Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Psychol., 08 September 2023
Sec. Psychology of Language

Place and place names: a unified model

  • 1Department of Chinese Language and Literature, Central China Normal University, Wuhan, China
  • 2Department of English, Hainan University, Haikou, Hainan, China

The goal of this paper is to offer a unified account of Place as a central theoretical notion across different disciplines. We show that while psychology, geography and other sciences have been converging to a unified view of this notion, linguistics still offers a fragmented perspective. Consequently, place names lack a full-fledged analysis that connects this category to the psychological concept of place. We propose to overcome this impasse by introducing a multi-modal Discourse Representation Theory (DRT) account of place as a conceptual construct and place concepts as specific instances of this construct. We show that current variants of DRT permit us to model place names and their senses, i.e., the meaning(s) that individuals associate with Sydney. We then model non-linguistic place concepts, i.e., the mental representation(s) that individuals can have of the city carrying this name. We present a model of the relation between linguistic meaning and conceptual content via the notion of anchoring relations applied to place. We pair this formal treatment with a morpho-syntactic account of place names building on current generative syntax treatments of proper names. Once we have a morpho-syntactic and semantic model of place names, we use a frame semantics treatment to account for lexical relations among place names. We test the overarching model on a set of recalcitrant problems afflicting current linguistic and multi-disciplinary treatments of place. These are the grammatical complexity and lexical content of place names, place concepts and their networks, and inter-subjective, communicative models of place in discourse. By solving these problems, our account integrates several frameworks (DRT, conceptual analysis, generative syntax, frame semantics) and connects several disciplines (linguistics, psychology, geographic information science, communication models) via a novel, multi-modal account of place. We conclude by discussing the theoretical and empirical import of these results.

1. Introduction

Place is often defined as any location that can welcome humans and their social interactions, and to which humans can develop forms of attachment (Cresswell, 2014: Ch. 1). Contemporary geographical thinking on place originated in Tuan (1977) and deeply influenced psychology (Manzo and Devine-Wright, 2021), sociology (Low, 2016), and other disciplines. Complex theories of place(s) and relations between individuals and these concepts therefore emerged (e.g., Scannell and Gifford, 2014). Formal treatments of the properties shaping places were proposed in psychological frameworks (Canter, 1977, 1997). Formalizations of these notions also emerged in Geographic Information Science (GIS) and exploited formal ontologies, first order logic-based specifications of conceptual domains (Hamzei et al., 2020). Place is thus an increasingly refined notion that finds a mentalist counterpart in the general concept of “place,” and in its more specific declinations (e.g., “country,” “city”).

Linguistic disciplines, however, present a different picture. Toponomastics studies place names and their etymological roots (e.g., Sydney, Pitt Street: Tent and Blair, 2011; Perono Cacciafoco and Cavallaro, 2023). Linguistic typology offers cross-linguistic analyses of place names’ grammatical properties (Stolz and Levkovych, 2020). Though both frameworks have made important discoveries on place names, neither framework connects these discoveries to theories of place. Furthermore, the conceptual semantics and generative syntax frameworks use the term “Place” to analyse adpositions and their senses (respectively Jackendoff, 1983; Svenonius, 2010). The consequences of this theoretical mismatch between linguistics and other disciplines create the empirical impasse that we illustrate via (1)–(3).

(1) The plane landed in Sydney.

(2) Pitt Street is in Sydney.

(3) The boys are playing in a park.

The sentence in (1) describes an event of a plane landing in the Australian city of Sydney; (2) describes a certain street, as a place within Sydney’s business district. Sydney and Pitt Street are the place names that allow individuals to refer to these places. Instead, (3) describes some boys playing in a nameless park, i.e., a location introduced in discourse without a specific “platial” (i.e., place-like, Tenbrink, 2020) status. Therefore, (1)–(2) are sentences offering semantic information about two closely related and unique places; (3) offers information about some non-specific location identified as a park.

Geographic and psychological frameworks suggest that (1)–(2) convey information about places via place names, mediated via mind-internal place concepts (Kuhn, 2012; Low, 2016). Instead, most toponomastic works suggest that this reference is direct: individuals do not have concepts about places (Coates, 2017). Generative and conceptual frameworks would consider the P(repositional)P(hrase)s in Sydney and in a park, in (1)–(3), as equally referring to places via place concepts (Svenonius, 2010). Linguistic frameworks do not attempt to capture the content that place names carry; some frameworks do not even semantically distinguish place names from other NPs and spatial PPs. Hence, place names and place concepts receive short thrift in linguistics.

This neglected status of place names in linguistics has inter-disciplinary ramifications. Psychological research suggests that individuals can develop rich place concepts, and associate them to place names (Scannell and Gifford, 2010; Davies, 2013). Some individuals may use (1)–(2), and thus the name Sydney, to describe situations and facts about a city they love; others, for a place they are unfamiliar with. Other uses are possible; individuals can express their own conceptual views about places via place names, and continually develop rich mind-internal representations (i.e., concepts) of places. GIS works instead suggest that place names retrieval algorithms need detailed semantic and morpho-syntactic representations to inform place models (Buscaldi, 2011; Zhang and Gelernter, 2014). Linguistic theorising on place names, as we gleaned via (1)–(3), lacks a morpho-syntactic analysis of place names, and mostly explains away their semantic properties. Therefore, the cognitive mechanisms by which place names convey information about places remain mostly unexplored.

The goal of this paper is to ameliorate this situation by proposing a linguistic model of place names integrated with a conceptual model of place. We use Discourse Representation Theory (DRT: Kamp et al., 2011) as a semantic framework to model the content of Sydney, Pitt Street, and other place names. We choose this framework because current DRT architectures use a general format (“Discourse Representation Structures”) to model any mental content, irrespective of the modality (e.g., Pross, 2010; Maier, 2015; Kamp, 2022). Therefore, DRT provides a formal language that can model the multi-modal cognitive content of place and place names into a general, if preliminary theory of “place.” We integrate DRT as a Domain-general Representation Theory with a generative analysis of place names. We then show that the lexical properties and relations connecting place names can be modelled by integrating this multi-modal model (DRT plus syntax) with a frame semantics analysis. We therefore show that our model of “place” can pave the way for a novel, inter-disciplinary approach to platial research (Tenbrink, 2020).

To reach this goal, we first analyse “place” as a psychological concept of a geographical notion (Section 2). We then discuss GIS formal treatments (Section 3). We problematize the uses of the label “place” in Linguistics and outline desiderata for a linguistic analysis (Section 4). We develop a multi-modal, representational model of place concepts and place names. We achieve this result via domain-general DRT’s anaphoric relations between cognitive domains (“anchoring relations”), coupled with a generative view of place names’ grammatical properties. We then address a number of recalcitrant problems stemming from the lack of a theory of place names informed by theories of place. We thus offer an account of the linguistic properties of place names, how they represent place concepts and networks, and how individuals can share place concepts and relations in discourse and communication (Section 5). Section 6 discusses the consequences of this proposal for a theory of place. Section 7 concludes.

2. Place as a concept: from geography to psychology

The goal of this section is to discuss how psychology has absorbed the geographical notion of place. First, however, we establish our terminology. We use the term place concepts to refer to concepts for cities, streets and other entities that can be considered particular instantiations of the general concept of place. “Sydney,” “Pitt Street,” are possible labels for singular place concepts: concepts for one (quantity-wise) unique place. We standardly conceive concepts as multi-modal, mind-internal representations about entities in the world (Laurence and Margolis, 1999; Margolis and Laurence, 2007; Carey, 2009; Ursini and Samo, 2022). We use place(s) as a label for geographic entities, the mind-external counterparts of Place concepts. We use italics for place names: Sydney, Pitt Street, respectively, are the names for the “Sydney,” “Pitt Street” place concepts. Given this distinction between mind-internal place concepts and mind-external places, we will discuss how reference to either entity type can come about in Sections 4–5, once we introduce the relevant notions.

The emergence of place as a theoretical construct originates in the work of geographers offering philosophical reflections on humans and their environment (Relph, 1976; Seamon, 1979; Tuan, 1979, 1990). These geographers suggested that humans develop place concepts via their interaction with places, thus imbuing these concepts with subjective meaning. Subsequent works sought to explore the psychological and social dimensions that could shape these concepts (Couclelis, 1992; Agnew, 1993; Harve, 1994; Thrift, 1999; Hollenstein and Purves, 2010). Hence, they suggested that the content of place concepts can develop and vary considerably over time, depending on individuals and groups’ emotive and cognitive connections to places. For instance, local dwellers can develop love for Sydney as their home; international rugby fans can love or hate this city when visiting it to experience rugby matches; manyfold possible forms of attachment are certainly possible. Current theories in geography (e.g., Agnew, 2011), philosophy (e.g., Malpas, 2018) and psychology (e.g., Smith, 2017) thus accept place and place concepts as mirror-like notions about locations that are meaningful to humans.

Research on place concepts abounds (cf. Agnew et al., 2015: Ch. 1; Mocnik, 2022); however, proposals tend to diverge on working terms and notions. The notion of “place attachment” has received the most attention in psychology (Smith, 2017; Manzo and Devine-Wright, 2021), sociology (Low and Altman, 1992; Low, 2016) and anthropology (Fitch, 2014; Harun et al., 2015), among others. Place attachment studies investigate how groups and individuals can develop forms of attachment to places by dynamically fostering (place) concepts. Attachment relations can involve manifold emotional, social and cognitive factors interacting in complex manners (e.g., Lewicka, 2008, 2011). These relations can be shaped via direct experience of a place or via indirect information gained via multi-modal sources (e.g., respectively Tang et al., 2021; Merciu et al., 2022). For instance, Sydney locals and tourists can develop attachment via experiences, alone and in groups (e.g., as rugby fans), and via books, videos, social media and any other relevant media.

Though place attachment studies may abound, a dearth of formal models seems attested (cf. Turton Catherine, 2016; Inalhan et al., 2021). One exception is the “tripartite place attachment” model of Scannell and Gifford (2010, 2014, 2017). In this model, place attachment is a triadic relation between “People,” “Places” and “Processes.” In the “People” domain, the model studies whether individuals or groups develop forms of place attachment (cf. also Manzo, 2005). In the “Places” domain, the model studies the facets, i.e., features and dimensions of variation constituting place concepts (Canter, 1977, 1997, 2012). Place facets can represent social and physical properties of places as two distinct types (Uzzell et al., 2002). In the “Processes” domain, the model studies attachment relations between individuals and places via emotive, cognitive and social bonds (Brown et al., 2003). The model suggests that place attachment arises when people (e.g., local inhabitants) develop relations towards places (e.g., love for Sydney) via processes (e.g., living “there”), and via place concepts.

Other notions attaining to place have also been thoroughly investigated, such as place identity, place memory, place formation, and others falling under the “place-making,” “sense of place” rubrics (Seamon, 2018). Place identity studies, for instance, investigate how individuals can shape their identities via the places they interact with (Proshansky et al., 1983; Hay, 1998; Pretty et al., 2003; Banini and Ilovan, 2021). These studies also investigate how the physical and social features of places shape the identities of individuals and the groups they belong to (Bonaiuto et al., 1996; Twigger-Ross and Uzzell, 1996; Stedman, 2002; Clayton, 2003; Knez, 2005). For instance, Sydneysiders can define themselves as city dwellers and beach-goers because Sydney is an Australian city blessed with several beaches. In general, individuals internalise places’ features as mental facets shaping place concepts that they use to develop complex place attachment relations. Place-making is therefore an ever-going process by which individuals imbue place concepts with meaning, thus defining their “sense of place” via the facets constituting these concepts (Seamon, 2012, 2018, 2021).

As our necessarily concise summary suggests, psychological theories of place take a dual stance inherited from Geography (Cresswell, 2014). While “place” describes mind-external entities, place concepts describe internal, multi-faceted and subjective representations that individuals have of places (e.g., Marzano and Siguencia, 2016). Psychology and other cognitive disciplines usually propose model-specific terms and assumptions about place concepts (Seamon, 2018). However, they converge in assuming that place concepts reflect social and physical/geographical aspects of places via facets, and guide the formation of place attachment relations (Scannell and Gifford, 2014). Furthermore, facet theory analyses suggest that place facets can be operationalised via formal languages such as first order logic (e.g., Canter, 1977, 1997, 2012). However, they leave the development of these tools mostly underdeveloped. Psychological models thus offer formally vague models of place concepts. At the same time, they also generally gloss over linguistic matters.

3. GIS and formal ontologies of place concepts

The goal of this section is to analyse how GIS has developed formally explicit treatments of place concepts. Within this field, the development of place models has moved in parallel with the exponential growth of information in two domains. One includes on-line gazetteers and geographical databases (Abdelmoty et al., 2007; Baglioni et al., 2007; Jones et al., 2008; Winter et al., 2009; Allen et al., 2016). The other includes “volunteered geographic information” (Goodchild, 2007; Keßler et al., 2009; Southall et al., 2011; Sui and Goodchild, 2011; Derungs and Purves, 2014; Dunn, 2017). On-line, open-access gazetteers and social media (e.g., OpenStreetMap, FourSquare) exist thanks to the spontaneous (“volunteered”) information that users offer about Places (Williams et al., 2012; Janowicz et al., 2013; Gao et al., 2017; Hu et al., 2019). GIS studies build models to represent these views as expressions of individuals’ place concepts and their inter-subjective variation.

Researchers have hence developed geo-ontologies, structured databases in which platial, individual-based content is explicitly represented. Most works use variants of first order logic (Frank, 2003; Agarwal, 2005a,b; Bishr and Kuhn, 2007; Fonseca, 2008; Fonseca and Câmara, 2009; Couclelis, 2010; Vasardani and Winter, 2016). Furthermore, several proposals use “geo-atoms” as the building blocks of these ontologies (Kuhn, 2005, 2012; Goodchild et al., 2007; Winter and Freksa, 2012; Hu, 2018; Purves et al., 2019). The core properties of geo-atoms can be defined as follows. First, geo-atoms are based on objects, usually defined via crisp boundaries. Second, geo-atoms represent the locations of these objects defined via a spatio-temporal coordinate system. Third, geo-atoms represent the properties and corresponding values associated to objects and locations. The use of geo-atoms allows researchers to represent place concepts via the format in (4)–(5) (cf. Kuhn, 2012).

(4) A:<x,l,S(l(x))>

(5) A:<Sydney,l,S = {extension,number-of-districts, popularity, citizens’-opinion},S(l(Sydney))>

As (4) shows, a geo-atom A represents an object x, a spatio-temporal location l for the object, a set of properties S individuating the object, and their respective values for the object at its unique location [i.e., S(l(x))]. The location function l(x) represents a “geo-object”: an object occupying a single spatio-temporal location. Consider now (5): this geo-atom offers a compact formalisation of a possible singular place concept for Sydney. For instance, Sydney can have 5 million inhabitants and a certain number of districts. It can also be popular among tourists and be a great or awful city to live in, according to its citizens. These and other properties can represent how individuals may develop place concepts for places, and connect these concepts into complex conceptual networks (Hu, 2018; Purves et al., 2019).

Research on GIS ontologies has also focused on two sub-goals: the formalisation of place and place concepts’ properties, and of relations among places (Ballatore et al., 2014; Ballatore, 2016). For instance, Hamzei et al. (2020) formalises facets as the properties and corresponding values that allow individuals to individuate places in space and time (cf. also Entrikin, 1994, 1996, 1997; Canter, 2012). This work divides place concept facets into two macro-types: geographic and anthropocentric, i.e., affordance-centred, facets (Gibson, 1979; Egenhofer and Mark, 1995; Galton, 2010; Jonietz and Timpf, 2015). Both facet types find their justification in volunteered descriptions of Places. For instance, WeChat users can tag pictures of Sydney’s Pitt Street and describe it as a peaceful central district street, providing information on geographical (i.e., location) and anthropocentric (i.e., peacefulness) facets they associate to this street. Representational systems such as geo-atoms can therefore represent place concepts, and can also represent facets as formal properties shaping these atoms [e.g., extension in (5)].

