- 1Scuola di Specializzazione in Psicoterapia Cognitiva S.r.l. – Associazione di Psicoterapia Cognitiva, Rome, Italy
- 2Guglielmo Marconi University, Rome, Italy
Recent accounts support the existence of two distinct feelings of guilt: altruistic guilt (AG), arising from the appraisal of not having been altruistic toward a victim and deontological guilt (DG), emerging from the appraisal of having violated an intuitive moral rule. Neuroimaging data has shown that the two guilt feelings trigger different neural networks, with DG selectively activating the insula, a brain area involved in the processing of disgust and self-reproach. Thus, insula activation could reflect the major involvement of self-reproach in DG rather than in AG. However, only a few studies have empirically tested whether and how DG and AG differently affect decision making and none have compared enhanced self-worth. Here we asked three groups of participants, respectively, induced with either pride, DG or AG, to participate in a third-party version of the ultimatum game in which they were asked to decide on behalf of others to accept or reject economic offers with several degrees of fairness. Results revealed that only deontological participants had higher median acceptances of Moderately Unfair offers as compared to proud participants. However fairness judgments were not different between groups, suggesting that deontological participants’ moral standards had not decreased. Crucially, a higher increase in DG was associated with an increase in the odds of accepting 30:70 offers. The opposite effects that DG and pride exert on self-worth can account for these results. Specifically, proud participants felt entitled enough to take action in order to restore equity, while deontological participants followed the “Do not play God” principle, which limited their decisional autonomy, not allowing them to decide on behalf of others.
Introduction
“Impious myself, and from an impious race.
Where is my splendor now?”
(Oedipus the King, Sophocles)
Traditional approaches to guilt tend to describe a unique emotion with specific situational and psychological determinants, a precise behavioral drive and a clear evolutionary function. However, different models lead to different explanations of the same emotional phenomenon, namely guilt. According to the intrapsychic or psychoanalytic approach (Mosher, 1965, 1966; Lewis, 1971; Piers and Singer, 1971; Wertheim and Schwarz, 1983; Monteith, 1993), guilt is the emotional result of a conflict between our interiorized moral authority and our behaviors (Fromm, 1985). Its evolutionary function is to keep human behavior in line with moral standards (Freud, 1959, 1961a,b). In this view, guilt corresponds to the feeling of having disobeyed one’s own inner moral values. This might cause an expectation or fear of punishment (Wicker et al., 1983), the tendency to atone or the will to apologize (Nelissen and Zeelenberg, 2009). The person who feels guilty has the feeling of being a “bad person” (Lewis, 1971).
Conversely, following the interpersonal theory (Hoffman, 1981, 1987; Baumeister et al., 1994; Niedenthal et al., 1994; Tangney, 1999; Tangney and Dearing, 2002; Ketelaar and Au, 2003), guilt results from the awareness of having caused unjustified harm to another or, in a more general sense, not having behaved altruistically. This feeling is based on empathy and compassion (Hoffman, 1981; Baumeister et al., 1994; Niedenthal et al., 1994; O’Connor et al., 1999, 2000; Tangney, 1998). Here, the trigger is a suffering person, unjustly penalized, who we did not help or did not even try to share his or her pain. The evolutionary function of altruistic guilt (AG) is to establish non-aggressive relationships and its aim is to protect and maintain reciprocal altruism and to restore equity (Trivers, 1971; Baumeister et al., 1994).
Even if both approaches describe guilt as a unique feeling, it is clear that they show important contrasting elements both on the level of motivation and on action tendencies. In particular, the psychoanalytic approach focuses on the fear of punishment (Tomkins, 1963; Mosher, 1965; Lewis, 1971), which should induce avoidant behavior. In contrast, according to the interpersonal approach, guilt should promote altruistic tendencies as well as a closeness to the putative “victim.” The question therefore is the following: is guilt a single emotion that activates contrasting behavioral outcomes depending on different situational variables, or are we to consider the existence of two distinct senses of guilt? (Carnì et al., 2013).
A recent attempt has been made (Mancini, 2008) to integrate these two perspective in a comprehensive model. According to this approach the intrapsychic and interpersonal models are not mutually exclusive if we consider the existence of two independent emotions, namely deontological guilt (DG) and AG. The word independent here signals that although these two kinds of guilt can be (and often are) experienced at the same time, they can be conceptually distinguishable with reference to appraisal theories of emotion, according to which specific cognitions are important antecedents of specific emotions and thereby of specific action tendencies (Smith and Ellsworth, 1985; Oatley and Johnson-Laird, 1987, 1992; Frijda et al., 1989; Scherer, 1999, 2001). In particular, in AG there is always a victim that suffers harm and the appraisal of not having been altruistic, but there may not have been any violation of moral rules (Baumeister et al., 1994). In DG, on the contrary, there might not have been a victim at all and the appraisal of having violated an intuitive moral rule is necessary and sufficient (Mancini, 2008; Gangemi and Mancini, 2011). Therefore, the two feelings are not just triggered by different types of events, but differ only in virtue of the appraisal of the event in the context of individual goals (Carnì et al., 2013). In particular, DG emerges from the appraisal of having disobeyed moral authority, or a deontological norm such as “Do not play God.” According to this norm, no one has the right to make a decision that does not respect the limits of his/her social rank or function (Sunstein, 2005). Therefore, the model predicts feelings of unworthiness and the expectation, or fear, of a punishment (Mancini, 2008; Gangemi and Mancini, 2011). Punishment is an essential ingredient for this type of guilt because, through the punishment of the transgressor, rank differences between him/her and authority are restored (Mancini, 2008). AG appears when one appraises his/her own conduct as not altruistic. The emotional state is connected to empathy, sorrow, and compassion for the victim. According to the model, AG should imply behavioral tendencies aimed at minimizing the number of victims, alleviating their suffering and restoring equity (Baumeister et al., 1995; Ketelaar and Au, 2003; Kubany and Watson, 2003). Indeed its evolutionary function is to maintain, reinforce and protect social relationships through the development of an empathic preoccupation for the well-being of others, especially loved ones (Hoffman, 1982, 1998; Baumeister et al., 1994; Tangney and Dearing, 2002).
