Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 09 October 2018
Sec. Cognitive Science

Commentary: Commentary: Beauty Requires Thought

  • Independent Researcher, Berlin, Germany

A Commentary on
Commentary: Beauty Requires Thought

by Luoto, S. (2017). Front. Psychol. 8:1281. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01281

I wish to make sense of an obvious conflict between a recent study published in Current Biology (Brielmann and Pelli, 2017) and a commentary on this study published in Frontiers in Psychology (Luoto, 2017). Accordingly, I comment on both the commentary and the study equally.

The Kant-inspired claim that “Beauty Requires Thought,” experimentally confirmed by the study of Brielmann and Pelli (2017) and Luoto (2017) succinctly argued objection, insisting that elaborate “cognitive processing is not a prerequisite for the appreciation of beauty” are diametrically opposed. There is, however, a possibility to do justice to both lines of evidence and to turn the contradiction into a contribution.

Kant's third Critique has two parts, the Critique of the Aesthetic Power of Judgment and the Critique of the Teleological Power of Judgment. The latter is about the “objective purposiveness of nature in its entirety, as a system of which the human being is a member” (Kant, 1790, 05:380). Objective purposiveness makes an appreciation “either teleological or grounded in mere sensations of an object (gratification or pain)” (Kant, 1790, 05:270, cf. 279). Responding in the horizon of reproduction and care is inherently purposive and predisposed by instincts and inclinations. Instinct is “[t]he inner necessitation of the faculty of desire to take possession of [an] object before one is familiar with it” (Kant, 1798, 07:365). Inclinations are acquired by experience. “In some cases (e.g., the sexual instinct; see Kant, 1775-1776, 25:584) one can feel an instinct without a direct cognition of the object of that instinct.” (Frierson, 2014) This strikingly coincides with the evidence Luoto provides concerning sexual stimuli (Ponseti and Bosinski, 2010; Gillath and Collins, 2016), facial beauty (Willis and Todorov, 2006) and the integration of visual information outside of consciousness (Mudrik et al., 2014; cf. Kant, 1798, 07:135f).

Qualitative (that is, formal) perfection is “belonging to teleology” (Kant, 1797, 06:386). Accordingly, Luoto's line of evidence has also an overlap with the judgment of perfection, an aesthetic judgment adherent to a prototype. This is especially interesting since Armstrong and Detweiler-Bedell (2008) connected this type of judgment to the fluency model of aesthetic pleasure (Reber et al., 2004).

Nonetheless, beyond responding to physical attractiveness in an implicitly teleological manner I can as well adopt a solely aesthetic-reflective attitude—also in the face of physical attractiveness. Here “at issue is not … what it is for us as a purpose, but how we take it in” (Kant, 1790, 05:350). The course of the aesthetic-reflective engagement reflects the richness of the expressive patterns and possible interpretations, and manifests itself in an animated interplay of imagination and understanding. The inherent motivational dynamics of the interplay are pleasant (Bluehm, 2017). Different stimuli in this way induce the same type of pleasure. Crucially, cognitive faculties are involved—nonetheless beauty is felt, not concluded (Wieland, 2001; Bluehm, 2018). Pleasure (inter alia) is explained “as the feeling that expresses a condition that promotes life and its activity.” (Guyer, editorial note, p. 366 in Kant, 1790; cf. 05:204, 05:244, 05:313). So the pure (or reflective) aesthetic judgment is triggered by the purposiveness of the form of an object (Kant, 1794, 20:230) for cognition in general (roughly, being “richly interpretable”—Biederman and Vessel, 2006; Biederman, 2017) without to serve any specific purpose. This type of purposiveness is said to pertain to the community of all judging subjects, understood in the most general sense (united e.g., by space and time as common format of intuition).

In conclusion, both lines of evidence, Brielmann/Pelli's and Luoto's, seem to have their right. They refer to different phenomena. The obvious conflict between Brielmann/Pelli and Luoto supports the assumption, that the correspondence between aesthetic preference behavior (as life world phenomenon) and aesthetic-reflective practice is rather limited.

