognition framework wants to bring multiple approaches together under a sole emblem. It understands cognition as a natural phenomenon, embodied in the biophysics of the body which is embedded both phylo- and ontogenically into the animal's ecological niche. To the 4E approach, cognition is also opportunistic and promiscuous as can be extended toward the world with objects both material (e.g., technology) and conceptual (e.g., institutions). Finally, the 4E approach thinks cognition as intended for action in an ongoing interactional sense-making process; an enactive phenomenon. The 4E cognition framework owes its current form to several landmark work such as the “enactive approach” (Varela et al., 2017), the “distributed cognition branch of cognitive science” (Flor and Hutchins, 1991; Hutchins, 1995), and the “extended mind” proposal (Clark and Chalmers, 1998), among others.
Despite decades of conceptual development of the 4E approach and its diverse subfields, there are many questions regarding its particular implications for neuroscience (e.g., how can neuroscientists can actually implement the 4E approach directly into their research agendas? Is one-person neuroscience necessary?, etc.) (Di Paolo and De Jaegher, 2012; Willems and Francken, 2012). As experimental neuroscientists interested in the interactional nature of cognition, we would like to extract the mechanistic implications of the 4E approach: components, activities, and processes (What?, How?, When?), their context (When?, How?) and their weights (How important?). Epistemologically, we concur with the view that conceives mechanisms as models of the phenomena to explain and consider the building of mechanistic models a fundamental explanatory aim of neuroscience (Craver, 2007). Without a mechanistic picture of the ways in which the 4Es constitute and/or affect cognitive processes, we are left with few tools to further empirical research.
We start by considering relevant distinctions provided by De Jaegher et al. (2010), where constitutive, enabling, and contextual factors can be identified as the “set of circumstances” which are phenomena themselves. A contextual factor modulates the phenomenon, whilst an enabling one is necessary for the phenomenon to occur. Finally, constitutive factors are processes, parts, and/or pieces that produce the phenomenon itself. What happens if we add a dynamic and mechanistic framework to the De Jaegher, Di Paolo, and Gallagher's proposal? The phenomenon to explain -at any scale (from action potentials to social interaction)- can be understood as the result of the dynamic operation of one or more mechanisms. Such mechanisms comprise components, their activities and the processes in which they participate, whose structural and functional organization in certain conditions produce the phenomenon (Bechtel and Abrahamsen, 2005; Craver, 2007). Thus, we suggest that constitutive factors are processes that can be composed of different components of a mechanism under consideration at different moments of time. Examples of components participating in a constitutive fashion are ion channels, for the phenomenon of the action potential, and participating agents for social interaction. In contrast, contextual and enabling factors are better understood here as elements which interact with mechanisms' components and can change its operation regime. Examples of enabling factors are the existence of ionic gradients across the membrane, for the action potential, and the alertness level of a participant, for social interaction. Examples of contextual factors are, a specific ion channel type for the action potential, and a given environmental setting, for social interaction. It is important to note here that the constitutive, enabling, or contextual quality of a given factor it is not fixed, but can change throughout the organism's ontogeny or history of structural change.
We think our mechanistic view is compatible with the original proposal of De Jaegher et al. (2010). In what follows, we consider the above mentioned points in some detail. We start by examining different mechanisms of body-world coupling, to then propose ways to extend this viewpoint into social-cognitive phenomena, considering the organism's ontogeny.
Body-World Coupling
Active Coupling Through Sensorimotor Activities
An example of body-world coupling is represented by an animal's sensory-motor activities. In situations where the sensory processes are important for the organism, there is usually a profound interplay between the animal's actions and the operation of its sensors (Rojas-Líbano et al., 2014). This is evident in motor actions associated with sensory sampling of the environment: touching, sniffing, echolocating, whisking, visual scanning. These actions allow the animal to bring stimuli to sensory surfaces. In most of these cases, stimuli sampling takes place in the wider context of adaptive and context-sensitive behavior. The animal actively moves its sensory systems to make decisions about navigation, small displacements, further explorations, language actions, and the like (Ganguly and Kleinfeld, 2004; Hayhoe and Ballard, 2005; Rojas-Líbano and Kay, 2012; Clark, 2013; Arce-McShane et al., 2016).