GIS works have also introduced the notion of “place network,” which requires some motivation for its current discussion. Several works have suggested that the formal modelling of concepts also passes through the study of relations (spatial, conceptual) among Places (Montello, 1993, 2009; Golledge, 2002; Montello et al., 2003; Tenbrink and Kuhn, 2011). Recent works on place information retrieval have shown that geo-tagged sources often offer information about “what” facets individuate places, but also “where” these places can be located (Vasardani et al., 2013; Zhou et al., 2016; Chen et al., 2018; Hamzei et al., 2021). For instance, Instagram users can tag pictures of Pitt Street and Hyde Park while being in Sydney. They therefore provide information about this street and this park being “in” Sydney, and about Sydney being a place that includes other distinct places. The place concepts and models that individuals can share in discourses must represent these manifold relations (Chen et al., 2018; Maren et al., 2020).

These insights are summarised in Purves et al. (2019)’s “ontological commitment” about place concepts. Formalisations of place concepts (e.g., geo-atoms) must represent objects occupying locations and instantiating manifold facets (i.e., places); they can enter relations and participate in events (i.e., define networks). To see why this ontological commitment finds empirical justification, consider (6)–(7) and how they convey information about two places, Sydney and Brisbane.

(6) Sydney is South of Brisbane.

(7) Sydney and Brisbane always had a cultural and sportive rivalry.

The sentence in (6) suggests that Sydney and Brisbane stand in a (approximate) “South-of” spatial relation. Instead, (7) suggests that the two Australian cities are connected via a type of social relation: the “rival-of” relation. Sports teams and musical bands have participated in various events that can have motivated the growth of this rivalry over time. Individuals who offer such descriptions of these places thus also offer information about their “Sydney” and “Brisbane” concepts, and how they subjectively connect these concepts. Hence, Purves et al. (2019)’s commitment can be interpreted in this way. Place concept formalisations (e.g., geo-atoms for “Sydney,” “Brisbane”) must represent objects (e.g., the physical cities) and their properties in their locations. These concepts can enter relations (e.g., being “South of” another place), and participate in events (e.g., “being in a rivalry”). Crucially, (6)–(7) also suggest that place names and other categories (e.g., adposition South of) introduce reference to these concepts. However, place names refer to places; spatial adpositions, instead, refer to relations between places and/or locations.

4. “Place” in linguistics

The goal of this section is to assess the status of “place” notions in linguistics; we begin our analysis from Toponomastics. Most works focus on the etymology of place names, and practices of use among communities (Kadmon, 2000; Watts, 2004; Ainiala et al., 2012: Ch. 2). Studies investigating place names’ grammatical properties usually suggest that place names can include generic terms and specific terms. While Street is a generic term, Pitt in Pitt Street is a specific term (Zinkin, 1969; David, 2011; Tent and Blair, 2011; Blair and Tent, 2015, 2021; Tent, 2015; Perono Cacciafoco and Cavallaro, 2023). Some works argue that place names represent individuals’ conceptualisation of their environment (Reszegi, 2012, 2020a,b). Most works however propose that place names only introduce “proper” (i.e., pragmatic) reference conditions to mind-external places (Coates, 2006a,b, 2013, 2017; after Kripke, 1972). Hence, toponomastics studies mostly ignore place concepts and their relations to place names.

Typology has instead uncovered three key morpho-syntactic properties of place names across languages (Cablitz, 2006; Nash, 2015; Nühling et al., 2015; Rybka, 2015). First, place names only including specific terms act as bare NPs (e.g., Sydney). Place names including generic terms are phrasal compounds (e.g., Pitt Street; Schlücker and Ackermann, 2017; Schlücker, 2018, 2020). Second, place names usually refer to unique discourse entities, and thus incorporate definiteness and specificity features (Anderson, 2004, 2007). Hence, they are a highly distinctive NP sub-type across languages (Van Langendonck, 2007, 2017; Köhnlein, 2015; Van Langendonck and Van de Velde, 2016). Third, place names often combine with case markers (e.g., locative case in Finnish) and may license the omission of spatial adpositions (Stolz et al., 2017; Stolz and Warnke, 2018; Haspelmath, 2019; Stolz and Levkovych, 2020). Typological studies thus offer fine-grained grammatical analyses of place names but explain away their semantic properties, and their relation to place concepts as psychological constructs.

While toponomastics and typology are frameworks that focus on functional, social and thus mind-external uses of languages, conceptual semantics and generative syntax take a mind-internal stance. Conceptual semantics attempts to individuate the core conceptual categories underpinning the senses of linguistic units (Jackendoff, 1983, 1990, 1997, 2002, 2010; van der Zee, 2000; van der Zee and Slack, 2003). The framework suggests that adpositions (e.g., in, behind) find their senses in PLACE-functions, which map the senses of NPs, i.e., concepts for objects, to concepts for locations: “Places,” in this framework. For instance, the PP in a park, from (3), includes an adposition, in, and an NP, a park. The sense of the NP is a concept/function individuating a park in discourse, as a landmark object. The sense of in is a concept/function mapping the “park” concept to an internal location, i.e., an “in” place. Other functions (e.g., “front” for in front of) may select specific place concepts defined with respect to landmark objects. In this framework, place concepts model adpositions’ senses. Therefore, these senses are not unique, shaped by individuals’ views nor associated to place names.

Works within generative syntax built theoretical analyses on these insights. These works adopt “Place” as a label for a category projecting from spatial adpositions and case markers (e.g., in, at: Wunderlich, 1991, 1993; Koopman, 2000; Kayne, 2004). This category individuates concepts for regions defined via a landmark object (e.g., “in,” “front” regions). The emergence of the Syntactic Cartography framework introduces a refinement of this analysis (e.g., Cinque and Rizzi, 2010; Garzonio and Rossi, 2020). Cartography suggests that each morpheme in complex adpositions can project a distinct category. If we take in front of as an example, the morpheme front introduces a so-called Ax(ial)Part category, which introduces a “front” concept. The morpheme in projects the Place category, and the “place” concept associated to the “front” concept (Svenonius, 2006, 2008; Franco, 2016). The morpheme of projects a Kase category, and a relation between “front” location concept and landmark concept. We discuss the upshot of this account via (8).

(8) The man sits in front of the table.

According to this analysis, the PP in front of the table introduces a “Place” concept individuating a front location via a given table. If we take the use of this term as in geography and psychology, individuals may use PPs and sentences such as (8) for locations to which they have affective and social relations. Aside this being a problematic claim, it would entail that in front of the table could be treated as a place name for a generic location unoccupied by objects, i.e., not a “proper” place. Thus, these frameworks create wrong predictions regarding place concepts and their mapping to place names.

Formal, model-theoretic semantics offers a parallel set of theoretical issues when addressing the notion of “place.” For instance, Cresswell (1978) suggests that English adpositions (e.g., over) can denote “places” as possible destinations of moving entities, but does not define this notion. Model-theoretic formalisations of conceptual semantics propose that PLACE-functions denote unique regions in space, or Eigenspaces, via the location function loc’ [i.e., we have loc’(x) = l]; Wunderlich, 1991, 1993; Zwarts and Verkuyl, 1994). Subsequent works propose that adpositions can denote regions or vectors (e.g., respectively, Nam, 1995; Aurnague et al., 1997; Krifka, 1998; Zwarts and Winter, 2000; Aurnague, 2004; Matushansky and Zwarts, 2019). Variants of DRT offer analyses of adpositions and spatial relations (e.g., Asher and Sablayrolles, 1995; Maillat, 2001, 2003; Roßdeutscher, 2013, 2014; Haselbach and Pitteroff, 2015; Haselbach, 2017). Thus, model-theoretic works address neither place Names nor place concepts.

Formal ontology works investigating linguistic issues present a different picture. Guizzardi (2005) suggests that adpositions can express mereo-topological (i.e., spatial “part-of”) relations (cf. also Egenhofer and Mark, 1995; Smith, 1995; Guarino, 1998). Smith and Mark (1998, 2001) suggest that generic terms in place names (e.g., street) may refer to “fiat” locations. Fiat (i.e., arbitrary) locations are such because humans can make complex assumptions on the properties/facets that individuate these locations (e.g., the postulation of boundaries: Smith and Varzi, 2000). These proposals treat place as a fiat type concept (Yue, 2013). They suggest that place names (e.g., Sydney, Pitt Street) encapsulate unique place concepts (e.g., “Sydney” as a unique city in Australia). Thus, these works analyse place names and adpositions as distinct categories realising distinct concept types within a rich ontology of “Space.” However, they do not explicitly state how one can analyse place names and concepts via these distinctions.

We can now summarise the picture emerging from Sections 2–4. Psychological models of place (e.g., Scannell and Gifford, 2010) converge on two assumptions. First, place concepts are shaped via the features that define places, though these features can be subjective and internalised as facets. Second, individuals and groups can internalise relations (e.g., forms of attachment) with these concepts. Crucially, facets theory and GIS models (e.g., Purves et al., 2019) suggest that place concepts and facets can be formalised via first order logic tools: geo-ontologies, representational tools (e.g., geo-atoms), and place networks. Third, linguistic frameworks do not lend themselves to integration in this picture. Some frameworks focus on pragmatic matters, thus explaining away the semantic properties of place names (Coates, 2017; Haspelmath, 2019). Other frameworks erroneously associate place concepts to adpositions (Jackendoff, 1983; Svenonius, 2010). Furthermore, ontology-driven and model-theoretical frameworks (Guizzardi, 2005; Haselbach, 2017) do not explore place names and their relations to place concepts. Therefore, (1)–(3), (6)–(8) and a unified model that makes correct predictions about place concepts, place names and their relations are still outstanding.

5. Place and place names: a unified account

The goal of this section is to outline a unified, multi-modal model of place names and place concepts that integrates different frameworks into a single theoretical architecture of cognition. Before we proceed, we clarify which version of DRT we implement and why.

DRT is a dynamic, representational, modular theory of meaning (Kamp et al., 2011: Ch. 1; Nouwen et al., 2016; Geurts et al. 2020). Dynamic, because it offers an incremental model of discourse interpretation that captures the role of extra-linguistic and linguistic context. Representational, because it manipulates Discourse Representation Structures (DRSs), which represent meanings as mental objects that speakers process as discourse unfolds. Modular, because it assumes that the interpretation algorithm takes structures (e.g., syntactic trees) as inputs, and returns DRSs as outputs. These structures can be connected with non-linguistic structures (e.g., concepts) via formally defined mappings, while being evaluated against a discourse context.

DRT comes in dozens of variants: many of these variants offer “layered” representations of linguistic content (e.g., Maier, 2006, 2015, 2017), and psychological states (e.g., Kamp, 2021, 2022). Crucial for our concerns is the fact that DRSs can be used as cognitive Domain-general Representation Structures.

Thus, via DRT, we can simultaneously model linguistic content, i.e., the senses of place names, and non-linguistic place concepts. In so doing, we can also integrate with DRT different theories on place (e.g., facets theories, formal GIS theories of place) that propose first order logic as a formal language. Therefore, we choose this framework as our starting point for two reasons. Theory-wise, DRT allows us to use one meta-language to connect different frameworks for studying place. Data-wise, it allows us to solve recalcitrant problems involving place names and place concepts via a multi-modal implementation of anaphoric relations.

We proceed as follows. We first introduce the basic principles of DRT as a theory of meaning (Section 5.1). We show how DRT permit us to formulate domain-general representations of meaning, and connect these representations via referential (“anchor”) relations (Section 5.2). We then move to the empirical applications, which cover place names’ grammar, semantic and lexical content, and their inter-subjective use in discourse (Section 5.3).

5.1. Discourse representation theory: key notions and a semantics for place names and place concepts

DRT can be conceived as a variant of first order logic enriched with relations among discourse referents. These are logical variables used to represent entities whose identity can be defined as discourse unravels (Kibrik, 2013: Ch. 2). Referents can be individuated via conditions: properties (i.e., 1-place functions) ascribed to referents, or relations (i.e., 2-place functions) holding between referents. The set of referents representing a discourse is known as the universe of discourse (e.g., U = {x,y}); the bundle of conditions, as the condition set (e.g., S = [condn]). A DRS is minimally formed by combining a universe and a condition set individuating and connecting these referents.

DRT has a well-known graphic format, or “box notation.” In this format, upper boxes represent universes of discourse as lists. Lower boxes represent condition sets as vertical lists, based on syntactic order of interpretation. Identity relations between referents act as anaphoric relations: pair-wise relations among different referents representing the same extra-linguistic entities. We illustrate these core notions via the example in (9).

(9) A man walks in a park. He whistles. [Adapted from Kamp et al., 2011: (16)]

(10) 

The two-sentence discourse in (9) establishes that there is a man walking in a park (first sentence), and that this man is also whistling (second sentence). The DRS in (10) introduces a possible representation of the sense assigned to this discourse. A set of conditions (e.g., man’, in’) defines the properties individuating each referent, and their possible relations. Referents have default existential import: for instance, x and y in the universe of discourse stand short for ∃x, ∃y. The sense assigned to the pronoun he introduces a new referent, identified as a man [i.e., man’(z)]. It then establishes that this referent is identical to the referent that a man introduces (i.e., x), via the anaphoric relation “z = x.” The two sentences form a coherent discourse, since they describe the same man [i.e., man’(z) = man’(x) also holds]. Each sentence also introduces other conditions individuating this man in discourse e.g., walk’(x) for the first sentence, whistle’(z) for the second sentence].

The DRS in (11) also shows that NPs referring to locations may introduce distinct referents and conditions. First, the condition park’(y) individuates a referent as a park. Second, a location function loc’ maps this referent to its corresponding Eigenspace (unique location), represented via the referent t [i.e., t:loc’(y) holds: Wunderlich, 1991; Kamp et al., 2011: Ch. 4]. The condition/relation in’(x,t) holds between the location t as the landmark referent, and the walking, whistling man as another referent. The interpretation of conditions can be captured via Boolean conjunction (i.e., “⊓”). However, this assumption depends on DRT variants (Brasoveanu, 2007: Ch. 2; Brasoveanu, 2010; Brasoveanu and Dotlačil, 2020: Ch. 6). We will show that individuals may also interpret conditions via other schemas (e.g., Boolean disjunction “⊔”), depending in which context they access these representations. We expand this point and its empirical import as we proceed.

Our next step is introducing the two key assumptions by which DRT analyses proper names. First, proper names introduce the sets of conditions that uniquely individuate a referent: they act as “compressed” descriptions (Geurts, 1999; Maier, 2006, 2015, 2017; Kamp, 2015, 2021). Second, each name introduces a unique labelling condition as its sense. For instance, the condition Sydney’ stands for a different set of conditions from Melbourne’: they label distinct concepts for cities. Third, proper names and other parts of speech introduce different referent types: individuals (e.g., men), places (e.g., Sydney), and events, among others. Thus, an ontology for referents and conditions is also integral to DRT. We repeat (1) as (11) and offer its DRS in (12) to illustrate these assumptions.

(11) The plane landed in Sydney.

(12) 

We discuss the conditions in (12) from bottom to top. The conditions p:loc’(sy) and Sydney’(sy) jointly read as follows. If sy is a referent representing Sydney as an individual/object (e.g., a physical agglomerate of buildings), then p is the unique location that this city occupies. Furthermore, sy is of type d (for individuals); p is of type l (for locations). The adposition in establishes that an internal location y, also of type l, is defined with respect to Sydney as a location Haselbach, 2017: Ch. 5; and references therein. The verb landed and the definite NP the plane establish that a plane (i.e., a referent x of type d) is in a landing relation with this internal location [i.e., e:land’(x,y); plane’(x)]. The verb landed thus also introduces an event referent e. Once this verb combines with its syntactic arguments and their senses, it describes a “landing” type of event in which the plane and Sydney become “related.”1

The representation of referent types in DRT passes via superscripts in the universe of discourse (e.g., xd). Ontological distinctions can be modelled via hierarchical type theories (e.g., Asher and Lascarides, 2003; Asher and Pustejovsky, 2013; cf. also Asher, 2011). We however discuss such matters in Section 5.3.3, once we address Place concepts’ networks. At this stage, we require three types for our data: individuals d, locations l, and eventualities ev. Psychological and GIS works suggest that events play a role in the making of place (e.g., Scannell and Gifford, 2010; Purves et al., 2019; respectively). We show how this can be the case as we proceed. The uniqueness of referents can be represented via a super-script (i.e., xn = 1: cf. Kamp et al., 2011: Ch. 4; Kamp, 2015). Thus, the referents for the plane, Sydney and its corresponding place are unique, cf. (12).