Recent empirical studies have tested the predictive power of this model, showing that it is possible to separately induce AG and DG by using facial expressions combined with the internal dialog typically connected with each guilt feeling (Basile and Mancini, 2011). Moreover, neuroscientific results revealed that different neuronal networks are involved in each kind of guilt, with the insula selectively responding to DG stimuli (Basile et al., 2010). It is known that the insula is activated when self-reproach and disgust are experienced (e.g., Rozin et al., 2000), thus the selective activation of the insula could reflect the major involvement of self-reproach and self-loathing characterizing DG more than AG (Rozin et al., 2000; Basile et al., 2010). Therefore, another difference concerning the two kinds of guilt might rely on the extent to which the two emotions affect self-worth. However, only a few studies have empirically tested whether and how AG and DG independently affect decision making (D’Olimpio and Mancini, 2014; Mancini and Gangemi, 2015) and none have compared a contingent enhancement of self-worth. Thus, the current study aims at disclosing how healthy participants, induced with either AG or DG, perform on a decision-making task. If DG – but not AG – decreases participants’ self-worth, only the former should prevent participants from performing any behavior that could threaten the “Do not play God” principle. To disclose the difference between AG and DG with respect to self-worth, we contrasted the induction of the two guilt feelings with that of pride in a third group of participants. Trivially, DG and pride are antithetic with respect to self-worth, which is diminished by the former and inflated by the latter.
In the present study we used a modified version of the Ultimatum Game (UG). In the classical one-shot version of the UG (Güth et al., 1982) two players must divide a given amount of money (e.g., €10). One player proposes how to split the money by making an offer. If the responder accepts, the money is divided according to the original offer; if he/she rejects, both players receive nothing. According to standard economic models, in order to maximize his/her own payoff the responder should accept any offer. Indeed, although inequitable, any offer is better than nothing. However, in accordance with the theories of reciprocal altruism (Trivers, 1971) and inequity aversion (Fehr and Schmidt, 1999), participants systematically reject unfair offers below 20–30% of the total pot (Nowak, 2000; Camerer, 2003), preferring to gain nothing rather than accepting an unequal distribution of resources (Fehr and Camerer, 2007). This type of behavior is also known as altruistic punishment, because it is aimed at preventing selfish free riders from adopting a similar behavior with a member of the same social group (Fehr and Gächter, 2002).
To measure how altruistic tendencies and aversion to break deontological norms differently affect decision making we expanded on previous studies in behavioral economics, which used economic games as experimental settings. In particular, the UG has been repeatedly used to examine fairness perception, prosocial motives and responses to unfairness (Camerer and Fehr, 2004; Sanfey, 2007), also under the effect of several negative emotions such as anger (Andrade and Ariely, 2009), sadness (Harlé and Sanfey, 2007), and disgust (Moretti and di Pellegrino, 2010). Additionally, the link between self-conscious emotions such as guilt (Ketelaar, 2004, 2005; de Hooge et al., 2007; Nelissen et al., 2007) or shame (de Hooge et al., 2008) and prosocial-behavior was extensively investigated by means of repeated games (e.g., the public good game, see Ketelaar and Au, 2003). While on the one hand previous literature provides a useful basis for comparison to our results, on the other hand it has failed to consider guilt not only in interpersonal terms but also in deontological terms. For this reason in the present study we used the third-party version of the UG. In this version participants must decide to accept or reject the offers on behalf of a third party (Civai et al., 2010; Corradi-Dell’Acqua et al., 2013). Recently it has been demonstrated that although physiological indexes of arousal were lower when participants played on behalf of a third party, they kept rejecting unfair offers (Civai et al., 2010). Hence, this version of the UG represents a valid method to investigate participants’ equity motives not just on an interpersonal axis, which contrasts selfishness and altruism but on an axis which allows for investigating the human tendency to stick to deontological norms beyond one’s own payoff.
On the basis of the described model (Mancini, 2008) we made two main predictions. The model implies a reduction of self-worth following DG but not AG induction. Therefore our first prediction was that deontological individuals (but not altruistic ones) will present a higher acceptance rate of unfair offers as compared to proud individuals, pursuing the aim of not interfering with the natural course of events and following the “Do not play God” principle. Secondly, if equity motives drive altruistic participants’ behavior, we should observe a higher amount of altruistic punishment in this group as compared to deontological participants (i.e., a lower acceptance rate of unfair offers).
Materials and Methods
Participants
A sample of 75 healthy participants volunteered for the study (F = 62; Mean age = 31.75 (±7); age range = 26–49). Participants were postgraduate students in their first year of the school for cognitive therapy (SPC) program in Rome. They were naive to the purposes of the study. Each participant was randomly assigned to one of three experimental groups: (i) DG induction (n = 25); (ii) AG induction (n = 25) and (iii) pride induction (n = 25). Informed consent was obtained from each participant before the experimental phase. Each participant was provided with an envelope containing a demographic questionnaire investigating age, sex, marital status, education level, and two questions assessing the presence of a neurological disorder, a psychiatric diagnosis and present or past use of psychiatric drugs. None of the participants reported neurological or psychiatric disorders or the use of psychiatric drugs. The experimental protocol was approved by the local scientific committee of SPC and was performed in accordance with the ethical standards of the 1964 Declaration of Helsinki.