The appropriate interplay or coordination between motor actions and sensory activations requires the participation of certain components of the world in the sensory-motor mechanism. Therefore, cognitive activities involving any type of movement will demand some environmental components to become participants of a mechanism (i.e., a transiently constitutive factor). If we manipulate world conditions that interfere with this loop, we can potentially destroy the organism's coupling in the sense that we decrease its ability to interact coherently with its world. Examples are everywhere. Sniffs manipulate the number of odor molecules drawn onto the olfactory epithelium, as well as the rate (i.e., flow) at which those molecules travel through the nose (Rojas-Líbano and Kay, 2012). Tactile (e.g., whisker, finger) movements are coordinated with body movements and control the spatiotemporal frequency at which mechanical stimuli contact the skin cutaneous receptors (Kurnikova et al., 2017). Eye/head/body movements effectively displace the photoreceptor surface so as to receive photons coming from specific objects from the visual scene (Schroeder et al., 2010), and mechanisms such as the accommodation reflex modify the amount and direction of light that reaches the retina, via the modification of pupil size and lens width (Michael-Titus et al., 2010). All these motor activities manipulate world components and -through this manipulation- cause changes onto sensory surfaces (Figures 1A,B). Thus, world components continuously move back and forth from participating in processes contextual or enabling to constitutive factors for a given point in time and a given sensorimotor act.
Figure 1. Illustration of body-world coupling, sensorimotor mechanisms, and the ontogeny of social cognition. Circles represent mechanisms' components internal to the organism (Ci), and crossed circles depict world components (Cw). Arrows represent causal effects between components. (A) In non-sensorimotor body-world couplings, an organism's motor activities capture world's components and makes them interact with body components. (B) In sensorimotor body-world couplings, through active motor sampling activities (e.g., sniffing, touching, fixating) the organism dynamically brings world components onto sensory surfaces. During ontogeny, the occurrence (or not) of specific sensorimotor activities produces plastic changes in body components, represented here as weighted arrows and circles. (C) Social cognition as a process grounded in sensorimotor coupling. World components relevant to sensorimotor coupling could well be stimuli produced by another organism, such as physical stimuli resulting from communication processes, and different agents coupled with shared world components can lead to social cognitive phenomena. This kind of sensorimotor coupling might entail different plastic processes within each organism (represented as different weighted arrows inside each agent). S, sensory; Mm, motor actions for movement; Ms, motor actions for sampling.
Other Examples of Coupling
Some mechanisms are part of the basic autonomy of a living being and can be independent of active volitional control. There are many examples, such as coupling through circadian rhythms or, at the cellular scale, through membrane potential maintenance, nutrient exchange, and structural interactions with the extracellular matrix. However, for the sake of simplicity, let us specifically focus on mammalian breathing as a non-sensorimotor example of a mechanism that allows an organism to functionally couple with its world. We know a fairly good deal of the neural mechanisms that implement breathing in mammals (Feldman and Del Negro, 2006). In this process, the animal actively exchanges components with its world, specifically air volumes with different amounts of oxygen and carbon dioxide. Neurons in the brainstem periodically fire impulses that eventually send activity down the phrenic nerve, delivering acetylcholine onto the muscle cells of the diaphragm. The diaphragm then contracts, expanding the thoracic cavity and increasing lung volume. This expansion draws air from the organism's surroundings into the lungs. Finally, the diaphragm relaxes, pushing air from inside the lungs back to the exterior of the animal's body. Accompanying the volume exchange there is a substance exchange: inspired air is more enriched in oxygen than expired air, which in turn is more enriched in carbon dioxide. At a molecular scale, we can conceive the mechanism as a continuous exchange of molecules. From an outside reservoir enriched in oxygen molecules, the organism draws oxygen inside and pushes out carbon dioxide. This mechanism operates as long as the animal preserves its biological autonomy.