The formal definitions for our discourse ontology are as follows. The set of spatial locations L does not overlap with that of individuals D and eventualities EV. The equation D ⊓ L ⊓ EV = ∅ holds: the intersection(s) of the sets of referents belonging to these types are empty sets (i.e., individuals are neither locations nor events). The equation D ⊔ L ⊔ EV=U also holds: in our minimal ontology, the universe of discourse is made up of the union set of objects, locations and eventualities. We represent location referents r as rl (with l ⊑ L, “” being the “sub-set/type of” relation: Carpenter, 1992: Ch. 2–3; Pustejovsky, 1995: Ch. 3; Asher, 2011: Ch. 2). We represent individual-type referents as xd (i.e., x ⊑ D holds); eventuality-type referents as eev (i.e., e ⊑ EV holds). Event semantics approaches abound, and implement various sub-types of eventualities (Parsons, 1990; Landman, 2000; Rothstein, 2004; Ramchand, 2010). We address this matter as we proceed.

The status of p as a place referent representing Sydney thus emerges from three properties. First, p is a unique location: the city of Sydney as a unique object occupies this location (cf. individual referent syd , n = 1). Second, the sense of the place name Sydney establishes that a unique location pl defined via a unique set of conditions (i.e., Sydney’) is under discussion. Place Names thus both label (i.e., describe) and refer to objects and the unique locations they occupy, i.e., places. Third, the unique place referent pl,n = 1 participates in two relations: a spatial relation with its internal location yl, and a landing relation with a unique plane xd ,n = 1. The landing relation, in turn, describes an event (referent) eev.

We now have a model of the senses/meanings of place names. We can exploit DRT’s machinery to define place concepts as formal objects. Next, we reconstruct the notions of facet from psychology (Section 2) and geo-atom from GIS (Section 3) as DRT-based (i.e., logic-based) notions. In (13), we repeat the geo-atom for the Sydney Place concept from (5). In (14), we offer its DRS reformulation.

(13) A:<Sydney, l, S = {extension, number-of-districts, popularity, citizens-opinion}, S(l(Sydney))>

(14) 

The DRS representing the “Sydney” place concept includes an object referent s for the city. The localising function l geo-tagging objects is represented as l(s). The set of facets individuating this place and their corresponding values are represented as conditions. For instance, the condition extension’(p’) represents Sydney’s spatial extension. The referents in this DRS belong to different types from discourse referents, because they represent our non-linguistic (e.g., visual) understanding of Place concepts. Though distinct, the corresponding ontologies are nevertheless inter-connected. We use Greek letters to represent these cognitive types: ο for objects (with ο ⊑ Ω), λ for locations (with λ ⊑ Λ), ϕ for (sums of) facets that individuate Place concepts (with ϕ ⊑ Φ). We assume that each type is disjointed from the other types/sets (i.e., Ω ⊓ Λ ⊓ Φ = ∅ holds), and that the sum of these types forms the set of types from which geo-atoms are built (i.e., Ω ⊔ Λ ⊔ Φ = Σ holds). The sub-script σ represents the type of this DRS as a spatial (and platial) representation; for practical reasons, we insert it inside the DRS.

By reformulating geo-atoms/place concepts as cognitive types of DRS, we add one assumption about how facets can be represented. We have Sϕ as a referent representing the set of facets that individuate Sydney. Such referents are known as structured referents, in DRT (Asher, 1993; Asher and Lascarides, 2003; Brasoveanu, 2007; Kamp et al., 2011: Ch. 3–4). These referents can represent (union) sets of referents or sets of conditions. For instance, plural nouns can denote (union) sets of individuals [e.g., the boys may denote the set A = ⊔{m,l} m, l being two individuals]. Contexts can be modelled as sets of conditions (i.e., structured referents) that hold in discourse [e.g., C(x) = ⊔{cond1(x), cond2(x)} holds]. In our case, the identity S(p’) = ⊔{cond’n}(p’) establishes that places can be individuated via a set of facets/conditions, descriptions of Place concepts that can become accessible in discourse.

Our novel re-formulation of place concepts as non-linguistic DRSs also offers two possible perspectives on facets. First, a unique combination of facets defines the conceptual content of a place concept: “Sydney” is shaped via a unique mental description or label (S, in (13)]. Second, the set union of these facets can be presented as a list of conditions [i.e., cond1 cond2… ⊔ condn): Sydney may be defined as beautiful, or an Australian city, or as a rugby haven, or also as a combination of all these facets. These two perspectives are equivalent: their role in DRSs and anaphoric relations is interchangeable, and thus equally connected to place names.

5.2. A multi-modal DRT architecture: connecting place concepts and place names

We now integrate different semantic (linguistic, conceptual) representations into one model of place names and place concepts. We choose Grounded DRT (e.g., Pross, 2010; Knott, 2012) for this purpose. In this variant, the flow of cognitive information is represented via three DRS layers: Sensori-Motor Structures (SMSs), External Presentation Structures (EPSs) and Internal Representation Structures (IRSs). SMSs represent perceptual information that individuals receive from objects in the world. EPSs represent mind-external objects and their relations mediated via perceptual information. IRSs build upon EMSs and SMSs and define constantly updating models of the multi-modal flow of information. Grounded DRT thus offers us a multi-modal, cognitively grounded model of how individuals can represent mind-external places as mind-internal concepts, and can use place names to discuss about these concepts.

We illustrate how this architecture works via a preliminary example. Imagine a context in which some individuals may decide to look up some information about Sydney. By consulting web-based content about this city, the individuals may temporarily access the “Sydney” place concept that the individual has memorised over time. The multi-modal representation in Figure 1 represents this information flow.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. The model shows that SMSs are activated once perceptual information is received. The precise format of this information is not crucial, for our purposes (e.g., pictures vs. direct observation). Activation of an SMS licenses the activation of an EPS. Once the perceptual stream is processed, an individual has information about Sydney as a place; thus, the Sydney place concept is activated. The two layers become connected via anchors (see main text). The use of Sydney in sentences potentially describing this concept can then activate an IRS (i.e., a discourse-specific representation structure) and anchor it to perceptual and conceptual structures. Hence, from mind-external information about Sydney as a place, an individual activates the “Sydney” place concept, which can be mentioned in discourse via the place name Sydney. The model thus assumes that cognitive processes are modular and dynamic, but also inter-connected across layers of cognition, with perceptual representations acting as “grounding levels.”

As the model shows, a directed flow of information connects the different DRS types. This flow is regulated via mappings known as anchoring relations, or anchors (Kamp et al., 2011; Ch. 6). Anchors are relations between referents belonging to different layers. They represent how the mind integrates representations across levels of comprehension by connecting their corresponding referents. Anaphoric relations are a sub-type of anchors in which referents belong to the same type and layer (e.g., xt = yt minimally holds). General anchors, instead, include functions mapping one referent from one layer, to a referent of another layer [i.e., f(xτ) = yt minimally holds; Ursini, 2011; Ursini and Acquaviva, 2019]. Anchors involve initial or “source” referents, and final or “floater” referents. We introduce the relevant definitions in (15) (cf. Pross, 2010, p. 41, definition 7).

(15) a. Given referents x, y, an anchoring relation is the duple ANCHOR < x,y>, with x a source and y a floater;

b. An anchor is:

internal if its floater is an IRS-reference marker and its source an EPS-reference marker;

external if its floater is an EPS-reference marker and its source an SMS object term;

anaphoric if its floater is an IRS-reference marker and its source an IRS-reference marker.

Crucially, if we assume that anchors connect referents across different layers, we predict that these relations can also include structured referents. Place concepts can introduce sets of facets as descriptions (e.g., F), which can then become part of anchors. The condition(s) name’ that place names carry become the internal (i.e., language-based) floaters of place concepts. This prediction can be made precise as follows. Consider a context in which we observe a touristic advertisement on-line, showing a plane landing in Sydney’s main airport. In this context, we can use (11) to minimally describe the event we perceive, and the “Sydney” place concept we entertain while watching this video. In this context, we also develop the most minimal form of cognitive attachment towards this concept: we acknowledge its existence in our mental life.

We next introduce a representational format for relations between concepts and individuals. In DRT, individuals entertaining representations can be represented via an indexing mechanism (Kamp et al., 2011: Ch. 7; Maier, 2015). If A, B represent individuals in discourse exchanging information, then A:DRS and B:DRS represent relations between these individuals and distinct DRSs that these individuals can entertain. We can now represent place attachment relations in their minimal form. A:PDRS can be taken as a shortcut for R < A:PDRS>: an individual A is attached to a concept for a Place P, represented as a DRS, via a relation R. For instance, love < A:SydneyDRS> is an attachment relation in which an individual A loves “Sydney” as a place concept. More in general, attachment relations represent the fact that individuals relate themselves to the place concepts they can use and exchange in any mental and social activity.

Figure 2 shows how our model integrates all this information.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. A multi-modal DRS for the sentence the plane landed in Sydney and its extra-linguistic context of interpretation, and as entertained by an individual A. We follow Pross (2010) in using Greek alphabet letters to represent EPS referents, and capital letters for the conditions individuating these referents. No ambiguity with types should arise, given the multi-modal/layered format of representations. Conditions in SMS-level structures display perceptual information allowing individuals to individuate entities and their possible relations (e.g., one referent looking like a plane, one looking like a city, the landing relation). We also follow Pross (2010) and use undecomposed conditions written in capital letters (e.g., PLANE) to represent this perceptual information in a compact manner. This DRS represents a distinct entity belonging to the SMS type (i.e., the relation “1 ⊑ SMS” holds). The condition CITY-AS-PLACE represents how Sydney is perceived as a place, i.e., a mind-external (complex) object occupying a location. The DRS belonging to the conceptual (i.e., EPS) layer includes the “Sydney” place concept in its extended form, but the “plane” and “land” concepts in their compressed forms. We focus only on this Place concept to better explain how anchors work. We represent place concepts as sets of facets identified with a structured referent: P is the set of facets identifying a plane concept, and S is the set of facets identifying the “Sydney” concept. We do not attempt to be exhaustive with our lists: their purpose is to hint at the complexity of concept representations, as we fully discuss in Section 5.3. We represent the fact that the DRSs belonging to the type σ of spatial (re)presentations are in turn part of the EPS (i.e., conceptual) layer via the relation σ ⊑ EPS. The relation a ⊑ IRS represents the fact that DRSs belonging to the type a (i.e., DRSs for assertions) are in turn part of the IRS layer (i.e., the discourse level). The Supplementary file offers further observations about anchors and ontological matters.

The place name Sydney refers to the place concept “Sydney,” which in turn represents individual A’s perception of Sydney as a mind-external place. This reference act passes via three anchors. Thus, ANCHOR < S(p’),Sydney’(p) > establishes that Sydney’, the sense assigned to this place name, refers to (i.e., labels) the unique facets set individuating the “Sydney” concept. ANCHOR <β,s> and ANCHOR <s,sy> establish that the tokens of these senses and concepts (i.e., the referents syd, xδ and α) are also connected. An individual A can see a video of the city of Sydney and activate a visual and conceptual referent to mentally (re)present it. The individual can then use the place name Sydney to refer to the corresponding place concept, “Sydney.” Place concept and place name can be anchored to the places that these facets describe. However, perceptual referents and SMSs must represent these entities, i.e., connect perceptual information to mind-external entities such as places, planes and so on.

One consequence of this result is that we must include eventualities as part of our ontology of Place concepts. We include the set Ε of eventualities in our Place ontology: Φ ⊔ Λ ⊔ Ε = Σ holds (Casati and Achille Varzi, 2015; Guarino and Guizzardi, 2016; Guarino et al., 2022). This formalisation captures the assumption in psychology (e.g., Seamon, 2012; Scannell and Gifford, 2017) and GIS (Purves et al., 2019) that place concepts are also defined via the events that can happen in them. Furthermore, it is consistent with recent research showing that events are distinct concept types (Zacks and Tversky, 2001; Zacks et al., 2007; Zacks and Swallow, 2007; Zacks, 2014). Our conceptual ontology for place only lacks a type for facets to reach full psychological plausibility; we defer their introduction to Section 5.3.3.

The model we have defined so far can be interpreted as follows. An individual can see images of the city of Sydney and read sentences such as (11). When this happens, the various perceptual stimuli (images, text) activate the individual’s place concept of “Sydney” via its multiple facets. The individual then connects this concept to the place name Sydney and the sentence in which this name occurs. The multi-modal Domain-general Representation Structure (DRS) in Figure 2 represents these interwoven facets by which this individual makes sense of this place in context. We must now integrate this semantic model of place names and place concepts with a novel morpho-syntactic analysis of place names.

5.3. The proposal: core applications and results

The goal of this section is to present the model’s empirical import. To maintain our discussion focused but empirically sound, we offer a multi-modal account of place names with discourse-bound applications. We start by connecting place concepts and place names (Section 5.3.1). We then offer an account of adpositions that establishes their differences with place names (Section 5.3.2). We integrate the model with a frames theory analysis of conceptual and lexical relations, thereby defining a minimal model of place conceptual networks (Section 5.3.3). We conclude by showing how can we model place attachment relations in discourse-oriented, inter-subjective models in context (5.3.3–5.3.4). From here onwards, we omit uniqueness superscripts in DRSs unless necessary, to increase readability.

5.3.1. A model of place names

We begin with a novel account of the grammatical structure of place names.2 We treat place names as coordinated phrasal compounds, as standardly assumed for (complex) proper names (Jackendoff, 2009; Koptjevskaja-Tamm, 2009, 2013; Schlücker and Ackermann, 2017; Schlücker, 2018, 2020). The phrasal status of generic terms is justified because they can also occur as common nouns (e.g., street in the street is wide) or as adjectives or other categories (e.g., blue in Blue Mountains). Specific terms are either proper names or bare common nouns, i.e., NPs (e.g., Pitt in Pitt Street; Mountains in Blue Mountains). A potentially silent head connects the two phrases, although in place names such as Isle of Wight, of can project this head. We suggest that this head is a type of “relator” connecting two NP-like elements, and thus it projects an N head (den Dikken, 2006: Ch. 4; Bauer, 2009; Scalise and Bisetto, 2009; Köhnlein, 2015).

We assume that recursive structures are also possible (cf. Romanova and Spiridonov, 2018). Place names such as New South Wales can include two generic terms, New and South, and the specific term Wales. They can also introduce multiple silent heads connecting these terms into recursively built NPs. Place names may only include specific terms and thus amount to bare NPs, e.g., Sydney. We illustrate the proposed structures in Figure 3.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. We associate the structure in (A) to Sydney and other place Names only including a “bare” NameP. For Mount Shasta and similar other names, we assume the structure in (B). The mirror structure in (C) can represent place names such as Pitt Street. We also assume that the two mirror orders are base-generated, i.e., that PlacePs and NamePs can be linearized on either “side” of an N head (cf. David, 2011; Blair and Tent, 2015, 2021; Ursini, 2016). In either case, NamePs are complement phrases of N; PlaceP, specifier phrases of this head. For place names such as New South Wales, we allow recursion of PlacePs, as (D) shows. Note that we treat New and South as projecting PlacePs: they classify the type of place concept they name according to residing hemisphere (i.e., South) and historical novelty (i.e., New). The Supplementary file contains more observations on these structures.