Procedure
Participants were tested in groups, during three separate sessions (i.e., one for each group). The experimenter informed participants that they were going to perform a paper and pencil questionnaire about emotions in everyday life. The paper and pencil procedure has been used in previous studies differentiating self-conscious emotions such as shame, guilt (Smith et al., 2002), and embarrassment (Tangney et al., 1996). Moreover group administration has been proven to be effective in the induction of guilt in general (Smith et al., 2002) and in the independent induction of AG and DG (Basile and Mancini, 2011). The experimenter instructed participants to remain silent for the entire duration of the experiment and to avoid any interaction. Participants filled in 9 Visual Analog Scales (VAS) to assess baseline mood. Once all participants completed the VAS, the emotion induction phase began. Right after the induction, participants were asked to again assess their mood on the same type of VAS. Finally, participants were provided with the Third-Party Ultimatum Game Questionnaire, which was created ad hoc. At the end of the experimental session participants were fully debriefed on the purposes of the study.
Emotion Induction
Altruistic guilt and deontological guilt inductions consisted of reading two stories evoking the corresponding emotion. The stories were taken from a preliminary stage of research in a previous study (D’Olimpio and Mancini, 2014). Specifically, they were selected by independent judges from a series of personal recalls provided by 120 undergraduate students. Participants were instructed to begin reading at the same time and the induction took place simultaneously for all of them. The group procedure was also successfully adopted in a previous study, in which DG and AG were independently induced (Basile and Mancini, 2011). The order of the stories was randomized across participants. To increase the power of the induction at the end of the stories participants were further asked to recall a life event in which they had felt the same way, remembering their emotional experience. For pride induction participants were asked to recall a life event in which they felt proud of themselves remembering their emotional experience and writing it down.
Emotion Induction Check
To assess the effectiveness of induction procedures, before and after the induction participants responded to several questions investigating the intensity of their different emotions. To conceal our interest in specific affective states, and in order to assess putative emotional halo effects, we included nine different emotions: shame, sadness, fear, disgust, anger, compassion, AG, DG, and happiness. The nine VAS scales were built following the appraisal theory of emotions, according to which specific cognitions are important antecedents of specific emotions and thereby of specific action tendencies (Smith and Ellsworth, 1985; Oatley and Johnson-Laird, 1987, 1992; Frijda et al., 1989; Scherer, 1999, 2001). Therefore, each affective state was identified by the name (e.g., DG), the corresponding mental state represented by an internal dialog sentence (e.g., “Oh God! What have I done! How dare I!?”), and the corresponding action tendency (e.g., desire to repent, to confess, to ask for forgiveness). Participants could rate the intensity of each emotion by making a mark with their pen on a VAS scale measuring 11 cm, ranging from 0 (not at all) to 100 (very much).
Third Party Ultimatum Game Questionnaire
Right after the emotion manipulation check, participants were provided with six hypothetical dilemmas. Each dilemma described a typical UG scenario in which two people must divide a sum of money. One of the two characters was described as the proposer and the other as the responder. Participants were instructed to play on behalf of the responder. Here is an example of the UG scenarios (translated from Italian):
Anna and Marco are brother and sister. They inherited a sum of money from their grandparents. The only condition for inheritance is that Anna must propose how to split the money. You have been called upon to decide on behalf of Marco. If you accept the offer proposed by Anna, the money will be divided according to the offer. If you refuse neither Anna nor Marco will gain anything. Anna made the following offer: 60% Anna, 40% Marco.
Offers were expressed as percentages of the total pot (i.e., 90:10, 80:20, 70:30, 60:40, 50:50, and 40:60). Indeed, it has been shown across various parameters and participant pools that rejection behavior in the UG is independent from the actual amount of money offered, and rather more affected by its relative value (Camerer, 2003). Each dilemma was associated with two different offers. Therefore, each type of offer was repeated twice for a total of 12 responses. Participants could respond by writing an A (acceptance) or an R (rejection) near each offer. Moreover, they could rate the fairness of the offer on a VAS scale ranging from 0 (not at all fair) to 100 (very fair). The order of the dilemmas and that of the offers was randomized across participants.
Data Analysis
A research assistant, who was blinded to the purpose of the study, coded all paper data. Since our data were not normally distributed across groups, as assessed by Shapiro–Wilk’s test (all Ps < 0.05), we employed non-parametric statistics.
Emotion Induction
For each subject VAS scores were measured in centimeters. To assess emotion induction effectiveness, pre and post induction VAS scores for each emotion were compared using the Wilcoxon signed-rank test in each of the three groups.
Furthermore, data coding revealed that eight participants originally coded as deontological reported a higher increase in AG intensity as compared to DG (+8.50, +9.70, +3.40, +2.90, +2, +5.50, +8, +2, respectively), even if they received the DG induction. Analogously, one participant originally coded as altruistic and one participant originally coded as proud, reported higher increase in DG scores as compared to the increase in AG and pride (+1, +8, respectively). Therefore, groups were re-coded accordingly and subsequent data analysis was performed on the following groups: Deontological group (n = 19), Altruistic group (n = 32) and Proud group (n = 24).
In order to assess the amount of change produced by the induction with respect to the baseline, an index was obtained by subtracting the pre-induction scores from the post-induction scores. The obtained indexes for each emotion were then compared between the three new groups, by means of the Kruskal–Wallis H test. Where appropriate post hoc pairwise comparisons were performed by means of the Mann–Whitney U test with a Bonferroni correction for multiple comparisons. Adjusted p-values are reported for significant comparisons.
Median Acceptance and Fairness Ratings
Offers were grouped in Unfair (10:90 and 20:80), Moderately Unfair (30:70 and 40:60), and Fair (50:50 and 60:40). A Kruskal–Wallis H test was run to test for differences between the three groups in the distribution of acceptance of each type of offer (i.e., 10, 20, 30, 40, 50, and 60%). Where appropriate post hoc pairwise comparisons were performed by means of the Mann–Whitney U test with a Bonferroni correction for multiple comparisons. Adjusted p-values are reported for significant comparisons. The same type of analysis was performed on fairness ratings.
Additionally, six cumulative odds ordinal logistic regressions with proportional odds were run to determine the effect of the post induction modulation of each of the nine emotions (shame, sadness, fear, disgust, anger, compassion, AG, DG, happiness) on each type of offer (i.e., 10, 20, 30, 40, 50, and 60%). Significant results were adjusted by means of the Bonferroni correction. Where appropriate adjusted p-values are presented.