Now, consider what happens when we intervene on the external side. Lowering the air oxygen concentration causes a decrease in blood oxygen, which in turn activates peripheral and central chemoreceptor neurons (Teppema and Dahan, 2010). The activation of the latter triggers an increase in drive to the diaphragm, resulting in stronger, and more frequent breathing cycles. Something similar happens if we prevent molecules from crossing the boundary, say by occluding the airway. This indicates that by manipulating the external state of affairs, and/or by preventing physical exchanges across the body-world boundary, we causally intervene in the mechanism. We propose that this is a feature of mechanisms that couple body and world. It is also trivially true that several manipulations of the external conditions can causally affect the body, such as when the body is hit, for example, by a heavy object. But in those cases the world component involved was not implicated in a regular mechanism with the organism.
Ontogeny, Social Cognition, and Body-World Coupling Mechanisms
In the cases described above, and in many others, what we see is a physiological mechanism that contains -as part of its regular components- some element(s) of the world. By altering either internal or external components, we alter the mechanism operation (Figures 1A,B).
Let M be a (neuro)physiological mechanism (e.g., respiration, sensorimotor operations, circadian rhythms) containing internal components Ci which normally interact with some world's components Cw (any processes and/or entities, whether living or not, present outside the organism's physical body). Traditionally, it is conceived that the operation of M depends on Ci alone. However, for relevant biological phenomena, such as respiration or sensorimotor activities, Cw are mechanism components, participating in the resulting processes, and therefore we think is useful to regard them as constitutive1. Likewise, other Cw would be enabling and/or contextual, depending on the phenomena under consideration. Considering Cw as constitutive and/or enabling elements of a given M, we can further state that many organizational principles of the brain -generated from multiple operating mechanisms- will be much better explained by incorporating their relationship to the world (Clark and Chalmers, 1998; Cosmelli and Thompson, 2010; Parada and Rossi, 2018).
We could also say that the operation of a given M will depend on the organism's past and current temporospatial contingencies (i.e., both Ci and Cw). A key notion here is that biological mechanisms are not timeless laws, but historically contingent processes (Craver, 2007). Consider, as an example, the mechanisms of neural plasticity. It has been shown that present neuronal properties -both structural and functional2- are dependent on the neuron's previous interactions with its immediate environment (Rose and Rankin, 2001; Bailey et al., 2015; Andersen et al., 2017; Schulz and Lane, 2017). Importantly, this is not a special feature of neurons, but a general biological phenomenon. The actual state and capacities of any organism are activity- and ontogeny-dependent, and are always intertwined with the environment in which ontogeny takes place (Stagg et al., 2011; Kelly et al., 2012; Ganguly and Poo, 2013; Sale et al., 2014; Fields, 2015). Social-cognitive phenomena can be conceived, within this framework, as interactions occurring through the sharing of some Cw between the agents engaged in it (Figure 1C).
Taking into account the dependence on history of biological mechanisms, it is particularly relevant to distinguish the role of Cw at different moments along ontogeny. At different moments, the weight of a Cw could play a role as a constitutive, enabling, or contextual factors in a given phenomenon. For example, the case of behavioral habituation shows that, under sustained interactions, responses to the same Cw can decrease drastically, turning a Cw stimulus from a once-constitutive element to a mere contextual perturbation (Brunelli et al., 1976). In what follows, we use these ideas to propose a link between ontogenic mechanisms of body-world coupling and social interactions.