We use the categorial label PlaceP to underline that generic terms individuate place concepts such as mountains, cities and streets. Some generative works suggest that the category “Place” can act as a sub-type of a Classifier Phrase (e.g., Kayne, 2004; Romanova and Spiridonov, 2018). Specific terms, instead, name individuals (e.g., families, Pitt; cities as constructs, Sydney). We use the category NameP to capture this fact, treating it as a sub-type of (bare) NP (Anderson, 2004, 2007; Van Langendonck, 2007). The term “place name” thus appears as a slight misnomer. The term however encapsulates the fact that categories referring to place concepts and individual concepts combine to form place names.

Before we continue, note that we assume that bare place names, e.g., Sydney, may involve the projection of empty categories [i.e., no term projects PlaceP in (a)]. However, it is generally assumed that bare place names such as Sydney are semantically equivalent to formal counterparts including generic terms, such as city of Sydney (Blair and Tent, 2015, 2021; Perono Cacciafoco and Cavallaro, 2023: Ch. 2). In our account, both forms have the same syntactic structure, but Sydney corresponds as a reduced form of the more formal place name City of Sydney. Semantic equivalence holds because of this relation.

We can now anchor this grammatical account to a semantics for Place Names, in turn anchoring this content to place concepts. We assume that NamePs can introduce reference to any entities from which a place may receive its name (e.g., a wealthy family for Pitt). The relator N introduces a relation holding between these referents (Matushansky, 2009). We propose that this relation implicitly describes a “baptism” or naming event (Coates, 2017; Blair and Tent, 2021). We suggest that all categories denoting relations (here, N) introduce event referents that these relations describe (Landman, 2000: Ch. 8; Ramchand, 2010). We thus represent the fact that individuals may tacitly assume that a place received a name in a socially sanctioned event. The nature of this event, i.e., its etymological roots, may remain unknown to them. Nevertheless, it guides their interpretation of a place name’s sense by also establishing that a community, at some stage, bestowed this name to the place to which the name refers. Knowing the meaning of a place name thus also means knowing the existence of this baptism event.

The next step is to anchor place names as linguistic (i.e., grammatical, semantic) units to place concepts as non-linguistic units. We standardly assume that reference is defined at a phrasal level (e.g., Kamp et al., 2011: Ch. 2; Coates, 2017; Acquaviva, 2019; and references therein). We thus predict that reference is a “layered” property. Anchors among referents entail anchors among their facets. In our case, anchors among referents for place concepts and place names entail anchors between the facets and the linguistic meanings shaping these distinct units. That is, the meaning of mount in Mount Shasta refers to the bundle of facets defining a “mount” place concept.

We also predict that place names introduce three “points” of reference to conceptual structure. First, NamePs refer to the entities bestowing names to places, via the concepts associated to them (Kamp, 2015, 2022; Maier, 2017). Second, PlacePs refer to the (structured) facets describing place concepts. Third, place names as “whole” NPs refer to naming event connecting naming entity and named Place. We show the import of all these assumptions via the analysis of Pitt Street in Figure 4, and Sydney in Figure 5.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. This multi-modal representation reads as follows. The spatial DRS (typed σ) includes PT as the set of facets individuating a concept for the Pitt family. The set ST includes the facets individuating a street place concept. The relation dedicated-to’ represents the possible conceptual link between family and street concepts. Speakers may not know of the etymological roots of this Place name, but at least know that some conventionally defined naming relation holds between these concepts (cf. Coates, 2017; Perono Cacciafoco and Cavallaro, 2023: Ch. 3). There is strong evidence that naming relations come into different types and define conceptual hierarchies (e.g., Blair and Tent, 2015, 2021; Tent and Blair, 2011). Here we use dedicated-to’ as a partially descriptive label, so that readers may easily remember the role of this class of relations. The event referent e’, belonging to the conceptual type ϵ, therefore represents the naming event establishing this relation within a linguistic community. From here onwards, we omit SMS-type DRSs representing perceptual information for clarity. The Supplementary file contains more observations.

FIGURE 5
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 5. This representation of Sydney and the “Sydney” concepts acts as a (final) extension to our analysis, and reads as follows. The DRS σ includes information about the specific place type for Sydney: a city, defined via its set of (non-exhaustive) facets C. The possible relation between these facets and those individuating the specific place (i.e., S) can be a “simple” naming relation (i.e., name-of’). Crucially, the lack of an overtly realised PlaceP term in the place name entails that the “city” concept remains unexpressed: no explicit label refers to this concept, i.e., C remains unanchored. Conversely, a representation for the formal name City of Sydney would include an explicit anchor to the C concept. The Supplementary file contains some more observations.

5.3.2. Place concepts and networks: the case of adpositions

As discussed in Sections 2–3, psychology and GIS models suggest that Place concepts can enter different types of relations, thus forming “place networks” (e.g., Scannell and Gifford, 2010; Purves et al., 2019). The sentences in (1)–(3), (6)–(8) offer evidence supporting this claim. Individuals who use these sentences in discourse can describe spatial relations between Sydney and Pitt Street, and between Sydney and Brisbane. They can also express how they internalise the place concepts associated to these cities and streets. Our conceptual knowledge of places can include facets defining these places and the relations holding among these places: place networks. These relations are expressed via verbs and adpositions in discourse; thus, we need a minimal linguistic model of verbs and adpositions to account for place networks.

We begin by offering an alternative analysis of adpositions to those discussed in Section 4 (cf. Emonds, 1985; Acedo-Matellán, 2016; Matushansky and Zwarts, 2019; Ursini, 2020; Ursini and Tse, 2021). We assume that complex adpositions (e.g., in front of or South of) include a relational noun/NP (front, South). These NPs may form a phrase with a possibly silent first adposition [e.g., in and front form in front; South and “∅” form the phrase (∅ South)]. We assume that the first adposition projects a “Loc(ative)” head: it maps the object that the NP denotes onto a location. The resulting LocP(hrase) enters a relation with this NP (e.g., the house) via a relational adposition P (e.g., of in South of, in front of). The PP introduces a relation between two spatial concepts: one for the landmark object referent, one for a second location defined via this object. Our model thus predicts that LocPs, i.e., landmark and relational NPs, PPs introduce reference to matching spatial concepts. We show these predictions via the pair of PPs South of Brisbane and in front of the car in Figures 6, 7.

FIGURE 6
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 6. The PP South of Brisbane, from the sentence Sydney is South of Brisbane [i.e., (8)], is assigned the structure on the left, and the multi-modal DRS on the right. The structure shows that adpositions and the PPs they form include five potential sites for the introduction of anchors: the ground NP (here, Brisbane), the specifier PP (i.e., South forming a LocP with a silent head), and the PP as a complex phrase. A fourth site is the relational NP (i.e., South, front) as an NP embedded in the adpositional domain. The Supplementary file contains more observations. Note that we remove the individual’s index to increase readability.

FIGURE 7
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 7. The PP in front of the table, from the sentence the man sits in front of the table [i.e., (8)], is assigned the structure on the left, and the DRS on the right. The analysis confirms that adpositions introduce reference to location and reference system concepts via their embedded nominal elements (here, front). The analysis also shows that definite NPs such as the table may introduce unique referents in discourse, as we mark in the universe of the discourse DRS (i.e., td,n = 1). This uniqueness condition can determine the uniqueness of the location that this object occupies, in a manner similar to how place concepts involve unique objects and their locations. However, unlike place names, this NP does not introduce a naming event for this table. This is the case because NPs other than proper names introduce referents instantiating these concepts via different grammatical and conceptual mechanisms, such as discourse marking [(e.g., in)definiteness], but also via quantification [e.g., the indefinite a park in (3)]. In other words, while spatial adpositions can introduce relations among locations and places, place names introduce reference to one selected place. Our account correctly captures and predicts this division of labour.

As the DRSs in Figures 6, 7 show, relational NPs can introduce reference to object concepts such as (abstract) cardinal points (South) or parts of grounds (front; Tenbrink, 2011; Rybka, 2015). Once they merge with Loc heads, a LocP introduces reference to a location concept and the type of spatial reference system they represent. Thus, the “bare” NP South introduces reference to a location that is part of the polar coordinates system. In front can instead introduce reference to a location defined via the parts of an object. Once full PPs are formed via the head of and a landmark NP, the PPs introduce spatial relations defined via these reference systems. This view is consistent with standard views on the semantics of adpositions and reference systems (e.g., Levinson, 2003: Ch. 1; Levinson and Wilkins, 2006: Ch. 1; Cablitz, 2006; Palmer, 2015).

We can then show how spatial adpositions and verbs can define relations over place concepts (cf. Figure 8). To capture this fact, we offer a minimal structure for the sentence in (5). We assume that the copula projects a verb head V, and forms a “bare-bones” VP as a minimal clause (cf. Figure 8). As the layered DRS shows, Sydney and Brisbane refer to the Place concepts for these two Australian cities. Instead, South of introduces reference to a “South-of” relational concept. Other spatial relations can certainly be defined, via the content of their relational NPs (e.g., ‘inclusion’, ‘part of’: Aurnague et al., 1997; Zwarts and Winter, 2000; Haselbach, 2017: Ch. 5).

FIGURE 8
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 8. The sentence in (6), Sydney is South of Brisbane, is assigned the structure to the left and the DRS to the right. All anchors and conditions correspond to those discussed in Figures 5, 7; hence, we trust the readers to find their role clear. We assume that the copula is acts as a simple relational head establishing a form of identity between referents (cf. den Dikken, 2006: Ch. 3; and references therein). The anchor mapping the conceptual relation holding between “Sydney” and “Brisbane” as place concepts is ANCHOR <be’, R’>, i.e., the anchor establishing that a sentence (i.e., a bare-bones VP) introduces this relation and reference to the z state it represents. The conceptual relation between the “Sydney” and “Brisbane” places is expressed via this predicative sentence. It establishes that the first place, “Sydney,” lies in the (broadly) defined South region of a second place, ‘Brisbane.”

Crucially, this analysis correctly distinguishes the properties of place names from those of other NP types. For instance, we predict that the indefinite a park in (3), the definite the table in (8) do not refer to place concepts. The indefinite NP does not refer to a unique location (i.e., there can be more than one park); the definite NP refers to a unique location, but one lacking a name that establishes its status as a place. Our model can therefore account for why the place names Sydney and Pitt Street in (1)–(2) introduce reference to Places and their respective concepts, and why the PP in a park in (3) refers to a general location.

Thanks to this result, our model can also solve the theoretical problems arising in conceptual semantics and generative approaches (again, Jackendoff, 2002; Svenonius, 2010). More importantly, this view highlights the linguistic and conceptual differences between place names and adpositions (here, adpositions). Adpositions refer to locations and spatial reference systems via the category LocP: they introduce spatial relations. Place names are instead anchored to place concepts as possible arguments of spatial relations. The two categories thus have different roles and properties within grammar. This fact can be captured only by formally distinguishing the functional and lexical heads forming these categories (e.g., Loc for adpositions, Place for place names).

5.3.3. Conceptual place networks: a lexicon of place names

We can now define place concepts networks. For this purpose, however, we must extend our approach to a formal theory of hierarchies.

Various disciplines within cognitive sciences use frames as a representation format for any concepts (Barsalou, 1992a,b, 1999; Gamerschlag et al., 2014: Ch. 1; Gamerschlag et al., 2015). Frames can be recursively defined as sets of attributes and the values associated to these attributes. For instance, the concept MAMMAL can be defined via the attribute animal, which can have further attributes as its values: bear, human and several others. The attribute human can have more specific attributes as values (e.g., woman, child). Attributes can be classificatory or relational: they classify entities described via concepts, or establish relations among entities and/or concepts (e.g., Petersen, 2007; Naumann, 2013). The framework known as “Frame Semantics” models word senses via frames (Fillmore, 1982; Fellbaum, 1998; Fillmore et al., 2003; Fillmore and Baker, 2010; Busse, 2012). Word senses can involve reference to different attributes individuating concepts. As words can share attributes and/or values they encapsulate, they can also enter hierarchical (or “inheritance”) relations reflecting these relations among attributes. For instance, the attribute child is a sub-type of human attribute, which in turn is a sub-type of animal attribute.

Recall now that models of Place attachment (e.g., Scannell and Gifford, 2010) and GIS approaches (e.g., Hamzei et al., 2020) distinguish between geographical and anthropological types of facets. For this reason, we propose that the place concept “Sydney” includes the geographical facet extension’, and the anthropological facet citizens-opinion’. We can thus define a basic ontology of facets by introducing G and A as sub-types for geographical and anthropocentric facets, respectively. We assume that these sub-types form mutually exclusive sets (i.e., G ⊓ A = ∅ holds), and that they jointly form the general type of facets Φ (i.e., G ⊔ A = Φ holds). We represent these types via sub-scripts: extensiong and citizens-opiniona are typed versions of these facets. We can therefore enrich place concepts with an ontology of facets.

We can now use this ontology to model relations among place names. Hence, we can use our linguistic model to capture relations among place concepts: define place networks as a reflection of the relations that individuals internalise about places. We show why this is the case via the conceptual DRSs for “Sydney” and “Pitt Street” in Figures 9, 10. Since we have specific templates for place concepts is that we can formulate a general template for place concepts, which we offer in Figure 11.

FIGURE 9
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 9. The place concept in (A) represents facets in a compressed form. The frame-theoretic representation of the facets in (B) decompresses their hierarchical structure. The place concept for Sydney includes two geographical and two anthropological facets. The first set in the DRS corresponds to the set union of the geographical facets; the second set, to the union of anthropological facets. Assigning specific values to these facets/attributes may add a further level. For instance, Sydney includes 21 districts, so one can connect this value to the corresponding frame. Connecting edges between nodes can be read in either direction. From bottom to top, they represent hierarchical relations between facets and their (super)-types. From top to bottom, they represent relations between attributes and their values. Sydney as a place name acts as a linguistic label for this whole frame; when we use this place name, we can refer to this complex conceptual frame.

FIGURE 10
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 10. Frame-theoretic representation for the “Pitt Street” concept. Note that concepts can undergo a form of compositional facet unification (“feature unification” in frame theories: Löbner, 2014, 2021). The concept “Pitt” and the concept “Street” are represented via their structured facet referents, F and S. These concepts enter a naming relation, as they individuate two different concept types (respectively, individual and Place types). The relation dedicated-to’ represents this unification process, and also establishes that the compositional concept “Pitt Street” includes facets belonging to both concepts. The event e’ represents the naming event that sanctioned this relation between Family concept and Place concept, establishing the etymology of this name.

FIGURE 11
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 11. Singular place concept (s): general template in DRT format [i.e., (A)] and frame format [i.e., (B)]. As the template shows, geographic facets individuate the specific place referent p’ that a concept describes, and anthropocentric facets individuate a possibly distinct second referent a’. In the case of “Pitt Street,” the second referent is the aforementioned family after which the street is dedicated. In the case of “Sydney,” it is the city as the complex human artifact (and object) that is located in this place. “Place” thus becomes the relational concept that binds objects and locations, but also the manifold facets individuating these mental referents, here represented as union sets of more basic facets/conditions. Via frames we can potentially model all the semantic (i.e., conceptual and linguistic) representations of place concepts to the effect of faithfully representing individuals’ meanings for places. Our figures simply offer an overview of the possible structures emerging from these processes.

Figure 9 shows that Sydney and other bare place names can refer to complex Place concept frames and their hierarchies. Instead, Figure 10 shows that Pitt Street and other complex place names can include a certain division of labour. PlacePs seem to refer to geographical facets (e.g., a place belonging to the “street” type); NamePs, at least indirectly, to anthropological facets (e.g., the name being dedicated to a family). Once these words form a place name, their frames form the unified frame for the Place Name. Figure 11 therefore generalises this model to any place concept. It shows that place concepts involve different types of facets, which can then individuate the referents (objects, locations, individuals related to places, events) shaping these concepts. Hence, our model of place concepts can potentially capture any type of meaning (e.g., geographical, anthropological, historical) associated to places by re-interpreting DRSs as frames.