Results
Induction Check
As shown in Table 1, the Wilcoxon signed-rank test, run on the original groups, those with 25 participants exposed to the three conditions, determined that the median post-induction scores related to DG and AG were higher as compared to the median pre-induction-scores in DG and AG groups, respectively. Furthermore, the proud group showed a significant increase in happiness scores (all Ps < 0.0001). Proud participants’ recalls are shown in Table 2.
TABLE 1. Pre and Post induction scores for each group, Wilcoxon Z and significance levels (∗p < 0.05; ∗∗p < 0.01; ∗∗∗p < 0.001).
TABLE 2. The Table reports pride episodes recalled by the 25 participants in the original proud group.
The Kruskal–Wallis H test, run on the three newly coded groups, revealed that the medians of the increase index scores were statistically significantly different between groups (Table 3). Distributions of the increase indexes were similar for all groups, as assessed by visual inspection of a boxplot.
TABLE 3. Kruskal–Wallis H test results for each emotion, with χ2 values and asymptotic significance (two-sided test).
Mann–Whitney U test for pairwise comparisons revealed that DG showed a higher increase in the deontological group (Median = 8.5) with respect to the altruistic group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.0003) and to the proud group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.0003). No significant differences were found between the altruistic group and the proud group in the increase of DG (p = 0.17, NS). Shame was increased to a higher extent in the deontological group (Median = 0.9) as compared to the proud group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.0003). No significant differences were found between the altruistic group and the proud group in the increase of shame (p = 0.124, NS). Fear increased more in the deontological group (Median = 1.8) than in the proud group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.0003). Additionally fear increase was higher in the altruistic group (Median = 1.1) as compared to the proud group (Adj.p = 0.0003).
Altruistic guilt showed a higher increase in the altruistic group (Median = 4.65) with respect to both the deontological group (Median = 1.2, Adj.p = 0.021) and the proud group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.0003). Additionally, AG was higher in the deontological group with respect to the proud group (Adj.p = 0.018). Compassion showed a higher increase in the altruistic group (Median = 5.7) with respect to both the deontological group (Median = 1.8, Adj.p = 0.042) and the proud group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.0003). Additionally, the deontological group showed a higher increase in compassion scores than the proud group (Adj.p = 0.0003). Furthermore, the increase in anger was higher in the altruistic group (Median = 2.150) as compared to both the deontological group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.0003) and the proud group (Median = 0, Adj.p = 0.021). In addition the median anger increase was not different between the deontological and the proud group (Adj.p = 0.153, NS).
Sadness showed a lower increase in the proud group (Median = –0.50) with respect to both the deontological group (Median = 1.9, Adj.p = 0.0003) and the altruistic group (Median = 0.5, Adj.p = 0.0003). Disgust showed a lower increase in the proud group (Median = 0) with respect to both the deontological group (Median = 5, Adj.p = 0.0003) and the altruistic group (Median = 0.5, Adj.p = 0.009). The median increase in shame, disgust, fear and sadness were not significantly different between the deontological group and the altruistic group (all Ps > 0.103).
Finally happiness increased to a higher extent in the proud group (Median = 4.95) both with respect to the deontological group (Median = –24, Adj.p = 0.0003) and to the altruistic group (Median = –6.45, Adj.p = 0.0003). Additionally, median happiness increase index was lower in the altruistic group than in the deontological group (Adj.p = 0.036). Differences in median values for each emotion between groups are represented in Figure 1.
FIGURE 1. The figure shows the median increase of each emotion after the induction for the deontological group (white bars), altruistic group (gray bars) and proud group (black bars). (A) The emotions presenting a higher median increase in the deontological group than in the proud group [namely deontologic guilt (DG), shame and fear]. (B) The emotions that presented a higher median increase in the altruistic group with respect to both the deontological and the proud group [namely altruistic guilt (AG), compassion and anger]. (C) The emotions presenting similar increase in the AG and DG group and happiness scores (which showed a higher decrease in the AG group with respect to the other two groups.
Median Acceptances between Groups
Figure 2 illustrates median acceptances as a function of the UG offers and emotion condition.
FIGURE 2. (A) Median acceptance of Moderately Unfair offers presented by the deontological group (white bar), the altruistic group (gray bar), and the pride group (black bar). (B) Median acceptance of Fair offers presented by the deontological group (white bar), the altruistic group (gray bar), and the proud group (black bar).
The distributions of acceptance had a similar shape for all groups, as assessed by visual inspection of the boxplots. The Kruskal–Wallis H test showed that for Moderately Unfair offers, median acceptance was statistically significantly different between groups, [χ2(2) = 7.567, p = 0.023]. The Mann–Whitney U test for pairwise comparisons revealed that median acceptance for the deontological group was higher than that of the proud group (Adj.p = 0.027; Figure 2A). Neither the comparison between the altruistic group and the proud group, nor that between the deontological group and the altruistic group were significantly different (p = 0.130, and p = 0.096, respectively). Moreover, for Fair offers, median acceptance values were significantly different between groups, [χ2(2) = 6.385, p = 0.041]. The Mann–Whitney U test for pairwise comparisons revealed that median acceptance of the altruistic group was higher than that of the proud group (Adj.p = 0.042; Figure 2B). Neither the comparison between the deontological group and the proud group, nor that between the deontological group and the altruistic group were significantly different (p = 0.144 and p = 0.337, respectively). For Unfair offers median acceptance was not significantly different between groups (p > 0.922).
Fairness Ratings
The Kruskal–Wallis H test on fairness ratings scores showed no significant differences between groups for all the three types of offers (all Ps > 0.285).