Social interaction starts very early during development, from prenatal experiences to turn-taking in babies to early verbalizations in infants (Siddiqui and Hägglöf, 2000; Kugiumutzakis, 2017; Quigley et al., 2017). From the point of view of mechanisms of body-world coupling, these developmental changes correspond to an increment in the allowed complexity of sensorimotor interactions. Mechanistically, increased sensorimotor complexity can be reached by reducing the sensorimotor contingencies' dimensionality, using both history of interactions and sensorimotor function. This is the organism's current morphological shape, as a product of previous body-world couplings in time, affords more complex actions contained in appropriate ecological niches. A now-classic example is the theoretical (Smith et al., 1999) and empirical (Smith and Thelen, 2003) dynamical systems account of the A-not-B error in infants (Piaget, 1962). Briefly, the processes underlying the perseverative reaching seen in the A-not-B error are not only continuously tied to the infant's sensorimotor system but also to her history of interactions (Spencer et al., 2011). From our perspective, evidence from animal models suggests a constitutive role of external factors such as maternal state during gestation (Kofman, 2002), maternal care/physical contact (Cancedda et al., 2004; Sale et al., 2004), as well as overall environmental conditions (Cai et al., 2009). Similar effects have been reported in humans; social, cultural, and/or physical environmental conditions in earlier developmental stages might bias -or even shape- bio-psycho-social trajectories (Guzzetta et al., 2009; Bowers and Yehuda, 2016; McEwen, 2017). Later in life, most of these factors can become enabling and/or contextual.
A more speculative example -directly related to social cognition- could be found in language; a higher-level cognitive phenomenon profoundly sensitive to ontogenic changes (Peña et al., 2003; Dehaene-Lambertz et al., 2008; Mampe et al., 2009; Mahmoudzadeh et al., 2013; Werker and Gervain, 2013; Werker and Hensch, 2015). The available evidence indicates that human auditory learning starts in the third trimester of gestation (Shahidullah and Hepper, 1994; Hepper, 1996). We further interpret this evidence as suggesting a constitutive role for prenatal listening experiences (Cw) in the specific physiological and developmental trajectory that gives rise to speech processing brain structures (Ci) (Wermke and Friederici, 2004). Between the 8th and 10th month of age, this body-world coupling begins its consolidation, allowing infants to extract statistical regularities (Saffran et al., 1996), which we conceive as a dimensionality reduction of the complex linguistic world (Werker and Tees, 1984; Maurer and Werker, 2014)3. Following our interpretation of these data, listening experiences and verbal interactions (Cw) become contextual factors after the 10th month of age (Werker and Curtin, 2005; Werker and Hensch, 2015). We further speculate that such change, from constitutive to contextual, illustrates the dimensionality reduction required for the appearance of more complex sensorimotor operations, such as actively seeking learning opportunities, maximizing informative interactions, and the beginning of adult-like social interactions (Begus et al., 2016). We still lack both data and tools to appropriately model the role, weight, and influence of external factors (from physical interplay to social interactions to processes unfolding from them) in the emergence of social-cognitive functioning and the overall biophysics of human experience.
Closing Remarks
The present opinion piece seeks to facilitate a mechanistic approximation to multi-level phenomena, grounding social cognition, and social interaction into time-dependent functional and structural components and their interplay; a goal for the 4E approach to cognition. Furthermore, it points to the need of modeling, through experimental manipulations, the weight and influence of both internal [i.e., (neuro)physiological] and external (i.e., objects, processes, other people) components at a given developmental period. This modeling can be achieved through tools derived from network science and/or machine learning techniques (Vespignani, 2011; Boonstra et al., 2015; Sekara et al., 2016; Shine et al., 2016; Avena-Koenigsberger et al., 2017; Aguilera, 2018; Parada and Rossi, 2018). Furthermore, implementing scalable experimental paradigms (Parada, 2018; Matusz et al., 2019; Shamay-Tsoory and Mendelsohn, 2019) and generating novel hypotheses of interacting brain/body systems functioning during natural cognition (De Jaegher et al., 2010, 2016; Di Paolo and De Jaegher, 2012; Gramann et al., 2014; Ladouce et al., 2017; Parada, 2018; Parada and Rossi, 2018) are among the most outstanding challenges for the 4E-cognition research program. We believe that the incorporation of a mechanistic framework facilitates meeting those challenges and advancing a deeper understanding of cognitive phenomena, social, and otherwise.
Author Contributions
DR-L and FP conceptualized the present work and wrote the current version for publication.