The model can also capture place networks as follows. In standard dictionary definitions, avenue, alley and street are terms referring to place types definable via various facets (e.g., spatial extension, ability to connect other places in cities; Ursini and Samo, 2022). However, avenues usually include the presence of trees, aisles and other spaces for the leisure of walkers; alleys are narrower, secondary streets. One can also consider back alleys and side alleys as possible sub-types of alleys. Roads may be streets that may stretch beyond cities, unlike streets and alleys. The terms avenue, alley, road and street can thus refer to concepts that seem related via the different facets shaping their structure. Such hierarchical relations can be modelled via the sub-type relation “⊑”: via facets, we model “avenue,” “road” and “alley” as conceptual sub-types of the “street” concept. Hence, the lexical hierarchical relations between alley, avenue, road and street reflect how individuals conceptualise different types of places and relate them via their increasingly descriptive content. We show the emerging set of hierarchical relations from this example in Figure 12.

FIGURE 12
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 12. In this hierarchy, we represent concepts and the facets potentially distinguishing these concepts. We propose that “street” minimally includes the facets extension’ and connector’: a street is a place with an extension and connecting other places. We then propose that the concepts “avenue,” “alley” and “road” include at least one more facet distinguishing one concept from the other place concepts. For instance, avenues usually have trees, so the “avenue” concept includes the facet trees’. Alleys are often narrow, so the concept “alley” includes the facet narrow’. Roads can sometimes connect different cities, so the concept “road” includes the facet cities’. These three concepts are thus sub-ordinate to the “street” concept, because their condition sets include more facets and therefore individuate smaller sub-sets of places (e.g., “avenue” ⊑ “street” holds because ⊔{ext’, conn’, trees’} ⊑ ⊔{extension’, connector’} also holds). The Supplementary file contains more details on Figures 912.

We now move to lexical relations among place names. Adpositions provide our next test (e.g., in, South of, in front of), because they can reflect the spatial, relational organisation of place concepts. For instance, English in introduces a relation in which one place’s location can be included in a second place’s location [e.g., Pitt Street being in Sydney, cf. (2)]. Instead, South of or in front of introduce relations between two place concepts via a third location and the reference system it introduces [e.g., Sydney being South of Brisbane, cf. (6)]. Consider thus Figures 13, 14.

FIGURE 13
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 13. The model shows that “Sydney,” “Brisbane,” “Adelaide” and “Melbourne” are singular place concepts that are part of the “Australia” concept, and thus indirectly part of the “Country” concept. This concept is a sub-type of the “place” singular concept (not represented in the figure for space reasons). Other sub-types we introduce in our toy model are “New Zealand” and “UK,” as sub-types of the “Country” concept. The “South-of” spatial relation is a concept that can have multiple realisations or states (e.g., s1 for the relation between “Sydney” and “Brisbane”). However, while “Sydney” and “Brisbane” are hierarchically linked to “Australia” (i.e., both singular place concepts are related to the “Australia” place concept), their spatial relation is mediated via a different concept and domain. For this purpose, we add nodes explicitly representing the states associated to each relation as a concept (cf. Landman, 1991: Ch. 6; Landman, 2000: Ch. 8; Ganter and Wille, 1998: Ch. 4; Krifka, 1998; for discussion on this technique).

FIGURE 14
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 14. The hierarchy shows that “Pitt Street,” “Hyde Park” and “Opera House,” among other place concepts, can be defined as sub-types of the “Sydney” concept: in this case, parts of this city that are also distinct (sub-)types of urban place concepts. We can add the concepts explicitly representing these relations, to model the emergence of the “in” relational concept. Thus, s1 represents in abbreviated form the state described by relation s: in’(Pitt-Street, Sydney). This relation represents the fact that the place concept “Pitt Street” and the place concept “Sydney” are connected via the relational spatial concept “in,” and thus describe a spatial state s1. This relation, in turn, considerably abbreviates the relation that the sentence Pitt Street is in Sydney in (2) denotes. The set of states that one can define between “Sydney” and the other place concepts via this ‘inclusion’ relation forms part of the denotation of the “in” concept in our toy model: other “in” states can be defined accordingly, via relations between “Sydney” and other Places being “in” this city (e.g., “Hyde Park,” “Opera House”).

As Figure 13 shows, we can represent “Sydney” and “Brisbane” as Place concepts that are part of a network including “Australia” and “Country” as super-types. At a coarse-grained level of conceptual resolution, we represent the fact that these two cities are located in Australia, a country and therefore a more abstract place concept. Once we individuate these concepts, we can connect them to the “South of” relational concept by individuating the state (i.e., eventuality) in which the first city is located to the South of the second city. We represent the different natures of this relation via a graphical choice. Hyponym relations can be read in a top-down fashion; spatial relations, in a bottom-up fashion. We operate a similar analysis in Figure 14, which shows how Place concepts can be related via the “in” concept. We can show that “Sydney” as a place concept can also enter in mereo-topological relations with other place concepts (e.g., “Opera House”), mirroring spatial relations among places.

Let us summarise our achievements so far. Our model of place names can capture their key grammatical and lexical properties. These properties reflect the ontological properties of the place concepts to which these names are connected. Place concepts can be organised into networks according to the category-internal relations among their facets. These relations may be realised as lexical relations among place terms (e.g., street, avenue and so on). These relations can also be realised as lexical relations (e.g., ‘South-of”) among place names, mediated via verbs and adpositions. We have therefore defined an ontology for place networks, as proposed in the psychology (e.g., Scannell and Gifford, 2010) and GIS literature (e.g., Purves et al., 2019).

5.3.4. Multiple place representations and shared models: prolegomena to place in discourse

In this section we show how our model can be used to represent inter-subjective place concepts in discourse. As discussed in Sections 2–3, individuals can have subtly different place concepts and forms of attachment representing one or more places. Such inter-subjective differences can emerge in how individuals discuss places in social media and other geo-tagged formats (e.g., Chen et al., 2018; Hamzei et al., 2020; Maren et al., 2020). In general, individuals can develop different though co-existing perspectives in discourse and compare these perspectives as a discourse unfolds (Heller and Brown-Schmidt, 2023; and references therein). In our specific case, individuals can discuss and present personal views/concepts of place and attachment relations. Individuals can simultaneously entertain inter-subjective concepts of these places, representing how other individuals conceive these places. One example involving “Sydney” as a place is as follows (cf. Figure 15 for the model).

FIGURE 15
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 15. We use simplified DRSs for “Sydney,” to maintain our discussion compact (cf. Figure 5). The Supplementary file contains a more thorough discussion of the formal properties of this context. Horizontal edges are akin to “vicarious anchors” (Kamp, 2021, 2022) or “perspective relations” (Heller and Brown-Schmidt, 2023). In Figure 15, they represent the fact that individuals may connect their own DRSs for places to DRSs that other individuals may have about the same places under discussion. See the Supplementary file for more information.

Imagine three individuals that discuss their opinions of Sydney in an on-line conversation on TripAdvisor about “Sydney, capital of New South Wales.” As the conversation unfolds, the individuals A, B, D discover that they have subtly different views of this city. We offer an example of a conversation approximating such an exchange of opinions in (16).

(16) A: I really find Sydney a beautiful

    city, one I can call home.

  B: Yes, Sydney is now also my home,

    though I was not born here.

  D: Beautiful, yes, but my home

    remains Auckland I guess.

These opinions can share some factual knowledge, but each individual may have different feelings and thus forms of attachment towards this city. Individual B considers Sydney home (cf. the facet/condition home’); individual D considers Sydney beautiful (cf. the facet beautiful’) but not home; individual A considers Sydney home and a beautiful city. Given the title of the thread, all three individuals may also tacitly acknowledge that Sydney is the capital of the Australian state of New South Wales (i.e., the facet capital’). All three individuals also indirectly agree that their respective “Sydney” concepts differ and are related to the city of Sydney, though some common aspects (i.e., facets) certainly can be defined.

We can model this shared opinion as the minimal discourse context C’. This context may represent a part of the on-line discussion, e.g., a post in which all three individuals acknowledge their common views on Sydney (i.e., the facets name-of’, capital’). Individuals can then consider each of their respective “Sydney” concepts as intermediate, possibly partial views on this city and the facets defining it. The horizontal edges connecting these individual relations (e.g., A:DRS to D:DRS) represent this form of inter-subjective understanding of the “Sydney” concept. A third emerging possibility is that individuals can jointly develop a “Sydney” concept encompassing all alternative views (i.e., C’). We can represent place concepts that individuals share as a group as the (set) union of their subjective views on a Place.

These logical possibilities correspond to different aspects of this mini-discourse and its context (cf. Heller and Brown-Schmidt, 2023, p. 4). In this context, each individual contributes distinct though partially overlapping views (i.e., concepts) of Sydney, and discusses how these views can differ from one another. They can agree that Sydney is the city they are talking about and, tacitly, the capital of New South Wales. They also display different forms of attachment to this city and concept, since they are willing to share and compare their views in this discussion.

Our model can now capture place attachment relations and their flexibility across individuals and groups (Scannell and Gifford, 2010). This result is achieved by showing that these relations are shaped by how individuals can define “senses of place” (i.e., conceptual content via facets) in their subjective representations of place concepts (i.e., our DRSs). Therefore, this analysis has three important consequences. First, it allows us to fully reconstruct place as a subjective, individual-oriented concept (e.g., Cresswell, 2014). Second, it permits us to show that inter-subjective place concepts can be defined in volunteered information contexts (e.g., Sui and Goodchild, 2011; Chen et al., 2018). Third, it also captures the fact that groups of individuals can share models that do not necessarily involve identical place concepts (Mohammed et al., 2010; Maren et al., 2020; Mocnik, 2022; Heller and Brown-Schmidt, 2023).

6. Discussion

We believe that our proposal offers key solutions to the recalcitrant problems outlined in the introduction. We expose these solutions via five discussion points.

First, we offer a novel morpho-syntactic account of place names. This account solves the problem of “category conflation” emerging in previous generative models (e.g., Svenonius, 2010). We model place names as corresponding to either phrasal compounds or bare NPs (cf. Köhnlein, 2015; Schlücker and Ackermann, 2017). This analysis hinges on identifying two morpho-syntactic categories: Place as a classifier category, Name as a content category. These categories form place names as an NP sub-type, distinct from other NPs (e.g., indefinite a park) and from PPs (e.g., in a park). We then embed our novel proposal in current formal (generative) treatments of proper names and NPs (e.g., Anderson, 2007; Acquaviva, 2019). As a welcome result, we can account increasingly complex places names (e.g., New South Wales, Pitt Street and City of Sydney), but also “bare” place names (e.g., Sydney). This is the case because we offer a generative, recursive and empirically justified morpho-syntactic analysis of place names.

Second, we offer a novel semantic account of place names. This account solves the problem of place names’ content being reduced to their referential properties (e.g., Coates, 2017). We use a multi-modal DRT analysis to achieve this result (cf. Pross, 2010). We assign a semantic interpretation to place names that captures their descriptive content and referential potential, via DRT’s treatment of proper names (Kamp, 2015; Maier, 2017). According to this interpretation, place names have senses that allow individuals to refer to places via the rich descriptive content they associate to these places. We also show that place names as NPs introduce reference to the baptism events in which a place receives its name (Kamp, 2022). We thus formally reconstruct accounts that address how individuals associate place names to rich senses (e.g., Blair and Tent, 2021; Perono Cacciafoco and Cavallaro, 2023). More importantly, we can capture the compositional contribution of the categories forming place names (e.g., Pitt, Street in Pitt Street). We also reconcile descriptive and referential theories of proper names under one multi-modal DRT model (cf. Kamp et al., 2011; Kamp, 2022).

Third, we develop a formal treatment of lexical relations among place names that reflects places’ conceptual relations (cf. Reszegi, 2020a,b). This account solves the problem of offering a full-fledged treatment of place networks as conceptual/semantic relations among place names and the place concepts they reflect (cf. Purves et al., 2019). We achieve this result by extending our approach with a frame semantics analysis of facets and place concepts (e.g., Löbner, 2014, 2021). We show that place names and terms (e.g., alley and street) can enter hierarchical types of relations in conceptual networks. We thus connect standard insights from lexical semantics (e.g., Cruse, 2000; Hanks, 2013) with novel results in GIS (e.g., Purves et al., 2019; Ursini and Samo, 2022). We also reconstruct a view of place names implemented in gazetteers as nodes of complex networks (e.g., Hill, 2006: Ch. 4; Hu, 2018). Overall, we sketch an initial formal model of the lexicon of place names (Reszegi, 2020a,b). Hence, we account why and how place names can refer to places, their facets and their relations.

Fourth, we solve the problem of having a full-fledged and cognitively plausible linguistic theory of place names. We model place concepts as domain-general DRSs: enriched versions of the geo-atoms found in GIS frameworks (e.g., Kuhn, 2012; Hu, 2018). We then offer a formal treatment of place concepts that is consistent with their analysis in geography and psychology (e.g., Cresswell, 2014; Manzo and Devine-Wright, 2021). We achieve this result by modelling facets, the building blocks of place concepts (e.g., Canter, 2012; Hamzei et al., 2020), as conditions forming conceptual DRSs. We then connect facets to a rich ontology underpinning psychological models (e.g., Scannell and Gifford, 2014; Seamon, 2018) and GIS formal models (e.g., Purves et al., 2019; Hamzei et al., 2020). We thus reconcile linguistic analyses of place names with non-linguistic analyses of place as a general concept with manifold declinations (e.g., “city,” “street,” ‘Sydney” and so on).

Fifth, our model achieves a considerable degree of inter-operativity. It connects linguistics, psychology and GIS via the notion of place, thus reaching a theoretical desideratum (e.g., Ballatore, 2016). This is a consequence of DRT integrating apparently opposite (e.g., cognitivist and formalist) perspectives (cf. Hamm et al., 2006; Pross, 2010; Maier, 2017). The model can also achieve a degree of inter-operativity with cognitivist models of communication (e.g., Heller and Brown-Schmidt, 2023; cf. also Maren et al., 2020; Mocnik, 2022). This is the case because our model also uses reference relations and multi-modal representations as the central tools to represent cognitive con tent. Considerations are however offered in the Supplementary file, due to length requirements.

7. Conclusion

The goal of this paper has been to propose a linguistic model of place names (e.g., Sydney) integrated with a conceptual model of place (“Sydney”). We have shown that such an account is possible once we offer a formal account of place names’ morpho-syntactic and semantic properties. Our account models place names as a sub-type of NPs involving rich descriptive content that can refer to the subjective or inter-subjective place concepts that individuals entertain in discourse. Therefore, our account can solve the recalcitrant problems illustrated via (1)–(3), (6)–(8), and (16). We obtain this result by introducing DRT as a multi-modal theory of mental content and as a variant of first order logic that is compatible with other frameworks. We then build a full-fledged linguistic and psychological model of place names and place concepts on this framework. Overall, we suggest that formal linguistics can offer key inter-disciplinary insights and tools to platial research (cf. again Tenbrink, 2020). This can be the case, however, insofar as linguistic analyses of place names maintain inter-operativity as a clear-cut research goal.

The account also invites the observation that other problems now become tractable (e.g., formal, cross-linguistic analyses of place names, cf. Köhnlein, 2015), though still outstanding. The approach also obtains at least two interesting secondary results. First, we may have the prolegomena of a novel model of adpositions and their senses, fully compatible with our model of place names (cf. also Ursini, 2020; Ursini and Tse, 2021). Second, the model also appears compatible with recent approaches to place names based on construction grammar (e.g., Leino, 2007, 2011) and cognitive linguistics (e.g., Sjöblom, 2011; Reszegi, 2022). Though these frameworks use different assumptions from the generative and DRT assumptions we implemented in this paper, they also propose rich representational analyses of place names. Third, our model may be consistent with multi-modal models of memory (e.g., Tulving, 2002; Cowan, 2005; Bush et al., 2014). In such models, memorising information about events and individuals occurs by tracing their “place” in the world, via dedicated sets of so-called “place cells.”

Our model thus seems potentially extendable to domains and frameworks that may offer further views on place names and places. However, we leave the exploration of these extensions for further research.

