Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 22 June 2023
Sec. Consciousness Research
This article is part of the Research Topic Psychedelic Humanities View all 21 articles

Commentary: Not in the drug, not in the brain: causality in psychedelic experiences from an enactive perspective

  • 1Center for Research, Innovation and Creation, Temuco Catholic University, Temuco, Chile
  • 2Faculty of Religious Sciences and Philosophy, Temuco Catholic University, Temuco, Chile

A Commentary on
Not in the drug, not in the brain: causality in psychedelic experiences from an enactive perspective

by Meling, D., and Scheidegger, M. (2023). Front. Psychol. 14:1100058. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1100058

Introduction

I welcome with great enthusiasm Meling and Scheidegger's (2023; henceforth “M&S”) timely contribution to advance an enactive approach to psychedelic therapy, especially to the complex causality involved. Their two main research questions concerned: (i) the causal interaction between the psychedelic molecule and brain activity; and (ii) the causal interaction between brain activity and the psychedelic experience. While I largely agree with and celebrate much of what is proposed by M&S, especially their employment of key enactive concepts to advance our understanding of the first research question, in the following, I will present some worries regarding their answers to the second. Although I agree that there is probably a two-way reciprocal relationship between neural activity and experience, I have several points of contention regarding M&S's proposal. My hope is to stimulate discussion on M&S's important contribution, and to help advance a much-needed enactive science of psychedelics.

Brain activity and psychedelic experience: dynamic co-emergence and circular causality

A concept that figures prominently in M&S's account of the relationship between brain activity and the psychedelic experience is dynamic co-emergence (henceforth “DCE”). A first worry is that DCE applies to the relationship between autonomous wholes and their parts (Thompson, 2007), but it is not clear that this mereological relationship holds for consciousness and brain activity. Arguably, the parts of a given psychedelic experience taken as a whole during certain time intervals (e.g., the experience of being dissolved into a cosmic unity), are phenomenal parts (e.g., feeling united to something greater, one's sense of self being disrupted, accompanying visual images, sounds, bodily sensations, thoughts, etc.), rather than local neural activity. Additionally, regarding the latter (i.e., neural parts), the corresponding whole is more plausibly a neural whole, i.e., a global brain activity such as interhemispheric synchronic gamma oscillations, rather than the experience itself.

A second issue is that M&S's treatment of DCE suggests that it is equivalent to circular causality, characterizing both in terms of global-to-local and local-to-global determination. However, they are related but distinct notions. While DCE is meant to describe the reciprocal, constitutive relationship between parts and wholes in autonomous systems (Thompson, 2007), circular causality characterizes the reciprocal but causal relationship between them (Haken, 1983; Kelso, 2021). While the difference between constitution and causation is a matter of ongoing debate (Aizawa, 2014; Kirchhoff, 2015), at least for a matter of theoretical clarity and to guide future research, they should be more clearly differentiated.

Third, I worry that the notion of DCE is currently too obscure to incentivize further psychedelic research from an enactive perspective. In contrast to circular causality, it is not obvious what DCE really amounts to. Thompson writes that “in an autonomous system… parts do not exist in advance, prior to the whole, as independent entities… part and whole co-emerge and mutually specify each other” (Thompson, 2007, p. 65). Of course, there is a sense in which this is certainly the case: a defining feature of autopoietic autonomous systems (e.g., a cell) is that its components are produced by the network of mutually enabling processes that constitute the system, and where global topological constraints play a key role (Maturana and Varela, 1980). Hence, there is a sense in which a protein molecule produced inside the cell may be said to have “emerged from the whole” or be “specified by the whole”. However, when applied to a brain network, it is far from obvious how to make sense of DCE. While it seems very plausible that a neuron behaves differently depending on whether it is part of system A rather than system B (i.e., an instance of global-to-local causality), it seems less plausible to hold that a neuron emerges from or is constitutively specified by the neural system it belongs to. Intuitively, a neuron remains being a neuron even if it were hypothetically isolated before being incorporated into, or after being separated from, a larger neural system, as long as it can remain potentially functional and structurally intact.

Fourth, in order to advance an enactive psychedelic science, circular causality should be formalized to make it a scientifically useful tool. To the best of my knowledge, the mathematical, dynamical approaches to circular causality that are most close to the enactive approach are the ones from Haken (1983) and Kelso (2021). Nonetheless, close attention should also be paid to formal accounts of causal emergence and downward causation from complexity science and information theory (Hoel et al., 2016; Mediano et al., 2022). Without an enactive, formal account of circular causality in psychedelic experience, M&S hardly improve the pluralistic view of causation and provide an “account of how biochemical, neural, and experiential processes affect each other through local-to-global and global-to-local determination” (Meling and Scheidegger, 2023, p. 9).