Funding
The present work was supported by Comisión Nacional de Investigación Científica y Tecnológica (CONICYT, Chile), through FONDECYT Iniciación en Investigación Grant No. 11180620 awarded to FP. FP was also funded from FONDECYT Regular Grant No. 1170292. Both DR-L and FP receive funding from FONDECYT Regular Grant No. 1190610. Funding sources (CONICYT, Chile) had no role in the production and development of this manuscript. DR-L receives funding from FONDECYT 1180932.
Conflict of Interest
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Acknowledgments
The authors would like to thank Dr. Ismael Palacios and Dr. Alejandra Rossi for insightful comments and constant meaningful conversations during the writing of this work. We would also like to thank the reviewers for their deeply constructive comments and suggestions during the review process.
Footnotes
1. ^We follow Craver (2007) in using manipulability as a criterion for recognizing mechanisms' components. Briefly stated, if interventions on the mechanism as a whole are accompanied by changes of a potential component, and if interventions on the component produce, in turn, changes in the mechanism, then the component under consideration is a mechanism's component.
2. ^And hence of the networks in which the neuron participates.
3. ^This is also seen in other aspects of perceptual development (Scott et al., 2007).
References
Aguilera, M. (2018). Rhythms of the collective brain: metastable synchronization and cross-scale interactions in connected multitudes. Complexity 2018:4212509. doi: 10.1155/2018/4212509
Andersen, N., Krauth, N., and Nabavi, S. (2017). Hebbian plasticity in vivo: relevance and induction. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 45, 188–192. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2017.06.001
Arce-McShane, F. I., Ross, C. F., Takahashi, K., Sessle, B. J., and Hatsopoulos, N. G. (2016). Primary motor and sensory cortical areas communicate via spatiotemporally coordinated networks at multiple frequencies. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 113, 5083–5088. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1600788113
Avena-Koenigsberger, A., Misic, B., and Sporns, O. (2017). Communication dynamics in complex brain networks. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 19, 17–33. doi: 10.1038/nrn.2017.149
Bailey, C. H., Kandel, E. R., and Harris, K. M. (2015). Structural components of synaptic plasticity and memory consolidation. Cold Spring Harb. Perspect. Biol. 7:a021758. doi: 10.1101/cshperspect.a021758
Bechtel, W., and Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: a mechanist alternative. Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci. 36, 421–441. doi: 10.1016/j.shpsc.2005.03.010
Begus, K., Gliga, T., and Southgate, V. (2016). Infants' preferences for native speakers are associated with an expectation of information. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 113, 12397–12402. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1603261113
Boonstra, T. W., Danna-Dos-Santos, A., Xie, H.-B., Roerdink, M., Stins, J. F., and Breakspear, M. (2015). Muscle networks: Connectivity analysis of EMG activity during postural control. Sci. Rep. 5:17830. doi: 10.1038/srep17830
Bowers, M. E., and Yehuda, R. (2016). Intergenerational transmission of stress in humans. Neuropsychopharmacology 41, 232–244. doi: 10.1038/npp.2015.247
Brunelli, M., Castellucci, V., and Kandel, E. R. (1976). Synaptic facilitation and behavioral sensitization in Aplysia: possible role of serotonin and cyclic AMP. Science 194, 1178–1181. doi: 10.1126/science.186870
Cai, R., Guo, F., Zhang, J., Xu, J., Cui, Y., and Sun, X. (2009). Environmental enrichment improves behavioral performance and auditory spatial representation of primary auditory cortical neurons in rat. Neurobiol. Learn. Memory 91, 366–376. doi: 10.1016/j.nlm.2009.01.005
Cancedda, L., Putignano, E., Sale, A., Viegi, A., Berardi, N., and Maffei, L. (2004). Acceleration of visual system development by environmental enrichment. J. Neurosci. 24, 4840–4848. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0845-04.2004
Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 36, 181–204. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12000477
Clark, A., and Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis 58, 7–19. doi: 10.1093/analys/58.1.7
Cosmelli, D., and Thompson, E. (2010). “Embodiment or envatment? Reflections on the bodily basis of consciousness,” in Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science, eds J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, and E. Di Paolo (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 361–385.
Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. New York, NY: Clarendon Press.