Addison (1712) already distinguishes “two kinds of beauty”, the first with background in sexual desire (Guyer, 2015). In the Kantian approach (1790) different phenomena obtain different names. Levinson (2011) posits “Beauty Is Not One.” Empirically, Brielmann et al. (2017) found, artistic coherence is not experienced to depend on idealized body proportions. Schulz and Hayn-Leichsenring (2017) dissociate attractiveness and artistic beauty.

Besides the valuable overall outcome, Brielmann and Pelli's presentation of their Kantian sources prompts a word of warning. It is the imagination, which enters into a harmonious interplay with the understanding. To ascribe the free play to “the faculties of sensation and understanding ([2] (p. 102, §4), [7])” is mistaken (Brielmann and Pelli, 2017 p. 1506). Sensations are what the faculty of sensibility—a receptive opposed to a spontaneous faculty—receives from the object. Further: 1764, in the Observations on the feeling of the beautiful and the sublime Kant by no means “claimed that beauty requires thought and that sensuous pleasures do not” (Brielmann and Pelli, 2017, p. 1506). To the contrary, in this early essay beauty is addressed as “agreeable,” and is said to “charm” and to “touch” (Kant, 1764, 02:208f). All these attributes become contrast terms to beauty in Kant's mature approach, and furnish exactly the realm, which Brielmann and Pelli endeavor to test as their second task: whether sensuous pleasures can be experienced as beautiful. Thus, they included trials with primarily sensory stimuli, such as candies. Sensuous pleasures are for Kant “the agreeable” and do not “supply a supplement … to the satisfaction in the form.” However, they can contribute indirectly by “awakening and sustaining attention” (Kant, 1790, 05:225f). Beauty permeated with sensory satisfaction is called impure. In the experiment, 37% of participants “responded ‘definitely yes' for beauty on candy trials.” The authors report, that most of these participants “remarked that sucking candy had personal meaning for them, like a fond childhood memory” (Brielmann and Pelli, 2017, p. 1511). The taste seem to operate as memory key (Proust, 1913-1927). We see an attention-directing role in addition to the sensory pleasure itself. One of the notable merits of the paper is the fact that it records the natural use of the term “beautiful” for quite protean animating immersive positive experiences.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

Parts of an earlier version were included in the poster Pleasure as self-maintaining motivation—a Kantian approach, presented at the Visual Science of Art Conference 2017 in Berlin; I am grateful for all the highly qualified feedback.

References

Addison, J. (1712, June 23). Taste and the pleasures of the imagination, Vol. 3. The Spectator. 412, 543–544.

Armstrong, T., and Detweiler-Bedell, B. (2008). Beauty as an emotion: The exhilarating prospect of mastering a challenging world. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 12, 305–329. doi: 10.1037/a0012558

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Biederman, I. (2017). Aesthetics and the brain. Abstracts from the 5th Visual Science of Art Conference (VSAC). Art Percept. 5, 337–426. doi: 10.1163/22134913-00002099

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Biederman, I., and Vessel, E. A. (2006). Perceptual Pleasure and the Brain. Am. Sci. 94, 249–255. doi: 10.1511/2006.59.995

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bluehm, K. (2017). Pleasure as self-maintaining motivation – a kant-based approach. Abstracts from the 5th Visual Science of Art Conference (VSAC). Art Percept. 5, 337–426. doi: 10.1163/22134913-00002099

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bluehm, K. (2018). “[D]as Vermögen, durch […] Lust […] zu urtheilen”, in Akten des 12. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses ‘Natur und Freiheit' in Wien 2015. Hg. Berlin: V. L. Waibel und M. Ruffing; Walter de Gruyter.

Brielmann, A. A., Fingerhut, J., and Prinz, J. (2017). The Golden Ratio is not always preferred in art. Abstracts from the 5th Visual Science of Art Conference (VSAC). Art Percept. 5, 337–426. doi: 10.1163/22134913-00002099

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brielmann, A. A., and Pelli, D. G. (2017). Beauty requires thought. Curr. Biol. 27, 1506–1513. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2017.04.018

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Frierson, P. (2014). Kant's Empirical Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Gillath, O., and Collins, T. (2016). Unconscious desire: the affective and motivational aspects of subliminal sexual priming. Arch. Sex. Behav. 45, 5–20. doi: 10.1007/s10508-015-0609-y

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Guyer, P. (2015). A History of Modern Aesthetics, Vol. 1, The Eighteenth Century. Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Kant, I. (1764). “Observations on the feeling of the beautiful and sublime,” Transl. by P. Guyer, in Anthropology, History, and Education, eds G. Zöller and R. B. Louden (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge University Press) 2007. In the Prussian (today Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy Edition, Vol. 2, 205–256.