Ordinal Regression
The only ordinal regression model found to be significant was for 30% offers. The assumption of proportional odds was met, as assessed by a full likelihood ratio test comparing the residual of the fitted location model to a model with varying location parameters, [χ2(9) = 13.266, p = 0.151]. The deviance goodness-of-fit test indicated that the model was a good fit for the observed data, [χ2(139) = 135.165, p = 0.576], but most cells were sparse with zero frequencies in 66.7% of cells. However, the final model statistically significantly predicted the dependent variable over and above the intercept-only model, [χ2(9) = 135.165, p = 0.011]. A higher increase in DG was associated with an increase in the odds of accepting 30% offers, with an odds ratio of 1.466 (95% CI [1.166 to 1.843]), [Wald χ2(1) = 10.717, Adj.p = 0.009; Figure 3A]. The increase indexes of other emotions were not significantly associated with participants’ responses to 30% offers (all Ps > 0.13).
FIGURE 3. (A) The number of times participants accepted 30:70 offers (i.e., 0;1;2, X-axis) as a function of the increase in deontological guilt (Y-axis). Each participant is identified as deontological (white circles), altruistic (gray circles), or proud (black circles). (B) The number of times participants accepted 60:40 offers (i.e., 0;1;2, X-axis) as a function of the decrease in happiness (Y-axis). Each participant is identified as deontological (white circles), altruistic (gray circles), or proud (black circles). Spearman Rho correlation coefficients and their relative p-values are reported above each panel.
For 60% offers the deviance goodness-of-fit test indicated that the model was a good fit for the observed data, [χ2(139) = 115.055, p = 0.932], but most cells were sparse with zero frequencies in 66.7% of cells. However, the ability of the model to predict the dependent variable over and above the intercept-only model approached significance, [χ2(9) = 16.395, p = 0.059]. A higher decrease in happiness levels was associated with an increase in the odds of accepting 60% offers, with an odds ratio of 0.845 (95% CI [0.750 to 0.951], [Wald χ2(1) = 7.747, Adj.p = 0.045]. The assumption of proportional odds was met, as assessed by a full likelihood ratio test comparing the residual of the fitted location model to a model with varying location parameters, [χ2(9) = 14.736, p = 0.098; Figure 3B]. The increase indexes of other emotions were not significantly associated with participants’ responses to 60% offers (all Ps > 0.14).
Discussion
Our results showed that the induction was effective in enhancing baseline levels of the targeted emotion in each group. DG scores were higher in the deontological group as compared to the altruistic and the proud groups. However, eight participants originally coded as deontological presented a higher enhancement of AG as compared to DG and one participant originally coded as altruistic presented a higher enhancement of DG. It might be that the scenarios described in some of the stories used for the DG induction also elicited in some participants altruistic and empathic feelings (as accounted for by post-induction compassion scores, which were strongly enhanced in the original DG group). It is worth noting that previous experiments combined the use of internal dialog sentences with the exposure to emotional facial expressions (Basile and Mancini, 2011). This latter method might be more effective to separately induce the two types of guilt.
Data analysis performed on the increase indexes of the newly coded groups revealed that the enhancement in AG was accompanied by an increase in anger and compassion scores, which were greater in the AG group with respect to the other two groups. Additionally, the AG group presented a significantly higher decrease in happiness scores as compared to the other two groups. Similar emotional “halo effects” were also found in previous studies (see Basile and Mancini, 2011 relative to compassion and sadness, and D’Olimpio and Mancini, 2014 relative to anger). These effects were consistent with the goal of AG, which is to promote pro-social and reparative behaviors toward the victim and feeling sorry for her/him (Mancini, 2008; Basile and Mancini, 2011).
The main purpose of our research was to determine whether and how different guilt feelings, namely the deontological type and the altruistic type, differently affected decision making, as compared to pride in a third party version of the UG. In accordance with our first prediction, results showed that participants induced with DG accepted Moderately Unfair offers to a higher extent as compared to proud participants. This result can be explained by the opposite effect that DG and pride exert on self-worth. Indeed, recent accounts posited that factors others than immediate emotional reaction, such as the judgments directed toward the self, influence decision making in the UG (Dunn et al., 2010). Specifically, high trait positivity (i.e., the tendency to experience positive emotions rather than negative) was related to a higher rejection rate of unfair offers, while high trait negativity was related to the acceptance of such offers. Interestingly, the relationship between positive and negative trait levels and the levels of rejection of unfair offers was not mediated by contextual variations in participants’ mood. Therefore, the authors hypothesized that they were rather mediated by self-worth, with those of a positive disposition believing to be “worth more than that” and those of a negative disposition resigning themselves to “take the crumbs from under the table” (Dunn et al., 2010). Consistently, it was shown that high levels of disgust toward the self-strongly modulated moral judgments of others’ behavior. In particular, individuals with high traits of self-loathing judged strict moral transgressions (e.g., murder) as less disgusting and punishment deserving, as compared to participants with low self-loathing traits (Olatunji et al., 2012). Recent evidence has shown that AG and DG activate different brain networks. Specifically, while AG was associated with activity in medial prefrontal areas, consistently associated with theory of mind, empathy, and compassion (Blair, 1995; Shallice, 2001; Moll et al., 2006), DG activated the anterior cingulate cortex and insula, previously associated with self-reproach and disgust (Rozin et al., 2000).
An alternative explanation could be that since the induction of DG produced an increase in several other negative emotions, the increase in one of these or the general negativity of the affect experienced by deontological participants could have been predictive of their behavior in the UG. However, this interpretation seems to be disconfirmed by the results of the ordinal regression model, which showed only the increase of DG to be predictive of 30:70 offers median acceptance. In addition, fairness ratings were not different across groups, indicating that the higher acceptance rate of Moderately Unfair offers exhibited by deontological participants did not depend on a decreased ability to judge others’ behavior. According to the principle of “Do not play God” no one has the right to make a decision that does not respect the limits of his/her social rank or function (Sunstein, 2005). Therefore the adoption of this principle should induce a humble attitude, which results in the limitation of decisional autonomy (Mancini, 2008). Previous accounts have shown that DG and AG differently affect moral decision-making (Mancini and Gangemi, 2015). Specifically, participants induced with DG preferred inaction when faced with the switch version of the trolley dilemma, while those induced with AG preferred action (Mancini and Gangemi, 2015). Crucially, deontological participants justified their omission bias with the goal of not interfering with the natural order, or in other words, with the “Do not play God” principle (Gangemi and Mancini, 2013). Moreover, the presence of an authority limited participants’ decision-making autonomy activating the “Do not play God” principle and led them to prefer inaction (Gangemi and Mancini, 2013).