De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., and Adolphs, R. (2016). What does the interactive brain hypothesis mean for social neuroscience? A dialogue. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond., B, Biol. Sci. B Biol. Sci. 371:20150379. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2015.0379
De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., and Gallagher, S. (2010). Can social interaction constitute social cognition? Trends Cogn. Sci. 14, 441–447. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2010.06.009
Dehaene-Lambertz, G., Hertz-Pannier, L., Dubois, J., and Dehaene, S. (2008). How does early brain organization promote language acquisition in humans? Euro. Rev. 16, 399–411. doi: 10.1017/S1062798708000513
Di Paolo, E., and De Jaegher, H. (2012). The interactive brain hypothesis. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 6:163. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2012.00163
Feldman, J. L., and Del Negro, C. A. (2006). Looking for inspiration: new perspectives on respiratory rhythm. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 7, 232–242. doi: 10.1038/nrn1871
Fields, R. D. (2015). A new mechanism of nervous system plasticity: activity-dependent myelination. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 16, 756–767. doi: 10.1038/nrn4023
Flor, N. V., and Hutchins, E. L. (1991). “A case study of team programming during perfective software maintenance,” in Empirical Studies of Programmers: Fourth Workshop eds J. Koenemann-Belliveau, T. Glenn Moher, and S. P. Robertson (Norwood, NJ: Intellect Books), 36.
Ganguly, K., and Kleinfeld, D. (2004). Goal-directed whisking increases phase-locking between vibrissa movement and electrical activity in primary sensory cortex in rat. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 101, 12348–12353. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0308470101
Ganguly, K., and Poo, M.-M. (2013). Activity-dependent neural plasticity from bench to bedside. Neuron 80, 729–741. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2013.10.028
Gramann, K., Ferris, D. P., Gwin, J., and Makeig, S. (2014). Imaging natural cognition in action. Int. J. Psychophysiol. 91, 22–29. doi: 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2013.09.003
Guzzetta, A., Baldini, S., Bancale, A., Baroncelli, L., Ciucci, F., Ghirri, P., et al. (2009). Massage accelerates brain development and the maturation of visual function. J. Neurosci. 29, 6042–6051. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5548-08.2009
Hayhoe, M., and Ballard, D. (2005). Eye movements in natural behavior. Trends Cogn. Sci. 9, 188–194. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2005.02.009
Hepper, P. G. (1996). Fetal memory: does it exist? What does it do? Acta Paediatr. 85, 16–20. doi: 10.1111/j.1651-2227.1996.tb14272.x
Kelly, S. A., Panhuis, T. M., and Stoehr, A. M. (2012). Phenotypic plasticity: molecular mechanisms and adaptive significance. Compr. Physiol. 2, 1417–1439. doi: 10.1002/cphy.c110008
Kofman, O. (2002). The role of prenatal stress in the etiology of developmental behavioural disorders. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 26, 457–470. doi: 10.1016/S0149-7634(02)00015-5
Kugiumutzakis, G. (2017). “Intersubjective vocal imitation in early mother-infant interaction,” in New Perspectives in Early Communicative Development eds J. Nadel and L. Camaioni (New York, NY: Routledge, 23–47.