Data availability statement

The raw data supporting the conclusions of this article will be made available by the authors, without undue reservation.

Author contributions

F-AU collected the literature (psychology, linguistics, GIS), developed the DRT and frames parts of the article, and wrote the article. YZ collected the literature (psychology, linguistics), developed the frames parts of the article (visual notation, diagrams, figures), and edited the article. All authors contributed to the article and approved the submitted version.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Supplementary material

The Supplementary material for this article can be found online at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1237422/full#supplementary-material

Footnotes

1. ^We omit representing temporal information, e.g., the sense associated to the simple past landed in (11).

2. ^We gloss over place names including morphologically complex forms (e.g., Man-chester); length requirements prevent us from addressing these classes. See however Köhnlein (2015); Ursini (2016); Perono Cacciafoco and Cavallaro (2023: Ch. 3) for discussion.

References

Abdelmoty, A., Smart, P., and Jones, C. (2007). “Building place ontologies for the semantic web: issues and approaches” in Proceedings of the 4th ACM workshop on geographical information retrieval, ACM. eds. R. Purves and C. Jones (New York: Association for Computing Machinery), 7–12.

Google Scholar

Acedo-Matellán, Víctor. (2016). The Morphosyntax of transitions: A case study in Latin and other languages. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Acquaviva, P. (2019). Two studies on the internal syntax of complex names. Ital. J. Linguist. 31, 3–36. doi: 10.26346/1120-2726-137

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Agarwal, P. (2005a). “‘Sense of place’ as a place indicator: establishing ‘sense of place’ as a cognitive operator for semantics in place-based ontologies” in Conference on spatial information theory (COSIT) 2005. eds. A. Cohn and D. Mark (Berlin: Springer-Verlag), 96–114.

Google Scholar

Agarwal, P. (2005b). Topological operators for ontological distinctions: disambiguating the geographic concepts of place, region and neighbourhood. Spat. Cogn. Comput. 5, 69–88. doi: 10.1207/s15427633scc0501_3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Agnew, J. A. (1993). “Representing space: space, scale and culture in social science” in Place/Culture/Representation. eds. J. Duncan and D. Ley (London, UK: Routledge), 251–271.

Google Scholar

Agnew, J. A. (2011). “Space and place” in Handbook of geographical knowledge. eds. J. Agnew and D. Livingstone (Riverside, CA: Sage Publications), 316–330.

Google Scholar

Agnew, John, and Duncan, James (2015). The power of place: Bringing together geographical and sociological imaginations. London, UK: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Ainiala, Terhi, Saarelma, Minna, and Sjöblom, Paula. (2012). Names in focus: An introduction to Finnish onomastics. Helsinki: Finnish literature Society.

Google Scholar

Allen, C., Hervey, T., Kuhn, W., Lafia, S., Phillips, D. W., and Vahedi, B. (2016). “Exploring the notion of spatial lenses” in Geographic information science. eds. J. Miller, D. O’Sullivan, and N. Wiegand (Berlin: Springer), 259–274.

Google Scholar

Anderson, J. (2004). On the grammatical status of names. Language 80, 435–474. doi: 10.1353/lan.2004.0108

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Anderson, John. (2007). The grammar of names. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Asher, Nicholas. (1993). Reference to abstract objects in discourse. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Google Scholar

Asher, Nicholas. (2011). Lexical meaning in context: A web of words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Asher, Nicholas, and Lascarides, Alex. (2003). Logics of conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Asher, N., and Pustejovsky, J. (2013). “A type composition logic for generative lexicon” in Advances in generative lexicon theory. eds. J. Pustejovsky, P. Bouillon, H. Isahara, K. Kanzaki, and C. Lee (Dordrecht: Springer), 39–68.

Google Scholar

Asher, N., and Sablayrolles, P. (1995). A typology and discourse semantics for motion verbs and spatial PPs in French. J. Semant. 12, 163–209. doi: 10.1093/jos/12.2.163

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aurnague, Michel. (2004). Les Structures de l’Espace Linguistique: Regards croisés sur quelques constructions spatiales du basque et du français. Leuven/Paris: Peeters.

Google Scholar

Aurnague, M., Vieu, L., and Borillo, A. (1997). “Représentation formelle des concepts spatiaux dans la langue” in Langage et Cognition Spatiale. ed. M. Denis (Paris: Masson), 69–102.

Google Scholar

Baglioni, M., Masserotti, M. V., Renso, C., and Spinsanti, L. (2007). “Building geospatial ontologies from geographical databases” in International conference on GeoSpatialSematics (GeoS 2007). eds. F. Fonseca, M. A. Rodriguez, and S. Levashkin (Heidelberg: Springer), 195–209.

Google Scholar

Ballatore, A. (2016). “Prolegomena for an ontology of place” in Advancing geographic information science. eds. H. Onsrud and W. Kuhn (Needham, MA, USA: GSDI Association Press), 91–103.

Google Scholar

Ballatore, A., Bertolotto, M., and Wilson, D. (2014). Linking geographic vocabularies through WordNet. Ann. GIS 20, 73–84. doi: 10.1080/19475683.2014.904440

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Banini, T., and Ilovan, O.-R. (2021). “Introduction: dealing with territorial/place identity representations” in Representing place and territorial identities in Europe. eds. T. Banini and O.-R. Ilovan (Berlin: Springer), 1–19.

Google Scholar

Barsalou, L. W. (1992a). Cognitive psychology. An overview for cognitive scientists. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

Google Scholar

Barsalou, L. W. (1992b). “Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields” in Frames, fields, and contrasts: New essays in semantic and lexical organization. eds. A. Lehrer and E. Kittay (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 21–74.

Google Scholar

Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behav. Brain Sci. 22, 577–660. doi: 10.1017/s0140525x99002149

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bauer, L. (2009). “Typology of compounds” in The Oxford handbook of compounding. eds. R. Lieber and P. Štekauer (New York: Oxford University Press), 343–356.

Google Scholar

Bishr, M., and Kuhn, W. (2007). “Geospatial information bottom-up: a matter of trust and semantics” in The European information society: Leading the way with geo-information. eds. S. Fabrikant and M. Wachowicz (Berlin: Springer), 365–387.

Google Scholar

Blair, David, and Tent, Jan. (2015). Feature terms for Australian Toponymy. ANPS technical proposal. No. 2. New South Wales: Placenames Australia.

Google Scholar

Blair, D., and Tent, J. (2021). A revised typology of place names. Names 69, 1–15. doi: 10.5195/names.2021.2260

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bonaiuto, M., Breakwell, G., and Cano, I. (1996). Identity processes and environmental threat: the effects of nationalism and local identity upon perception of beach pollution. J. Community Appl. Soc. Psychol. 6, 157–175. doi: 10.1002/(SICI)1099-1298(199608)6:3<157::AID-CASP367>3.0.CO;2-W

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brasoveanu, Adrian. (2007). Structured nominal and modal reference. Rutgers University Dissertation.

Google Scholar

Brasoveanu, A. (2010). Structured anaphora to quantifier domains. Inf. Comput. 208, 450–473. doi: 10.1016/j.ic.2008.10.007

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Brasoveanu, Adrian, and Dotlačil, Jakub. (2020). Computational cognitive modelling and linguistic theory. Berlin: Springer.

Google Scholar

Brown, B., Perkins, D. D., and Brown, G. (2003). Place attachment in a revitalizing neighborhood: individual and block levels of analysis. J. Environ. Psychol. 23, 259–271. doi: 10.1016/S0272-4944(02)00117-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Buscaldi, David. (2011). Toponym disambiguation in natural language processing. University of Valencia Dissertation.

Google Scholar

Bush, D., Barry, C., and Burgess, N. (2014). What do grid cells contribute to place cell firing? Trends Neurosci. 37, 136–145. doi: 10.1016/j.tins.2013.12.003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Busse, Dietrich. (2012). Frame-Semantik: ein Kompendium. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

Google Scholar

Cablitz, Gabriele H. (2006). Marquesan: A grammar of space. Trends in 344 linguistics 169. Berlin; New York: Mouton de Gruyter

Google Scholar

Canter, D. (1977). The psychology of place. London: The Architectural Press: Architectural Press.

Google Scholar

Canter, D. (1997). “The facets of place” in Toward the integration of theory, methods, research, and utilization. eds. G. T. Moore and R. W. Marans (Boston, MA: Springer US), 109–147.

Google Scholar

Canter, D. (2012). Facet theory: Approaches to social research. New York: Springer Science & Business Media.

Google Scholar

Carey, Susan. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Carpenter, Bob. (1992). The logic of typed feature structures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Casati, R., and Achille Varzi, C. (2015). “Events” in The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2015 ed.). ed. E. N. Zalta (Stanford, CA: Meta-physics Research Lab, Stanford University)

Google Scholar

Chen, H., Vasardani, M., and Winter, S. (2018). Georeferencing places from collective human descriptions using place graphs. J. Spatial Inform. Sci. 17, 31–62. doi: 10.5311/JOSIS.2018.17.417

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cinque, Guglielmo, and Rizzi, Luigi (Eds.). (2010). Mapping spatial PPs. The cartography of syntactic structures, vol. 6. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Clayton, S. (2003). “Environmental identity: conceptual and operational definition” in Identity and the natural environment: The psychological significance of nature. eds. S. Clayton and S. Opotow (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 45–65.

Google Scholar

Coates, R. (2006a). Properhood. Language 82, 356–382. doi: 10.1353/lan.2006.0084

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Coates, R. (2006b). “Names” in A history of the English language. eds. R. M. Hogg and D. Denison (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 312–351.

Google Scholar

Coates, R. (2013). “Place-names and linguistics” in Perceptions of place: Twenty-first-century interpretations of English place-name studies. eds. J. Carroll and D. Parsons (Nottingham: English Place-Name Society), 129–161.

Google Scholar

Coates, R. (2017). The meaning of names: a defence of the pragmatic theory of properhood (TPTP) addressed to Van Langendonck, Anderson, Colman and McClure. Onoma 52, 7–26. doi: 10.34158/ONOMA.52/2017/1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Couclelis, H. (1992). “Location, place, region, and space” in Geography’s inner worlds. Pervasive themes in contemporary American geography. eds. R. F. Abler, M. G. Marcus, and J. G. Olson (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press), 216–233.

Google Scholar

Couclelis, H. (2010). Ontologies of geographic information. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 24, 1785–1809. doi: 10.1080/13658816.2010.484392

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cowan, Nelson. (2005). Working memory capacity. Hove: Psychology Press.

Google Scholar

Cresswell, M. J. (1978). Prepositions and points of view. Linguist. Philos. 2, 1–41. doi: 10.1007/BF00365129

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cresswell, Tim. (2014). Place: An introduction, 2nd edition. London: Wiley Blackwell.

Google Scholar

Cruse, Alan D. (2000). Meaning in language. An introduction to semantics and pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

David, J. (2011). Commemorative place names – their specifity and problems. Names 4, 214–224. doi: 10.1179/002777311X13082331190074

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Davies, C. (2013). “Reading geography between the lines: extracting local place knowledge from text” in International conference on spatial information theory. eds. T. Tenbrink, J. Stell, A. Galton, and Z. Wood (Berlin: Springer), 320–337.

Google Scholar

den Dikken, Marcel. (2006). Relators and linkers: The syntax of predication, predicate inversion, and copulas. Cambridge, MA. The MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Derungs, C., and Purves, R. (2014). From text to landscape: locating, identifying and mapping the use of landscape features in a Swiss alpine corpus. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 28, 1272–1293. doi: 10.1080/13658816.2013.772184

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dunn, S. (2017). Praxes of the human and the digital: spatial humanities and the digitization of place. Geo Human. 3, 88–107. doi: 10.1080/2373566X.2016.1245107

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Egenhofer, M. J., and Mark, D. (1995). “Naive geography” in Spatial information theory. eds. A. Frank and W. Kuhn, vol. 988 (Berlin: Springer), 1–15.

Google Scholar

Emonds, Joseph. (1985). A unified theory of syntactic categories. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.

Google Scholar

Entrikin, J. N. (1994). Place and region. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 18, 227–233. doi: 10.1177/030913259401800209

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Entrikin, J. N. (1996). Place and region 2. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 20, 215–221. doi: 10.1177/030913259602000206

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Entrikin, J. N. (1997). Place and region 3. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 21, 263–268. doi: 10.1191/030913297677390879

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fellbaum, Christiane (Ed.). (1998). WordNet: An electronic lexical database. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Fillmore, C. J. (1982). “Frame semantics” in Linguistic Society of Korea (Ed.), linguistics in the morning calm (Seoul: Hanshin Publishing), 111–137.

Google Scholar

Fillmore, C. J., and Baker, C. (2010). “A frames approach to semantic analysis” in The Oxford handbook of linguistic analysis. eds. B. Heine and H. Narrog (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 313–340.

Google Scholar

Fillmore, C. J., Johnson, C. R., and Petruck, M. R. L. (2003). Background to frame net. Int. J. Lexicogr. 16, 235–250. doi: 10.1093/ijl/16.3.235

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fitch, J. (2014). “Place attachment” in The encyclopedia of cross-cultural psychology. ed. K. D. Keith (London: John Wiley), 698–706.

Google Scholar

Fonseca, F. (2008). “The geospatial semantic web” in Encyclopedia of geographic information science. eds. S. Shekhar and H. Xiong (Berlin: Springer), 367–376.

Google Scholar

Fonseca, F., and Câmara, G. (2009). “Geo-Ontologies” in The GIS manual. ed. M. Madden (Bethesda, MR: ASPRS), 157–165.

Google Scholar

Franco, L. (2016). Axial parts, phi-features and degrammaticalization: the case of Italian presso/pressi in diachrony. Trans. Philol. Soc. 114, 149–170. doi: 10.1111/1467-968X.12067

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Frank, A. U. (2003). “Ontology for spatio-temporal databases” in Spatio-Temporal Databases. Lecture Notes in Computer Science. eds. T. K. Sellis, et al., vol. 2520 (Berlin: Springer), 9–77.

Google Scholar

Galton, Antony. (2010). The formalities of affordance. In Mehul Bhatt, Hans Guesgen and Shyamanta Hazarika (editors), Spatio-temporal dynamics, proceedings of workshop 21, 19th European conference on artificial intelligence, 1–6.

Google Scholar

Gamerschlag, Thomas, Gerland, Doris, Osswald, Rainer, and Petersen, Wiebke (Eds.). (2014). Frames and concept types. Applications in language and philosophy. Heidelberg: Springer.

Google Scholar

Gamerschlag, Thomas, Gerland, Doris, Osswald, Rainer, and Petersen, Wiebke (Eds.). (2015). Meaning, frames, and conceptual representation. Düsseldorf: Düsseldorf University Press.

Google Scholar

Ganter, Bernhard, and Wille, Rudolf. (1998). Formal concept analysis: Mathematical foundations. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

Google Scholar

Gao, S., Li, L., Li, W., Janowicz, K., and Zhang, Y. (2017). Constructing gazetteers from volunteered big geo-data based on Hadoop. Comput. Environ. Urban. Syst. 61, 172–186.

Google Scholar

Garzonio, Jacopo, and Rossi, Silvia (Eds.). (2020). Variation in P. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Geurts, Bart. (1999). Presuppositions and pronouns. Oxford: Elsevier.

Google Scholar

Geurts, B., Beaver, D. I., and Maier, E. (2020). “Discourse representation theory” in The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. ed. E. N. Zalta (Stanford, CA: Metaphysics Research Lab, Philosophy Department, Stanford University)

Google Scholar

Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

Google Scholar

Golledge, R. G. (2002). The nature of geographic knowledge. Ann. Assoc. Am. Geogr. 92, 1–14. doi: 10.1111/1467-8306.00276

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Goodchild, M. F. (2007). Citizens as sensors: the world of volunteered geography. Geo J. 69, 211–221. doi: 10.1007/s10708-007-9111-y

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Goodchild, M. F., Yuan, M., and Cova, T. (2007). Towards a general theory of geographic representation in GIS. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 21, 239–260. doi: 10.1080/13658810600965271

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Guarino, N. (1998). “Formal ontology and information systems” in Formal ontology in information systems, proceedings of the international conference on formal ontology and information systems (FOIS). ed. N. Guarino (Amsterdam: IOS Press), 3–15.