According to our second prediction, the induction of altruistic motives should have brought about a lower acceptance rate of unfair offers in AG participants as compared to DG participants. This would have also been consistent with the high scores of anger and the lower scores of happiness presented in the AG group with respect to the other two groups. Indeed, both angry and sad participants were significantly more likely to reject unfair offers in the classical version of the UG (Harlé and Sanfey, 2007; Andrade and Ariely, 2009). Contrastingly, altruistic participants’ median acceptance of Moderately Unfair offers was not significantly lower than that of deontological participants, nor was it higher than proud participants. One possible interpretation of this null result is that participants in the AG condition were somewhat divided between equity motives and the use of a utilitarian strategy, reflecting the aim of minimizing losses. Indeed, altruistic participants adopted a utilitarian strategy when faced with the switch version of the trolley moral dilemma (Mancini and Gangemi, 2015), choosing to “cause” the death of three people in order to save five others. Crucially, participants preferring the action tended to justify it by referring to the altruistic principle that prescribes minimizing other’s suffering (for example: “it’s better that three people die instead of five”). However, when faced with 60:40 offers, which are unbalanced in favor of the receiver, altruistic participants presented a higher median acceptance with respect to proud participants. The results of the ordinal regression suggest that these types of acceptances are compensatory, since 60:40 acceptances tended to be predicted by a decrease in happiness levels, lower in those who accepted these offers more frequently.
It is noteworthy that participants did not benefit economically from accepting the offers, since they were playing on behalf of a third party. According to social preference theory, people prefer to behave pro-socially because they derive higher hedonic value from mutual cooperation and altruism (Thibaut and Kelley, 1959; Fehr, 2008). Thus, it is widely held that the brain uses a common-reward metric for the processing of both individual and social rewards (Sanfey, 2007). Specifically, an increased activation of the ventral tegmental and striatal areas was found both when receiving money and in non-costly charitable donations (Moll et al., 2006; Harbaugh et al., 2007).
Conclusion
In sum, while DG leads to a higher acceptance rate of Moderately Unfair offers as compared to pride, AG does not show the same effect. We hypothesize that this occurs because proud participants feel entitled enough to take action in order to restore equity, while deontological participants are prone to take a humble attitude, which does not allow them to decide on behalf of others. AG instead may not entail a change in perceived hierarchy and possible utilitarian motives are not intense enough to produce any behavioral difference with proud participants in the acceptance of Moderately Unfair offers. However, in the present study self-worth was not directly estimated. This is a limitation of our results and future studies should directly assess the effect of AG and DG on self-worth and perceived moral hierarchy.
The distinction between AG and DG is important in light of the role played by guilt in obsessive compulsive disorder (OCD). Recent findings have shown that DG and not AG is the mental state underlying checking and cleaning compulsions (D’Olimpio and Mancini, 2014). Additionally, fMRI results have revealed an abnormal processing of DG (but not AG) in OCD patients (Basile et al., 2013). Finally, when faced with moral dilemmas, OCD patients – but not anxious patients – preferred omission, presumably in order to respect the of “Do not play God” principle (Mancini and Gangemi, 2015).
Author Contributions
Conceived and designed experiment: AM, FM. Data collection: AM, Alessia di Febo. Data Analysis: AM, FM. Wrote the paper: AM, FM.
Conflict of Interest Statement
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Acknowledgment
The authors are very thankful to Alessia di Febo for her help in data collection.
References
Andrade, E. B., and Ariely, D. (2009). The enduring impact of transient emotions on decision making. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 109, 1–8. doi: 10.1016/j.obhdp.2009.02.003
Basile, B., and Mancini, F. (2011). Eliciting guilty feelings: a preliminary study differentiating deontological and altruistic guilt. Psychology 2, 98–102. doi: 10.4236/psych.2011.22016
Basile, B., Mancini, F., Macaluso, E., Caltagirone, C., and Bozzali, M. (2013). Abnormal processing of deontological guilt in obsessive-compulsive disorder. Brain Struct. Funct. 219, 1321–1331. doi: 10.1007/s00429-013-0570-2
Basile, B., Mancini, F., Macaluso, E., Caltagirone, C., Frackowiak, R. S. J., and Bozzali, M. (2010). Deontological and altruistic guilt: evidence for distinct neurobiological substrates. Hum. Brain Mapp. 32, 229–239. doi: 10.1002/hbm.21009
Baumeister, R. F., Stillwell, A. M., and Heatherton, T. F. (1994). Guilt: an interpersonal approach. Psychol. Bull. 115, 243–267. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.115.2.243
Baumeister, R. F., Stillwell, A. M., and Heatherton, T. F. (1995). “Interpersonal aspects of guilt: evidence from narrative studies,” in Self-Conscious Emotions: The Psychology of Shame, Guilt, Embarrassment and Pride, eds J. P. Tangney and K. W. Fisher (NewYork, NY: Guilford Press).
Blair, R. J. (1995). A cognitive developmental approach to mortality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition 57, 1–29. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(95)00676-P
Camerer, C., and Fehr, E. (2004). “Measuring social norms and preferences using experimental games: a guide for social sciences,” in Foundations of Human Sociality: Economic Experiments and Ethnographic Evidence from Fifteen Small – Scale Societies, eds J. Henrich, R. Boyd, S. Bowles, C. Camerer, E. Fehr, and H. Gintis (New York, NY: Oxford University Press).
Camerer, C. F. (2003). Behavioral Game Theory: Experiments in Strategic Interaction. New York, NY: Russell Sage Foundation.