Kurnikova, A., Moore, J. D., Liao, S.-M., Deschênes, M., and Kleinfeld, D. (2017). Coordination of orofacial motor actions into exploratory behavior by rat. Curr. Biol. CB, 27, 688–696. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2017.01.013
Ladouce, S., Donaldson, D. I., Dudchenko, P. A., and Letswaart, M. (2017). Understanding minds in real-world environments: toward a mobile cognition approach. Front. Human Neurosci. 10:694. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2016.00694
Mahmoudzadeh, M., Dehaene-Lambertz, G., Fournier, M., Kongolo, G., Goudjil, S., Dubois, J., et al. (2013). Syllabic discrimination in premature human infants prior to complete formation of cortical layers. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 110, 4846–4851. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1212220110
Mampe, B., Friederici, A. D., Christophe, A., and Wermke, K. (2009). Newborns' cry melody is shaped by their native language. Curr. Biol. CB 19, 1994–1997. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2009.09.064
Matusz, P. J., Dikker, S., Huth, A. G., and Perrodin, C. (2019). Are we ready for real-world neuroscience? J. Cogn. Neurosci. 31, 327–338. doi: 10.1162/jocn_e_01276
Maurer, D., and Werker, J. F. (2014). Perceptual narrowing during infancy: a comparison of language and faces. Dev. Psychobiol. 56, 154–178. doi: 10.1002/dev.21177
McEwen, B. S. (2017). Allostasis and the epigenetics of brain and body health over the life course: the brain on stress. JAMA Psychiatry. 74, 551–552. doi: 10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2017.0270
Michael-Titus, A., Revest, P., and Shortland, P. (2010). “7 - the visual system,” in The Nervous System, 2nd Edn, eds A. Michael-Titus, P. Revest, and P. Shortland (London, UK: Churchill Livingstone, 121–140.
Newen, A., De Bruin, L., and Gallagher, S, (eds.). (2018). The Oxford handbook of 4E Cognition. Croydon: Oxford University Press.
Parada, F. J. (2018). Understanding natural cognition in everyday settings: 3 pressing challenges. Front. Human Neurosci. 12:386. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2018.00386
Parada, F. J., and Rossi, A. (2018). If neuroscience needs behavior what does psychology need? Front. Psychol. 9:433. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00433
Peña, M., Maki, A., Kovacić, D., Dehaene-Lambertz, G., Koizumi, H., Bouquet, F., et al. (2003). Sounds and silence: an optical topography study of language recognition at birth. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 100, 11702–11705. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1934290100
Quigley, K. M., Moore, G. A., Propper, C. B., Goldman, B. D., and Cox, M. J. (2017). Vagal regulation in breastfeeding infants and their mothers. Child Dev. 88, 919–933. doi: 10.1111/cdev.12641
Rojas-Líbano, D., Frederick, D. E., Egaña, J. I., and Kay, L. M. (2014). The olfactory bulb theta rhythm follows all frequencies of diaphragmatic respiration in the freely behaving rat. Front. Behav. Neurosci. 8:214. doi: 10.3389/fnbeh.2014.00214
Rojas-Líbano, D., and Kay, L. M. (2012). Interplay between sniffing and odorant sorptive properties in the rat. J. Neurosci. 32, 15577–15589. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1464-12.2012
Rose, J. K., and Rankin, C. H. (2001). Analyses of habituation in Caenorhabditis elegans. Learn. Memory 8, 63–69. doi: 10.1101/lm.37801
Saffran, J. R., Aslin, R. N., and Newport, E. L. (1996). Statistical learning by 8-month-old infants. Science 274, 1926–1928. doi: 10.1126/science.274.5294.1926
Sale, A., Berardi, N., and Maffei, L. (2014). Environment and brain plasticity: towards an endogenous pharmacotherapy. Physiol. Rev. 94, 189–234. doi: 10.1152/physrev.00036.2012
Sale, A., Putignano, E., Cancedda, L., Landi, S., Cirulli, F., Berardi, N., et al. (2004). Enriched environment and acceleration of visual system development. Neuropharmacology 47, 649–660. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropharm.2004.07.008
Schroeder, C. E., Wilson, D. A., Radman, T., Scharfman, H., and Lakatos, P. (2010). Dynamics of active sensing and perceptual selection. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 20, 172–176. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2010.02.010
Schulz, D. J., and Lane, B. J. (2017). Homeostatic plasticity of excitability in crustacean central pattern generator networks. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 43, 7–14. doi: 10.1016/j.conb.2016.09.015
