Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychol., 28 March 2023
Sec. Consciousness Research
This article is part of the Research Topic The Challenges of Consciousness Research in Light of the Variations of Conscious Experience View all 12 articles

Understanding incomprehensibility: Misgivings and potentials of the phenomenological psychopathology of schizophrenia

  • 1Department of Philosophy, University of Cologne, Cologne, Germany
  • 2Phenomenological Psychopathology and Psychiatry, University Clinic Heidelberg, Heidelberg, Germany

1. Introduction

Incomprehensibility is canonically regarded a key characteristic of schizophrenia. Bizarre delusions, in particular, contribute to its clinical picture and have been considered essential for diagnosing schizophrenia. Accordingly, the DSM-IV-TR speaks of bizarre delusions “if they are clearly implausible and not understandable and do not derive from ordinary life experiences” (American Psychiatric Association, 2007, p. 299). The ICD-10, on the other hand, complements that bizarre delusions are “culturally inappropriate and completely impossible” (World Health Organization, 1992, p. 87). In light of this, schizophrenia makes for the paradigm case of a psychopathological shift in consciousness, which has been described in terms of “a transformation in our total awareness of reality” (Jaspers, 1997, p. 95) or an “altered framework for experiencing” (Parnas and Henriksen, 2013, p. 320). The enigmatic character of this psychopathological shift consists in its all-encompassing nature, boiling down to its “core Gestalt” of “a fundamentally changed subjectivity that may manifest itself across all mental domains: affect, expression, motivation, mood, cognition, willing and action” (Parnas, 2012, p. 68). Since this shift consists in a pronounced instability of the schizophrenic self (Henriksen et al., 2021; Burgin et al., 2022), it is subject to debate whether it is best conceived as an explorable transformation of consciousness or as its unfathomable disorganization. This question has troubled the psychopathological discourse on schizophrenia significantly (Andreasen and Flaum, 1991; Parnas, 2011; Henriksen, 2018), in spite of the widespread recognition of the clinical utility of the notions of incomprehensibility and bizarreness (Cermolacce et al., 2010; Feyaerts et al., 2021).

The conundrum of schizophrenic incomprehensibility consists in whether there is any meaningful sense in which we can understand this incomprehensibility. We believe that there is. However, accessing the phenomenon of schizophrenic incomprehensibility is hindered by several confusions surrounding the psychopathological discourse.

In order to arrive at an unclouded judgement, the confusion surrounding the issue of incomprehensibility must itself be investigated. We propose that this confusion stems from three distinct sources. In the following we elaborate on each of them and advance a scheme for structuring the discourse on schizophrenic incomprehensibility (see Table 1):

1. Overreliance on delusional beliefs. The problem of incomprehensibility is ill-posed, biasing the discourse toward the delusional beliefs as is evidenced by their characterization in the ICD and DSM. Consequently, the origin and the experience of delusions are overlooked. Since they lie at the root of the psychopathology of schizophrenia, the discourse on the origin and experiential structure of incomprehensibility must be revisited.

2. False threat of irrationalism. Acknowledging the clinical reality of schizophrenic incomprehensibility is misevaluated as endangering the scientific status of psychopathology by pushing it toward irrationalism. Such an evaluation ultimately hinders the project of determining the possibilities and limits of psychopathological knowledge, which is essential to establishing it as a strict science: In light of the phenomenological approach, schizophrenic incomprehensibility does not mark the endpoint of our understanding of schizophrenia but is a starting point for developing a psychopathological agnotology (i.e., the scientific investigation of the production and experience of incomprehensibility).

3. Equivocations. The discourse on incomprehensibility is riddled with equivocations. This means that conflating concepts such as un-understandability, oddity, schizophrenic alterity or the praecox feeling is the norm rather than the exception. In order to distinguish these related concepts, it is helpful to consider their intellectual origins and to systematically classify competing approaches to schizophrenic incomprehensibility. Considering incomprehensibility can aid in enriching the discourse by moving beyond the classical framing in terms of the understanding-explanation dichotomy to the more adequate and encompassing trichotomy of un-understandability (“Unverständlichkeit”), obscurity (“Uneinfühlbarkeit”) and inexplicability (“Unerklärbarkeit”).

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. A scheme for structuring the debate on schizophrenic incomprehensibility.

In what follows, we sketch how phenomenology can aid psychopathology in overcoming these idols and, ultimately, arrive at a more encompassing and adequate assessment of schizophrenia. This entails that not only the clinical reality of schizophrenic incomprehensibility must be acknowledged, but—beyond that—investigating its experiential structure (both, of the patient and the clinician) is of the essence.