Carnì, S., Petrocchi, N., Del Miglio, C., Mancini, F., and Couyoumdjian, A. (2013). Intrapsychic and interpersonal guilt: a critical review of the recent literature. Cogn. Process. 14, 333–346. doi: 10.1007/s10339-013-0570-4
Civai, C., Corradi-Dell’Acqua, C., Gamer, M., and Rumiati, R. I. (2010). Are irrational reactions to unfairness truly emotionally-driven? Dissociated behavioural and emotional responses in the Ultimatum Game task. Cognition 114, 89–95. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2009.09.001
Corradi-Dell’Acqua, C., Civai, C., Rumiati, R. I., and Fink, G. R. (2013). Disentangling self- and fairness-related neural mechanisms involved in the ultimatum game: an fMRI study. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 8, 424–431. doi: 10.1093/scan/nss014
de Hooge, I. E., Breugelmans, S. M., and Zeelenberg, M. (2007). Moral sentiments and cooperation: differential influences of shame and guilt. Cogn. Emot. 21, 1025–1042. doi: 10.1080/02699930600980874
de Hooge, I. E., Breugelmans, S. M., and Zeelenberg, M. (2008). Not so ugly after all: when shame acts as a commitment device. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 95, 933–943. doi: 10.1037/a0011991
D’Olimpio, F., and Mancini, F. (2014). Role of deontological guilt in obsessive-compulsive disorder-like checking and washing behaviors. Clin. Psychol. Sci. 2, 727–739. doi: 10.1177/2167702614529549
Dunn, B. D., Makarova, D., Evans, D., and Clark, L. (2010). I’m worth more than that:” trait positivity predicts increased rejection of unfair financial offers. PLoS ONE 5:e15095. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0015095
Fehr, E. (2008). “Social preferences and the brain,” in Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain, eds P. W. Glimcher, C. F. Camerer, E. Fehr, and R. A. Poldrack (London: Academic∖Elsevier).
Fehr, E., and Camerer, C. F. (2007). Social neuroeconomics: the neural circuitry of social preferences. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11, 419–427. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2007.09.002
Fehr, E., and Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature 415, 137–140. doi: 10.1038/415137a
Fehr, E., and Schmidt, K. M. (1999). A theory of fairness competition & cooperation. Q. J. Econ. 114, 817–868. doi: 10.1162/003355399556151
Freud, S. (1959). “The ego and the ID,” in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey (London: Hogarth Press).
Freud, S. (1961a). “The dissolution of the Oedipus complex,” in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey (London: Hogarth Press).
Frijda, N. H., Kuipers, P., and Ter Schure, E. (1989). Relations among emotion, appraisal, and emotional action readiness. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 57, 212–228. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.57.2.212
Gangemi, A., and Mancini, F. (2011). “Guilt and guilts,” in Re-Constructing Emotional Spaces: From Experience to Regulation, eds R. Trnka, K. Balcar, and M. Kuška (Prague: Prague College of Psychosocial Studies Press).
Gangemi, A., and Mancini, F. (2013). “Moral choices: the influence of the do not play god principle,” in Proceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, Cooperative Minds: Social Interaction and Group Dynamics, eds M. Knauff, M. Pauen, N. Sebanz, and I. Wachsmuth (Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society).
Güth, W., Schmittberger, R., and Schwarze, B. (1982). An experimental analysis of ultimatum bargaining. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 3, 367–388. doi: 10.1016/0167-2681(82)90011-7
Harbaugh, W. T., Mayr, U., and Burghart, D. R. (2007). Neural responses to taxation and voluntary giving reveal motives for charitable donations. Science 316, 1622–1625. doi: 10.1126/science.1140738
Harlé, K. M., and Sanfey, A. G. (2007). Incidental sadness biases social economic decisions in the Ultimatum Game. Emotion 7, 876–881. doi: 10.1037/1528-3542.7.4.876
Hoffman, M. L. (1981). Is altruism part of human nature? J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 40, 121–137. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.40.1.121
Hoffman, M. L. (1982). “Development of prosocial motivation: empathy and guilt,” in The Development of Prosocial Behavior, ed. N. Eisenberg (New York, NY: Academic Press).
Hoffman, M. L. (1987). “The contribution of empathy to moral judgment,” in Empathy and its Development, eds N. Eisenberg and D. J. Strayer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Hoffman, M. L. (1998). “Varieties of empathy-based guilt,” in Guilt and Children, ed. J. Bybee (San Diego, CA: Academic Press).
Ketelaar, T. (2004). “Ancestral Emotions, Current Decisions: using Evolutionary Game Theory to explore the role of Emotions in decision-making,” in Evolutionary Psychology, Public Policy and Personal Decisions, eds C. Crawford and C. Salmon (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates).
Ketelaar, T. (2005). “The role of moral sentiments in economic decision making,” in Social Psychology and Economics, eds D. de Cremer, M. Zeelenberg, and K. Murnighan (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates).
Ketelaar, T., and Au, T. W. (2003). The effects of feelings of guilt on the behaviour of uncooperative individuals in repeated social bargaining games: an affect-as-information interpretation of the role of emotion in social interaction. Cogn. Emot. 17, 429–453. doi: 10.1080/02699930143000662
Kubany, E. S., and Watson, S. B. (2003). Guilt: elaboration of a multidimensional model. Psychol. Rec. 53, 51–90.
Mancini, F., and Gangemi, A. (2015). Deontological guilt and obsessive compulsive disorder. J. Behav. Ther. Exp. Psychiatry doi: 10.1016/j.jbtep.2015.05.003 [Epub ahead of print].