Google Scholar

Guarino, N., Baratella, R., and Guizzardi, G. (2022). Events, their names and their synchronic structure. Appl. Ontol. 14, 1–35. doi: 10.3233/AO-220261

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Guarino, N., and Guizzardi, G. (2016). “Relationships and events: towards a general theory of reification and truthmaking” in 15th conference of the Italian Association for Artificial Intelligence (AI*IA). eds. G. Adorni, S. Cagnoni, and M. G. M. Maratea (Berlin: Springer), 237–249.

Google Scholar

Guizzardi, Giancarlo. (2005). Ontological foundations for structural conceptual models. Enschede: Telematics Instituut.

Google Scholar

Hamm, F., Kamp, H., and van Lambalgen, M. (2006). There is no opposition between formal and cognitive semantics. Theor. Linguist. 32, 1–40. doi: 10.1515/TL.2006.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hamzei, E., Winter, S., and Tomko, M. (2020). Place facets: a systematic literature review. Spat. Cogn. Comput. 20, 33–81. doi: 10.80/13875868.2019.1688332

Google Scholar

Hamzei, E., Winter, S., and Tomko, M. (2021). Templates of generic geographic information for answering where-questions. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 36, 188–214. doi: 10.1080/13658816.2020.1869977

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hanks, Patrick. (2013). Lexical analysis: Norms and exploitations. Cambridge: the MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Harun, N. Z., Mansor, M., and Said, I. (2015). Place rootedness suggesting the loss and survival of historical public spaces. Procedia Environ. Sci. 28, 528–537. doi: 10.1016/j.proenv.2015.07.063

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Harve, D. (1994). The social construction of space and time: a relational theory. Geo. Rev. Japan Ser. B 67, 126–135. doi: 10.4157/grj1984b.67.126

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Haselbach, Boris. (2017). Ps at the interfaces: On the syntax, semantics and morphology of spatial prepositions in German. University of Stuttgart dissertation.

Google Scholar

Haselbach, B., and Pitteroff, M. (2015). A morphological case approach to PPs. Linguist. Berichte 244, 427–462.

Google Scholar

Haspelmath, M. (2019). Differential place marking and differential object marking. Lang. Typol. Univ. 72, 313–334. doi: 10.1515/stuf-2019-0013

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hay, R. B. (1998). Sense of place in developmental context. J. Environ. Psychol. 18, 5–29.

Google Scholar

Heller, D., and Brown-Schmidt, S. (2023). The multiple perspectives theory of mental states in communication. Cogn. Sci. 47, 1–32. doi: 10.1111/cog.s13322

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hill, Linda. (2006). Georeferencing: The geographic associations of information. Cambridge, MA: the MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Hollenstein, L., and Purves, R. S. (2010). Exploring place through user-generated content: using Flickr tags to describe city cores. J. Spatial Inform. Sci. 1, 21–48. doi: 10.5311/JOSIS.2010.1.3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hu, Y. (2018). “Geospatial semantics” in Comprehensive geographic information systems. eds. B. Huang, T. J. Cova, and M.-H. Tsou, et al., vol. 1 (Oxford: Elsevier), 80–94.

Google Scholar

Hu, Y., Deng, C., and Zhou, Z. (2019). A semantic and sentiment analysis on online neighbourhood reviews for understanding the perceptions of people toward their living environments. Ann. Am. Assoc. Geogr. 109, 1052–1073. doi: 10.1080/24694452.2018.1535886

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Inalhan, G., Yang, E., and Weber, C. (2021). “Place attachment theory” in A handbook of theories on designing alignment between people and the office environment. eds. I. R. A. Meulenbroek and V. Daniuska (London: Routledge), 6–21.

Google Scholar

Jackendoff, Ray. (1983). Semantics and cognition. Cambridge, MA, USA: The MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Jackendoff, Ray. (1990). Semantic structures. Cambridge, MA, USA: The MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Jackendoff, Ray. (1997). The architecture of the language faculty. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Jackendoff, Ray, (2002). Foundations of language: Brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford. Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Jackendoff, R. (2009). “Compounding in the parallel architecture and conceptual semantics” in The Oxford handbook of compounding. eds. R. Lieber and P. Štekauer (Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press), 105–128.

Google Scholar

Jackendoff, Ray. (2010). Meaning and the lexicon: The parallel architecture 1975–2010. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Janowicz, K., Scheider, S., and Adams, B. (2013). “A geo-semantics flyby” in Reasoning web. Semantic Technologies for Intelligent Data Access. Reasoning web 2013. eds. R. Sebastian, G. Gottlob, H. I. Ian, and F. Frank van Harmelen, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 8067 (Berlin: Springer), 230–250.

Google Scholar

Jones, C., Purves, R., Clough, P., and Joho, H. (2008). Modelling vague places with knowledge from the web. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 22, 1045–1065. doi: 10.1080/13658810701850547

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jonietz, D., and Timpf, S. (2015). On the relevance of Gibson’s affordance concept for geographical information science (GISc). Cogn. Process. 16, 265–269. doi: 10.1007/s10339-015-0719-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kadmon, Naftali. (2000). Toponymy: The Lore, Laws and Language of geographical names. New York: Vantage Press.

Google Scholar

Kamp, H. (2015). Using proper names as intermediaries between labelled entity representations. Erkenntnis 80, 263–312. doi: 10.1007/s10670-014-9701-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kamp, H. (2021). “Sharing real and fictional reference” in The language of fiction. eds. E. Maier and A. Stokke (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 51–87.

Google Scholar

Kamp, H. (2022). The links of causal chains. Theoria 88, 296–325. doi: 10.1111/theo.12381

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kamp, H., van Genabith, J., and Reyle, U. (2011). “Discourse representation theory” in Handbook of philosophical logic. eds. D. Gabbay and F. Gunthner, vol. 15 (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 125–394.

Google Scholar

Kayne, R. (2004). “Here and there” in Lexique Syntaxe, et Lexique-Grammaire/Syntax, Lexis, & Lexicon-Grammar: Papers in Honor of Maurice Gross. eds. C. Leclére, E. Laporte, M. Piot, and M. Silberztein (Amsterdam: John Benjamins), 253–275.

Google Scholar

Keßler, C., Krzysztof Janowicz, K., and Bishr, M. (2009). “An agenda for the next generation gazetteer: geographic information contribution and retrieval” in Proceedings of the 17th ACM SIGSPATIAL international conference on advances in geographic information systems. eds. O. Wolfson, D. Agrawal, and C.-T. Lu (New York, NJ: Association for Computing Machinery), 91–100.

Google Scholar

Kibrik, Andrej. (2013). Reference in discourse. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Knez, I. (2005). Attachment and identity as related to a place and its perceived climate. J. Environ. Psychol. 25, 207–218. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2005.03.003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Knott, Alistair. (2012). Sensori motor cognition and natural language syntax. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Köhnlein, B. (2015). The morphological structure of complex place names: the case of Dutch. J. Comp. German. Linguist. 18, 183–212. doi: 10.1007/s10828-015-9075-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Koopman, H. (2000). “Prepositions, postpositions, circumpositions and particles: the structure of Dutch PPs” in The syntax of specifiers and heads. ed. H. Koopman (London: Routledge), 204–260.

Google Scholar

Koptjevskaja-Tamm, M. (2009). Proper-name compounds in Swedish between syntax and lexicon. Ital. J. Linguist. 21, 119–148.

Google Scholar

Koptjevskaja-Tamm, M. (2013). “A Mozart sonata and the Palme murder: the structure and uses of proper-name compounds in Swedish” in Morphosyntactic categories and the expression of possession. eds. K. Kersti Börjars, D. Denison, and A. Scott (Amsterdam, Philadelphia: John Benjamins), 253–290.

Google Scholar

Krifka, M. (1998). “The origins of telicity” in Events and grammar. ed. S. Rothstein (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 197–235.

Google Scholar

Kripke, S. (1972). “Naming and necessity” in Semantics of natural language. eds. D. Davidson and G. Harman (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing), 253–354.

Google Scholar

Kuhn, W. (2005). Geospatial semantics: why, of what, and how? J. Data Sem. III 3534, 1–24. doi: 10.1007/11496168_1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kuhn, Werner. (2012). Core concepts of spatial information for transdisciplinary research. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 26 2267–2276. ttps://doi.org/10.1080/13658816.2012.722637

Google Scholar

Landman, Fred. (1991). Structures for semantics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Google Scholar

Landman, Fred. (2000). Events and plurality: The Jerusalem lectures. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Google Scholar

Laurence, S., and Margolis, E. (1999). “Concepts and cognitive science” in Concepts: Core readings. eds. E. Margolis and S. Laurence (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press), 3–82.

Google Scholar

Leino, A. (2007). “Construction grammar in onomastics: the case of Finnish Hydronyms” in I nomi nel tempo e nello spazio: Atti del XXIII congress Internazionale di Scienze Onomastiche. eds. D. Bremer, M. Bani, and F. Belli, Pisa 28 Agosto–4 Settembre, vol. 2005 (Edizioni ETS: Pisa), 297–309.

Google Scholar

Leino, A. (2011). Place-names as constructions. Onoma 41, 215–235.

Google Scholar

Levinson, Stephen C. (2003). Space in language and cognition: Explorations in cognitive diversity. Language, culture, and cognition 5. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Levinson, Stephen C., and Wilkins, David. (Eds.). (2006). Grammars of space: Explorations in cognitive diversity. Language, culture, and cognition 6. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Lewicka, M. (2008). Place attachment, place identity, and place memory: restoring the forgotten city past. J. Environ. Psychol. 28, 209–231. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2008.02.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lewicka, M. (2011). Place attachment: how far have we come in the last 40 years? J. Environ. Psychol. 31, 207–230. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2010.10.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Löbner, S. (2014). “Evidence for frames from natural language” in Frames and concept types. Applications in language and philosophy. eds. G. Thomas, D. Gerland, R. Osswald, and W. Petersen (Heidelberg: Springer), 23–68.

Google Scholar

Löbner, S. (2021). Frames at the Interface of language and cognition. Ann. Rev. Linguist. 7, 261–284. doi: 10.1146/annurev-linguistics-042920-030620

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Low, Setha. (2016). Spatializing culture: The ethnography of space and place. Sydney: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Low, S. M., and Altman, I. (1992). “Place attachment: a conceptual inquiry” in Place attachment. eds. I. Altman and S. M. Low (New York: Plenum Press), 1–12.

Google Scholar

Maier, Emar. (2006). Belief in context: Towards a unified semantics of de re and de se attitude reports. Ph.D. Dissertation. Radboud University Nijmegen.

Google Scholar

Maier, E. (2015). Reference, binding, and presupposition: three perspectives on the semantics of proper names. Erkenntnis 80, 313–333. doi: 10.1007/s10670-014-9702-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maier, E. (2017). Fictional names in Psychologistic semantics. Theor. Linguist. 43, 1–45. doi: 10.1515/tl-2017-0001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maillat, Didier. (2001). Directional PPs and reference frames in DRT. In proceedings of the International Association for Computational Linguistics 2001 Conference, 1–8. Toulouse: Université de Toulouse-Le Mirail.

Google Scholar

Maillat, Didier. (2003). The semantics and pragmatics of directionals: A case study in English and French. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Oxford.

Google Scholar

Malpas, Jeff. (2018). Place and experience: A philosophical topography. Sydney: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Manzo, L. C. (2005). For better or worse: exploring multiple dimensions of place meaning. J. Environ. Psychol. 25, 67–86. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2005.01.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Manzo, Lynne C., and Devine-Wright, Patrick (Eds.). (2021). Place attachment: Advances in theory, methods and applications, 2nd edition. New York. Routledge.

Google Scholar

Maren, Mayer, Heck, Daniel, and Mocnik, Franz-Benjamin. (2020). Shared mental models as a psychological explanation for converging mental representations of place – the example of open street map. In Franz-Benjamin Mocnik & René Westerholt (eds.), Proceedings of the 2nd international symposium on PLATIAL information science (PLATIAL’19), 43–50.

Google Scholar

Margolis, E., and Laurence, S. (2007). The ontology of concepts abstract objects or mental representations? Noûs 41, 561–593. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0068.2007.00663.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Marzano, G., and Siguencia, L. O. (2016). “The turning point of the place identity” in proceedings of the 19th IPSAPA/ISPALEM international scientific conference Napoli. eds. L. C. Piccinini, T. F. M. Chang, M. Taverna, and L. Iseppi (Udine: IPSAPA/IPSALEM), 43–51.

Google Scholar

Matushansky, O. (2009). On the linguistic complexity of proper names. Linguist. Philos. 31, 573–627. doi: 10.1007/s10988-008-9050-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Matushansky, O., and Zwarts, J. (2019). “Tops and bottoms: axial nominals as weak definites” in proceedings of the 36th west coast conference on formal linguistics. eds. R. Stockwell, M. O’Leary, Z. Xu, and Z. L. Zhou (Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press), 270–280.

Google Scholar

Merciu, F.-C., Olaru, M., and Merciu, G.-L. (2022). Place attachment during territorial development challenges. J. Settlements Spat. Plan. SI, 5–22. doi: 10.24193/JSSPSI.02.PATDC

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mocnik, F.-B. (2022). Putting geographical information science in place–towards theories of Platial information and Platial information systems. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 46, 798–828. doi: 10.1177/03091325221074023

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mohammed, S., Ferzandi, L., Lori,, and Hamilton, K. (2010). Metaphor no more: a 15-year review of the team mental model construct. J. Manag. 36, 876–910. doi: 10.1177/0149206309356804

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Montello, D. R. (1993). “Scale and multiple psychologies of space” in Spatial information theory a theoretical basis for GIS. COSIT 1993. Lecture notes in computer science, vol 716. eds. A. Frank and I. Campari (Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer), 312–321.

Google Scholar

Montello, D. R. (2009). Cognitive research in GIScience: recent achievements and future prospects. Geogr. Compass 3, 1824–1840. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-8198.2009.00273.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Montello, D. R., Goodchild, M. F., Gottsegen, J., and Fohl, P. (2003). Where’s downtown? Behavioral methods for determining referents of vague spatial queries. Spat. Cogn. Comput. 3, 185–204. doi: 10.1080/13875868.2003.9683761

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nam, Senghuo. (1995). The semantics of locative prepositional phrases in English. Ph.D. Dissertation, UCLA

Google Scholar

Nash, J. (2015). Is Toponymy necessary? Stud. Lang. 39, 230–235. doi: 10.1075/sl.39.1.08nas

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Naumann, R. (2013). “An outline of a dynamic theory of frames” in Logic, language and computation: Tbi LLC 2011. eds. G. Bezhanishvili, S. Löbner, V. Marra, and F. Richter (Berlin: Springer), 26–30.

Google Scholar

Nouwen, R., Brasoveanu, A., van Eijck, J., and Visser, A. (2016). “Dynamic semantics” in The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. ed. E. N. Zalta (Stanford, CA: Metaphysics Research Lab, Philosophy Department, Stanford University)

Google Scholar

Nühling, Damaris, Fahlbusch, Fabian, and Heuser, Rita. (2015). Namen: Eine Einführung in die Onomastik. Tubingen: Narr Verlag.