Scott, L. S., Pascalis, O., and Nelson, C. A. (2007). A domain-general theory of the development of perceptual discrimination. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 16, 197–201. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8721.2007.00503.x
Sekara, V., Stopczynski, A., and Lehmann, S. (2016). Fundamental structures of dynamic social networks. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 113, 9977–9982. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1602803113
Shahidullah, S., and Hepper, P. G. (1994). Frequency discrimination by the fetus. Early Hum. Dev. 36, 13–26. doi: 10.1016/0378-3782(94)90029-9
Shamay-Tsoory, S. G., and Mendelsohn, A. (2019). Real-life neuroscience: an ecological approach to brain and behavior research. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 14, 841–859. doi: 10.1177/1745691619856350
Shine, J. M., Bissett, P. G., Bell, P. T., Koyejo, O., Balsters, J. H., Gorgolewski, K. J., et al. (2016). The dynamics of functional brain networks: integrated network states during cognitive task performance. Neuron 92, 544–554. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2016.09.018
Siddiqui, A., and Hägglöf, B. (2000). Does maternal prenatal attachment predict postnatal mother–infant interaction? Early Hum. Dev. 59, 13–25. doi: 10.1016/s0378-3782(00)00076-1
Smith, L. B., and Thelen, E. (2003). Development as a dynamic system. Trends Cogn. Sci. 7, 343–348. doi: 10.1016/s1364-6613(03)00156-6
Smith, L. B., Thelen, E., Titzer, R., and McLin, D. (1999). Knowing in the context of acting: the task dynamics of the A-not-B error. Psychol. Rev. 106:235. doi: 10.1037/0033-295x.106.2.235
Spencer, J. P., Perone, S., and Buss, A. T. (2011). Twenty years and going strong: a dynamic systems revolution in motor and cognitive development. Child Dev. Perspect. 5, 260–266. doi: 10.1111/j.1750-8606.2011.00194.x
Stagg, N. J., Mata, H. P., Ibrahim, M. M., Henriksen, E. J., Porreca, F., Vanderah, T. W., et al. (2011). Regular exercise reverses sensory hypersensitivity in a rat neuropathic pain model: role of endogenous opioids. Anesthesiology 114, 940–948. doi: 10.1097/ALN.0b013e318210f880
Teppema, L. J., and Dahan, A. (2010). The ventilatory response to hypoxia in mammals: mechanisms, measurement, and analysis. Physiol. Rev. 90, 675–754. doi: 10.1152/physrev.00012.2009
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (2017). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Vespignani, A. (2011). Modelling dynamical processes in complex socio-technical systems. Nat. Phys. 8, 32–39. doi: 10.1038/nphys2160
Werker, J. F., and Curtin, S. (2005). PRIMIR: a developmental framework of infant speech processing. Lang. Learn. Dev. 1, 197–234. doi: 10.1080/15475441.2005.9684216
Werker, J. F., and Gervain, J. (2013). “Speech perception in infancy: a foundation for language acquisition,” in The Oxford Handbook of Developmental Psychology, Vol. 1, ed P. David Zelazo (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 909–925.
Werker, J. F., and Hensch, T. K. (2015). Critical periods in speech perception: new directions. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 66, 173–196. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-010814-015104
Werker, J. F., and Tees, R. C. (1984). Cross-language speech perception: evidence for perceptual reorganization during the first year of life. Infant Behav. Dev. 7, 49–63. doi: 10.1016/S0163-6383(84)80022-3
Wermke, K., and Friederici, A. D. (2004). Developmental changes of infant cries–the evolution of complex vocalizations. Behav. Brain Sci. 27, 474–475. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X04390102
Keywords: sensorimotor mechanisms, social cognition, mechanistic explanation, ontogeny, 4E-cognition, sensorimotor coupling
Citation: Rojas-Líbano D and Parada FJ (2020) Body-World Coupling, Sensorimotor Mechanisms, and the Ontogeny of Social Cognition. Front. Psychol. 10:3005. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.03005
Received: 08 February 2019; Accepted: 18 December 2019;
Published: 14 January 2020.
Edited by:
Peter König, University of Osnabrück, GermanyReviewed by:
Miguel Aguilera, University of the Basque Country, SpainValentina Fantasia, Max Planck Institute for Human Development, Germany
Copyright © 2020 Rojas-Líbano and Parada. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Daniel Rojas-Líbano, daniel.rojas@udp.cl