Moll, J., Krueger, F., Zahn, R., Pardini, M., de Oliveira-Souza, R., and Grafman, J. (2006). Human fronto-mesolimbic networks guide decisions about charitable donation. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 103, 15623–15628. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0604475103
Monteith, M. J. (1993). Self-regulation of stereotypical responses: implications for progress in prejudice reduction. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 65, 469–485. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.65.3.469
Moretti, L., and di Pellegrino, G. (2010). Disgust selectively modulates reciprocal fairness in economic interactions. Emotion 10, 169–180. doi: 10.1037/a0017826
Mosher, D. L. (1965). Interaction of fear and guilt in inhibiting unacceptable behavior. J. Consult. Psychol. 29, 161–167. doi: 10.1037/h0021748
Mosher, D. L. (1966). The development and multitrait-multimethod analysis of three measures of three aspects of guilt. J. Consult. Psychol. 30, 25–29. doi: 10.1037/h0022905
Nelissen, R. M. A., Dijker, A. J., and de Vries, N. K. (2007). How to turn a hawk into a dove and vice versa: interactions between emotions and goals in a give-some dilemma game. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 43, 280–286. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2006.01.009
Nelissen, R. M. A., and Zeelenberg, M. (2009). When guilt evokes self-punishment: evidence for the existence of a Dobby Effect. Emotion 9, 118–122. doi: 10.1037/a0014540
Niedenthal, P. M., Tangney, J. P., and Gavanski, I. (1994). “If only I weren’t” versus “If only I hadn’t counterfactual thinking. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 67, 585–595. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.67.4.585
Nowak, M. A. (2000). Fairness versus reason in the Ultimatum Game. Science 289, 1773–1775. doi: 10.1126/science.289.5485.1773
Oatley, K., and Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1987). Towards a cognitive theory of emotions. Cogn. Emot. 1, 29–50. doi: 10.1080/02699938708408362
Oatley, K., and Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1992). Terms of emotion: the inferences that can be drawn. Rev. Psicol. Soc. 7, 97–104. doi: 10.1186/2046-4053-3-5
O’Connor, L. E., Berry, J. W., and Weiss, J. (1999). Interpersonal guilt, shame and psychological problems. J. Soc. Clin. Psychol. 18, 181–203. doi: 10.1521/jscp.1999.18.2.181
O’Connor, L. E., Berry, J. W., Weiss, J., Schweitzer, D., and Sevier, M. (2000). Survivor guilt, submissive behaviour and evolutionary theory: the down-side of winning in social comparison. Br. J. Med. Psychol. 73, 519–530. doi: 10.1348/000711200160705
Olatunji, B. O., David, B., and Ciesielski, B. G. (2012). Who am I to judge? Self-disgust predicts less punishment of severe transgressions. Emotion 12, 169–173. doi: 10.1037/a0024074
Piers, G., and Singer, M. (1971). Shame and Guilt: A Psychoanalytic and Cultural Study. New York, NY: Norton.
Rozin, P., Haidt, J., and McCauley, C. R. (2000). “Disgust,” in Handbook of Emotions, eds M. Lewis and J. Haviland-Jones (New York, NY: Guilford Press).
Sanfey, A. G. (2007). Social decision-making: insights from game theory and neuroscience. Science 318, 598–602. doi: 10.1126/science.1142996
Scherer, K. R. (1999). “Appraisal theory,” in Handbook of Cognition and Emotion, eds T. Dalgleish and M. J. Power (Chichester: Wiley).
Scherer, K. R. (2001). “Appraisal considered as a process of multi-level sequential checking,” in Appraisal Processes in Emotion: Theory, Methods, Research, eds K. R. Scherer, A. Schorr, and T. Johnstone (New York, NY: Oxford University Press).
Shallice, T. (2001). ‘Theory of mind’ and the prefrontal cortex. Brain 124, 247–248. doi: 10.1093/brain/124.2.247
Smith, C. A., and Ellsworth, P. C. (1985). Patterns of cognitive appraisal in emotion. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 48, 813–838. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.48.4.813
Smith, R. H., Webster, J. M., Parrot, W. G., and Eyre, H. L. (2002). The role of public exposure in moral and nonmoral shame and guilt. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 83, 138–159. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.83.1.138
Tangney, J. P. (1998). “How does guilt differ from shame?” in Guilt and Children, ed. J. Bybee (New York, NY: Academic Press).
Tangney, J. P. (1999). “The self-conscious emotions: shame, guilt, embarrassment and pride,” in Handbook of Cognition and Emotion, eds T. Dalgleish and M. J. Power (New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons).
Tangney, J. P., and Dearing, R. L. (2002). Shame and Guilt. New York, NY: Guilford Press. doi: 10.4135/9781412950664.n388
Tangney, J. P., Miller, R. S., Flicker, L., and Barlow, D. H. (1996). Are shame, guilt and embarrassment distinct emotions? J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 70, 1256–1269. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.70.6.1256
Thibaut, J. W., and Kelley, H. H. (1959). The Social Psychology of Groups. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons.
Tomkins, S. S. (1963). Affect, Imagery, Consciousness: The Negative Affects, Vol. 2. New York, NY: Springer.
Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Q. Rev. Biol. 46, 35–57. doi: 10.1086/406755
Wertheim, E. H., and Schwarz, J. C. (1983). Depression, guilt, and self-management of pleasant and unpleasant events. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 45, 884–889. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.45.4.884
Keywords: guilt, altruistic guilt, deontological guilt, pride, ultimatum game, “Do not play God” principle
Citation: Mancini A and Mancini F (2015) Do not play God: contrasting effects of deontological guilt and pride on decision-making. Front. Psychol. 6:1251. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01251
Received: 13 April 2015; Accepted: 05 August 2015;
Published: 25 August 2015.
Edited by:
Luiz Pessoa, University of Maryland, College Park, USAReviewed by:
Gideon Emanuel Anholt, Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, IsraelJan Van Den Stock, KU Leuven, Belgium
Copyright © 2015 Mancini and Mancini. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Francesco Mancini, Scuola di Specializzazione in Psicoterapia Cognitiva S.r.l. – Associazione di Psicoterapia Cognitiva, Viale Castro Pretorio 116, 00186 Rome, Italy, mancini@apc.it