Google Scholar

Palmer, Bill. (2015). Topography in language: absolute frame of reference and the topographic correspondence hypothesis. In Rik BusserDe and Randy J. LaPolla (eds.), Language structure and environment: Social, cultural, and natural factors, 179–226. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

Google Scholar

Parsons, Terence. (1990). Events in the semantics of English. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Perono Cacciafoco, F., and Cavallaro, F. (2023). Place names: Approaches and perspectives in toponymy and toponomastics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Petersen, W. (2007). Representation of concepts as frames. Baltic Int. Yearbook: Cogn. Logic Commun. 2, 151–170. doi: 10.1515/9783110720129-003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pretty, G. H., Chipuer, H., and Bramston, P. (2003). Sense of place amongst adolescents and adults in two rural Australian towns: the discriminating features of place attachment, sense of community and place dependence in relation to place identity. J. Environ. Psychol. 23, 273–287. doi: 10.1016/S0272-4944(02)00079-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Proshansky, H. M., Fabian, A., and Kaminoff, R. (1983). Place-identity. J. Environ. Psychol. 3, 57–83. doi: 10.1016/S0272-4944(83)80021-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pross, Tillman. (2010). Grounded discourse representation theory towards a semantics-pragmatics Interface for human-machine collaboration. Ph.D. Dissertation. Karlsruhe University.

Google Scholar

Purves, R., Winter, S., and Kuhn, W. (2019). Places in information science. J. Assoc. Inf. Sci. Technol. 70, 1173–1182. doi: 10.1002/asi.24194

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pustejovsky, James. (1995). The generative lexicon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Ramchand, Gillian Catriona. (2010). Verb meaning and the lexicon: A first phase syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Relph, Edward. (1976). Place and Placelessness. London: Pion.

Google Scholar

Reszegi, K. (2012). Cognitive approaches to Hungarian toponymy. Onoma 47, 367–379. doi: 10.2143/ONO.47.0.3085153

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Reszegi, K. (2020a). “Name–culture –– identity. The semantic structure of names” in Naming, identity and tourism. eds. L. Caiazzo, R. Coates, and M. Azaryahu (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing), 154–167.

Google Scholar

Reszegi, K. (2020b). Toponyms and spatial representations. Onomastica 64, 23–40. doi: 10.17651/ONOMAST.64.4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Reszegi, K. (2022). “Cognitive approach in onomastics” in Kognitív Szemléletű Névtudományi Vizsgálatok (Debrecen: Debrecen University Press), 211–226.

Google Scholar

Romanova, Eugenia, and Spiridonov, Dmitry V.. (2018). Syntactic features of proper names: The generativist approach (es) to Properhood. Вопросы ономастики [onomastics questions] 15(3).7–35.

Google Scholar

Roßdeutscher, A. (2013). “A syntax-semantics interface for verbs with p-elements” in Sub-lexical investigations: German particles, prefixes and prepositions. ed. A. Roßdeutscher (Stuttgart: Online Publikationsverbund der Universität Stuttgart), 1–57.

Google Scholar

Roßdeutscher, A. (2014). “When roots license and when they respect semantico-syntactic structure in verbs” in The syntax of roots and the roots of syntax. eds. A. Alexiadou, H. Borer, and F. Schäfer (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 282–309.

Google Scholar

Rothstein, Susan. (2004). Structuring events. London: Wiley Blackwell.

Google Scholar

Rybka, Konrad. (2015). The linguistic encoding of landscape in Lokono. Ph.D. Dissertation, Raboud University Nijmegen.

Google Scholar

Scalise, S., and Bisetto, A. (2009). “The classification of compounds” in The Oxford handbook of compounding. eds. R. Lieber and P. Štekauer (New York: Oxford University Press), 34–53.

Google Scholar

Scannell, L., and Gifford, R. (2010). The relations between natural and civic place attachment and pro-environmental behavior. J. Environ. Psychol. 30, 289–297. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2010.01.010

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Scannell, L., and Gifford, R. (2014). “The psychology of place attachment” in Robert. Gifford (ed.), environmental psychology: Principles and practice. 5th ed (Victoria: Optimal Books), 272–300.

Google Scholar

Scannell, L., and Gifford, R. (2017). The experienced psychological benefits of place attachment. J. Environ. Psychol. 51, 256–269. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2017.04.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schlücker, B. (2018). “Genitives and proper name compounds in German” in Germanic genitives. eds. B. Schlücker, T. Ackermann, H. J. Simon, and C. Zimmer (Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins), 275–299.

Google Scholar

Schlücker, B. (2020). Von Donaustrom zu Donauwelle. Die Entwicklung der Eigennamenkomposition von 1600-1900. Zeitschrift für Germanistische Linguistik 48, 238–268. doi: 10.1515/zgl-2020-2002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schlücker, B., and Ackermann, T. (2017). The morphosyntax of proper names: an overview. Folia Linguist. 51, 309–339. doi: 10.1515/flin-2017-0011

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seamon, David. (1979). A geography of the lifeworld. London, UK: Croom Helm.

Google Scholar

Seamon, D. (2012). “Place, place identity and phenomenology” in The role of place identity in the perception, understanding, and Design of Built Environments. eds. H. Kasakin and F. Bernardo (Sharja: Bentham Books), 3–21.

Google Scholar

Seamon, David. (2018). Life takes place: Phenomenology, lifeworlds and place-making. London: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Seamon, D. (2021). “Place attachment as phenomenology” in Advancements in place attachment theory. eds. L. C. Manzo and P. Devine-Wright. 2nd ed (New York: Routledge), 2–21.

Google Scholar

Sjöblom, P. (2011). A cognitive approach to the semantics of proper names. Onoma 41, 63–82. doi: 10.2143/ONO.41.0.2119611

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, B. (1995). Formal ontology, common sense and cognitive science. Int. J. Hum. Comput. Stud. 43, 646–667. doi: 10.1006/ijhc.1995.1067

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, Jonathan S. (ed.) (2017). Explorations in place attachment. London: Routledge.

Google Scholar

Smith, B., and Mark, D. (1998). “Ontology and geographic kinds” in Proceedings, international symposium on spatial data handling. eds. T. Poiker and N. Chrisman (Canada: Vancouver), 308–320.

Google Scholar

Smith, B., and Mark, D. (2001). Geographical categories: an ontological investigation. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 15, 591–612. doi: 10.1080/13658810110061199

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, B., and Varzi, A. (2000). Fiat and bona fide boundaries. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 60, 401–420. doi: 10.2307/2653492

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Southall, H., Mostern, R., and Berman, L. (2011). On historical gazetteers. Int. J. Human. Arts Comp. 5, 127–145. doi: 10.3366/ijhac.2011.0028)

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stedman, R. C. (2002). Toward a social psychology of place. Predicting behavior from place-based cognitions, attitude, and identity. Environ. Behav. 34, 561–581. doi: 10.1177/0013916502034005001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stolz, T., and Levkovych, N. (2020). “Grammatical versus onymic classifiers: first thoughts about a potentially interesting topic” in Aspects of the grammar of names. Empirical case studies and theoretical topics. eds. N. Levkovych and J. Nintermann (Munich: LINCOM Europa), 140–165.

Google Scholar

Stolz, T., Levkovych, N., and Urdze, A. (2017). When zero is just enough in a support of a special toponymic grammar in Maltese. Folia Linguist. 51, 453–482. doi: 10.1515/flin-2017-0016

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stolz, T., and Warnke, I. (2018). “Comparative colonial toponomastics: evidence from German and Dutch colonial place-names” in Sonstige Namen: Stiefkinder der Onomastik. eds. R. Heuser and M. Schmuck (Boston: De Gruyter), 65–90.

Google Scholar

Sui, D. Z., and Goodchild, M. F. (2011). The convergence of GIS and social media: challenges for GIScience. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 25, 1737–1748. doi: 10.1080/13658816.2011.604636

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Svenonius, P. (2006). The emergence of axial parts. Nordlyd 33, 49–77. doi: 10.7557/12.85

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Svenonius, P. (2008). “Projections of P” in Syntax and semantics of spatial P. eds. A. Asbury, J. Dotlačil, B. Gehrke, and R. Nouwen (Amsterdam, The Netherlands: John Benjamins), 63–84.

Google Scholar

Svenonius, P. (2010). “Spatial P in English” in The cartography of syntactic structures. eds. G. Cinque and L. Rizzi, vol. 6 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 127–160.

Google Scholar

Tang, V., Acedo, A., and Painho, M. (2021). Sense of place and the city: the case of non-native residents in Lisbon. J. Spatial Inform. Sci. 23, 125–155. doi: 10.5311/JOSIS.2021.23.165

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tenbrink, T. (2011). Reference frames of space and time in language. J. Pragmat. 43, 704–722. doi: 10.1016/j.pragma.2010.06.020

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tenbrink, Thora. (2020). The language of place: towards an agenda for linguistic platial cognition research. In R. Westerholt & F.-B. Mocnik. (eds.), Proceedings of the 2nd international symposium on PLATIAL information science (PLATIAL’19), 5–12.

Google Scholar

Tenbrink, T., and Kuhn, W. (2011). “A model of spatial reference frames in language” in Spatial information theory. eds. M. Egenhofer, N. A. Giudice, R. Moratz, and M. Worboys (Berlin: Springer), 371–390.

Google Scholar

Tent, J. (2015). Approaches to research in Toponymy. Names 63, 65–74. doi: 10.1179/0027773814Z.000000000103

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tent, J., and Blair, D. (2011). Motivations for naming. The development of a Toponymic typology for Australian Placenames. Names 59, 67–89. doi: 10.1179/002777311X12976826704000

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Thrift, N. (1999). “Steps to an ecology of place” in Human geography today. eds. D. Doreen Massey, J. Allen, and P. Sarre (Cambridge: Polity), 295–322.

Google Scholar

Tuan, Y. F. (1977). Space and place: The perspective of experience, Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

Google Scholar

Tuan, Y. F. (1979). “Space and place: humanistic perspective” in Philosophy in geography. eds. S. Gale and G. Olsson (Dordrecht: Reidel), 387–427.

Google Scholar

Tuan, Y. F. (1990). Topophilia: A study of environmental perceptions, attitudes, and values, New York: Columbia University Press.

Google Scholar

Tulving, E. (2002). Episodic memory: from mind to brain. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 53, 1–25. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.53.100901.135114

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Turton Catherine, J. (2016). Defining residential place attachment and exploring its contribution to community and personal environmental actions. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Surrey.

Google Scholar

Twigger-Ross, C. L., and Uzzell, D. L. (1996). Place and identity processes. J. Environ. Psychol. 25, 207–218.

Google Scholar

Ursini, F.-A. (2011). Space and the vision-language interface: a model-theoretic approach. Biolinguistics 5, 170–225. doi: 10.5964/bioling.8847

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ursini, F.-A. (2016). “On the structure of toponyms” in Word-formation across languages. eds. L. Kortellessy, P. Stekauer, and S. Valera (Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing), 375–393.

Google Scholar

Ursini, F.-A. (2020). General location across languages: on the division of labour between functional and lexical items in spatial categories. Linguist. Rev. 37, 495–542. doi: 10.1515/tlr-2020-2053

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ursini, F.-A., and Acquaviva, P. (2019). Nouns for visual objects: a hypothesis of the vision-language Interface. Lang. Sci. 72, 50–70. doi: 10.1016/j.langsci.2019.01.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ursini, F.-A., and Samo, G. (2022). Names for urban places and conceptual taxonomies: the view from Italian. Spat. Cogn. Comput. 22, 264–292. doi: 10.1080/13875868.2021.1954186

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ursini, F.-A., and Tse, K. (2021). On region prepositions: the view from French. Can. J. Linguist. 61, 31–59. doi: 10.1017/cnj.2020.35

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Uzzell, D., Pol, E., and Badenas, D. (2002). Place identification, social cohesion, and environmental sustainability. Environ. Behav. 34, 26–53. doi: 10.1177/0013916502034001003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

van der Zee, Emile. (2000). Why we can talk about bulging barrels and spinning spirals: curvature representation in the lexical interface. In Emile Zeevan der and Urpo Nikanne (Eds.), Cognitive interfaces: Constraints on linking cognitive information, 143–184. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

van der Zee, Emile, and Slack, Jon. (eds.) (2003). Representing direction in language and space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Langendonck, WillyVan. (2007). Theory and typology of proper names. Mouton de Gruyter: Berlin New York.

Google Scholar

Langendonck, WillyVan. (2017). A dichotomy in the diachronic structure of family names. In Proceedings of the fourth international conference on onomastics: Name and naming sacred and profane, 45–50. Baia Mare, Romania: Technical University of Cluj-Napoca.

Google Scholar

Langendonck, WillyVan, and Van de Velde, Mark. (2016). Names and grammar. In Carole Hough (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of names and naming, 17–38. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Vasardani, M., and Winter, S. (2016). “Place properties” in Advancing geographic information science. eds. H. J. Onsrud and W. Kuhn (Needham, MA: GSDI Association Press, United States of America), 243–254.

Google Scholar

Vasardani, M., Winter, S., and Richter, K.-F. (2013). Locating place names from place descriptions. Int. J. Geogr. Inf. Sci. 27, 2509–2532. doi: 10.1080/13658816.2013.785550

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Watts, Victor. (2004). The Cambridge dictionary of English place-names: Based on the collections of the English place-name society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Williams, M., Kuhn, W., and Painho, M. (2012). The influence of landscape variation on landform categorization. J. Spatial Inform. Sci. 5, 51–73. doi: 10.5311/JOSIS.2012.5.107

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Winter, S., and Freksa, C. (2012). Approaching the notion of place by contrast. J. Spatial Inform. Sci. 5, 31–50. doi: 10.5311/JOSIS.2012.5.90

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Winter, S., Kuhn, W., and Antonio Krüger, A. (2009). Guest editorial: does place have a place in geographic information science? Spat. Cogn. Comput. 9, 171–173. doi: 10.1080/13875860903144675

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wunderlich, D. (1991). How do prepositional phrases fit into compositional syntax and semantics? Linguistics 29, 591–621.

Google Scholar

Wunderlich, D. (1993). On German “um”: semantic and conceptual aspects. Linguistics 31, 111–134. doi: 10.1515/ling.1993.31.1.111

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Yue, P. (2013). “Geospatial semantic web” in Semantic web-based intelligent geospatial web services 17–20. ed. P. Yue (New York: Springer)

Google Scholar

Zacks, Jeffrey. (2014). Flicker: Your brain on movies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Zacks, J. M., Speer, N. K., Swallow, K. M., Braver, T. S., and Reynolds, J. R. (2007). Event perception: a mind/brain perspective. Psychol. Bull. 133, 273–293. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.133.2.273

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zacks, J. M., and Swallow, K. M. (2007). Event Segmentation. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 16, 80–84. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8721.2007.00480.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zacks, J. M., and Tversky, B. (2001). Event structure in perception and conception. Psychol. Bull. 127, 3–21. doi: 10.1037//0033-2909.127.1.3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zhang, W., and Gelernter, J. (2014). Geocoding location expressions in twitter messages: a preference learning method. J. Spatial Inform. Sci. 9, 47–70. doi: 10.5311/JOSIS.2014.9.170

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zhou, S., Winter, S., Vasardani, M., and Zhou, S. (2016). Place descriptions by landmarks. J. Spat. Sci. 62, 47–67. doi: 10.1080/14498596.2016.1196623

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zinkin, V. (1969). The syntax of place-names. Names 17, 181–198. doi: 10.1179/nam.1969.17.3.181

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zwarts, J., and Verkuyl, H. (1994). An algebra of conceptual structure; an investigation into Jackendoff's conceptual semantics. Linguist. Philos. 17, 1–28. doi: 10.1007/BF00985039

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zwarts, J., and Winter, Y. (2000). Vector space semantics: a model–theoretic analysis of locative prepositions. J. Log. Lang. Inf. 9, 169–211. doi: 10.1023/A:1008384416604

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: place, place concepts, place names, place models, discourse representation theory, anchoring relations, formal ontologies

Citation: Ursini F-A and Zhang YS (2023) Place and place names: a unified model. Front. Psychol. 14:1237422. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1237422

Received: 09 June 2023; Accepted: 18 August 2023;
Published: 08 September 2023.

Edited by:

Huili Wang, Dalian University of Technology, China

Reviewed by:

Francesco Perono Cacciafoco, Xi'an Jiaotong-Liverpool University, China
Katalin Reszegi, University of Debrecen, Hungary

Copyright © 2023 Ursini and Zhang. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Yue Sara Zhang, yingzhimeng8866@163.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.