Fifth, as a relation between parts/local and wholes/global activity, in contrast to what is suggested by M&S, circular causality would be more straightforwardly involved in the relationship between the psychedelic molecule and brain activity, rather than between brain activity and the psychedelic experience. In the absence of sound reasons to consider the relationship between brain activity and conscious experiences as mereological, alternative ways to understand their causal relation should be looked for.

Finally, instead of focusing mostly on “psychedelic experiential cognitive acts” (Meling and Scheidegger, 2023, p. 9) involved in mystical-type experiences, future enactive research may concentrate also on the dynamics of the affective experience under psychedelics and its causal influence on the associated emotional-somatic changes. Experiencing an emotional breakthrough in the psychedelic session has also been validated as a strong mediator of subsequent mental health benefits (Roseman et al., 2019). Hence, an important theoretical foundation for an enactive psychedelic science would be the enactive approach to affectivity (Varela and Depraz, 2005; Colombetti, 2014). Importantly, the affective experiential dimension would have its primary locus in what Thompson and Varela (2001) called the organismic regulation cycle, and therefore, psychedelic-induced changes in the subject's primordial feeling of being alive or continuous organismic sentience (Cea and Martínez-Pernía, 2023) may have a key causal explanatory role to play.

Author contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Funding

This work has been funded by the Center for Research, Innovation and Creation, Catholic University of Temuco, Chile and by the ANID-Fondecyt postdoctoral grant #3210707.

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Christopher Timmermann and Fernando Rosas for stimulating discussions on this topic.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

Aizawa, K. (2014). The enactivist revolution. AVANT Pismo Awangardy Filozoficzno-Naukowej 5, 19–42. doi: 10.26913/50202014.0109.0002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cea, I., and Martínez-Pernía, D. (2023). Continuous organismic sentience as the integration of core affect and vitality. J. Conscious. Stud. 30, 7–33. doi: 10.53765/20512201.30.3.007

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Colombetti, G. (2014). The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Haken, H. (1983). Synergetics: An Introduction, 3rd Edn. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

Google Scholar

Hoel, E. P., Albantakis, L., Marshall, W., and Tononi, G. (2016). Can the macro beat the micro? Integrated information across spatiotemporal scales. Neurosci. Conscious. 2016, niw012. doi: 10.1093/nc/niw012

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kelso, J. A. S. (2021). The Haken–Kelso–Bunz (HKB) model: from matter to movement to mind. Biol. Cybernet. 115, 305–322. doi: 10.1007/s00422-021-00890-w

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kirchhoff, M. D. (2015). Extended cognition and the causal-constitutive fallacy: in search for a diachronic and dynamical conception of constitution. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 90, 320–360. doi: 10.1111/phpr.12039

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Maturana, H., and Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Boston, MA: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

Google Scholar

Mediano, P. A. M., Rosas, F. E., Luppi, A. I., Jensen, H. J., Seth, A. K., Barrett, A. B., et al. (2022). Greater than the parts: a review of the information decomposition approach to causal emergence. Philos. Trans. Royal Soc. A 380, 20210246. doi: 10.1098/rsta.2021.0246

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meling, D., and Scheidegger, M. (2023). Not in the drug, not in the brain: causality in psychedelic experiences from an enactive perspective. Front. Psychol. 14, 1100058. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1100058

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Roseman, L., Haijen, E., Idialu-Ikato, K., Kaelen, M., Watts, R., and Carhart-Harris, R. (2019). Emotional breakthrough and psychedelics: validation of the Emotional Breakthrough Inventory. J. Psychopharmacol. 33, 1076–1087. doi: 10.1177/0269881119855974

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Thompson, E., and Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends Cogn. Sci. 5, 418–425. doi: 10.1016/S1364-6613(00)01750-2

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Varela, F. J., and Depraz, N. (2005). At the source of time: valence and the constitutional dynamics of affect. J. Conscious. Stud. 12, 61–81.

Google Scholar

Keywords: psychedelics, brain-consciousness relation, causal efficacy of consciousness, dynamic co-emergence, circular causality, interlevel causation, affect, enaction

Citation: Cea I (2023) Commentary: Not in the drug, not in the brain: causality in psychedelic experiences from an enactive perspective. Front. Psychol. 14:1217108. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1217108

Received: 04 May 2023; Accepted: 09 June 2023;
Published: 22 June 2023.

Edited by:

Nicolas Langlitz, The New School, United States

Reviewed by:

Joost J. Breeksema, University Medical Center Groningen, Netherlands

Copyright © 2023 Cea. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Ignacio Cea, aWduZW9jaiYjeDAwMDQwO2dtYWlsLmNvbQ==

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.