Google Scholar

Kant, I. (1775-1776). “Anthropology Friedländer,” Transl. by G. F. Munzel, in Kant's Lectures on Anthropology, eds R. B. Louden and A. W. Wood (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge University Press) 2012. In the Prussian (today Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy Edition, Vol. 25, 469–728.

Kant, I. (1790). “Critique of the power of judgment,” Transl. by P. Guyer and E. Matthews, ed P. Guyer (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge University Press 2000). In the Prussian (today Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy Edition, Vol. 5, 165–484.

Kant, I. (1794). “First Introduction to the Critique of the Power of Judgment,” first published by J. S. Beck (Hg.) in Erläuternder Auszug aus den critischen Schriften des Herrn Prof. Kant auf Anrathen desselben (Riga: Hartknoch) 541–590, Transl. by P. Guyer and E. Matthews, ed P. Guyer in Critique of the Power of Judgment (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge University Press) 2000. In the Prussian (today Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy Edition, Vol. 20, 193–251.

Kant, I. (1797). “The metaphysics of morals,” Transl. by Mary J. Gregor, in Practical Philosophy, eds M. J. Gregor and A. W. Wood (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge University Press) 1995. In the Prussian (today Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy Edition Vol. 6, 203–293.

Google Scholar

Kant, I. (1798). “Anthropology from a pragmatic standpoint,” Transl. by A. W. Wood. in Anthropology, History, and Education, eds G. Zöller and R. B. Louden (The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, Cambridge University Press) 2007. In the Prussian (today Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy Edition, Vol. 7, 117–333.

Levinson, J. (2011). “Beauty Is Not One: The Irreducible Variety of Visual Beauty”, in The Aesthetic Mind, eds P. Goldie and E. Schellekens (Oxford University Press) pp. 190-207. Reprinted in: Levinson, J., (2016). Aesthetic Pursuits: Essays in Philosophy of Art (Oxford University Press), 98–132.

Google Scholar

Luoto, S. (2017). Commentary: Beauty Requires Thought. Front. Psychol. 8:1281. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01281

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mudrik, L., Faivre, N., and Koch, C. (2014). Information integration without awareness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 18, 488–496. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2014.04.009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ponseti, J., and Bosinski, H. A. (2010). Subliminal sexual stimuli facilitate genital response in women. Arch. Sex. Behav. 39, 1073–1079. doi: 10.1007/s10508-009-9587-2

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Proust, M. (1913-1927). À la Recherche du Temps Perdu. In English known under the title Remembrance of Things Past (transl. C. K. Scott Moncrieff, since 1922, transl. by T. Kilmartin based on the new French edition of 1954); under the title In Search of Lost Time (Kilmartin transl.

Reber, R., Schwarz, N., and Winkielman, P. (2004). Processing fluency and aesthetic pleasure: is beauty in the perceiver's processing experience? Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev. 8, 364–382. doi: 10.1207/s15327957pspr0804_3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schulz, K. (2017). Face attractiveness versus artistic beauty in art portraits: a behavioral study. Front. Psychol. 8:2254. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.02254

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wieland, W. (2001). Urteil und Gefühl. Kants Theorie der Urteilskraft. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.

Willis, J., and Todorov, A. (2006). First impressions: making up your mind after a 100-ms exposure to a face. Psychol. Sci. 17, 592–598. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01750

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: beauty, physical attractiveness, immanent teleology, Kant, self-organization, aesthetic judgment, neuroaesthetics

Citation: Bluehm K (2018) Commentary: Commentary: Beauty Requires Thought. Front. Psychol. 9:1917. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01917

Received: 01 October 2017; Accepted: 18 September 2018;
Published: 09 October 2018.

Edited by:

Eddy J. Davelaar, Birkbeck University of London, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Elvira Brattico, Aarhus University, Denmark

Copyright © 2018 Bluehm. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Katharina Bluehm, YXJ0dGVudGlvbkBnbXguZGU=

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.