2. Overreliance on delusional beliefs

In order to outline a potential remedy for the bias toward delusional beliefs, we first turn to a historical perspective. Spitzer et al. (1993) notes that the concept of bizarre delusions derives from Kraepelin characterizing schizophrenic delusions as “non-sensical” and from Jaspers deeming them “incomprehensible” (cf. Cermolacce et al., 2010). The latter also originated the standard view of schizophrenic delusions, according to which they are conceived of as false beliefs that cannot be corrected and are entertained with subjective certainty (Jaspers, 1913a; Parnas, 2012). This standard view was maintained in the ICD's and DSM's insistence on the impossible contents of delusional beliefs until recently (cf. Heinimaa, 2002). Consider, for instance, the DSM-IV-TR's definition of schizophrenic delusions: “Delusions are erroneous beliefs that usually involve misinterpretation of perceptions or experiences” (American Psychiatric Association, 2007, p. 275–276). Whereas contemporary treatments focus on the incomprehensibility of the delusional content, i.e., the falsity, robustness and certainty of the propositional belief, Jaspers, originally, was concerned more with the origin and the experience of delusions (Jaspers, 1913a,b; cf. Schmitt, 2018).

With regard to this, three different notions of incomprehensibility ought to be differentiated. The first one derives from Jaspers' interpretation of Dilthey (1894) methodological dualism (cf. Henriksen, 2013). Since Jaspers posits a somatic origin of delusions, their scientific investigation ought to treat them as causal-genetic objects of explanation (cause-effect; nexus of causality). Accordingly, incomprehensibility pertaining to the origin of delusions arises because of the categorical inapplicability of understanding, which presupposes a meaningful psychological motivation through previous experiences (purpose-consequence; nexus of finality). Thus, a failure to identify the somatic origins of schizophrenia is more aptly described in terms of inexplicability (“Unerklärbarkeit”), which depends on the progress of the natural sciences and, accordingly, might be merely temporary.

The second and third notion of incomprehensibility both pertain to the status of schizophrenic delusions as primary phenomena (“Urphänomene”) (cf. Heinze and Kupke, 2006; Kupke, 2008; Thoma, 2013). One the one hand, primary delusions that occur in schizophrenia amount to an immediate, perception-like “awareness of meaning” that “undergoes a radical transformation” (Jaspers, 1997, p. 99). This entails that such primary delusions, in contrast to delusion-like ideas, cannot meaningfully be traced back to ‘the content' of preceding mental states and, thus, are ‘unmotivated' or exhibit no ‘meaningful connections'. Therefore, primary delusions are un-understandable in the sense that they defy the purpose-consequence structure of the nexus of finality.

On the other hand, primary delusions encompass changes on the level of subjectivity (Owen et al., 2004). Such primary delusions are disorders of self-consciousness and object-consciousness, such as thought broadcasting, thought insertion, delusions of passivity, etc. Since they pertain to the sphere of the conscious experience of reality (“Wirklichkeitserleben”), they cannot be reduced to or analogized with other phenomena but unveil a primary stratum of existence. For this very reason, Jaspers holds that primary delusions lie outside the realm of science altogether and must, instead, be investigated philosophically (Kupke, 2008). Hence, incomprehensibility concerning delusional experience arises because primary delusions exceed the scope of scientific investigation and, accordingly, lie beyond the dichotomy of explanation and understanding.

Considering this third sense, incomprehensible delusional content (as well as “crazy actions”), in turn, would be conceived of as a manifestation of the underlying primary delusional experience and has only a secondary status. This implies that it would be a mistake to take impossible delusional content as a sufficient criterion for diagnosing schizophrenia. Instead, “we must realize that the content and structure of these experiences are dialectically intertwined, and therefore we must take into account the altered framework of experiencing in schizophrenia” (Parnas and Henriksen, 2013, p. 324).

3. False threat of irrationalism

Explicating the changes of the experiential structure in schizophrenia converges with the prime interest of its phenomenological treatment. In the recent discourse, researchers agree that the psychopathological shift in consciousness occurring in schizophrenia can be described as a disturbance on the level of the minimal self (Cermolacce et al., 2007; Hur et al., 2014; Nelson et al., 2014), i.e., an abnormal sense of the first-person quality of experience, a loss of “mineness” that can lead to a quasi-solipsistic world-view and a pervasive alienation from the lived-body, i.e. disembodiment (Fuchs, 2020b). This disordered structure underpins changes (a) on the level of the extended self (Gallagher, 2003; Phillips, 2003; Parnas and Zandersen, 2018), i.e., a fragmented or delusional narrative self-understanding that becomes explicit in schizophrenic belief contents, and (b) on the level of extended intersubjectivity (Stanghellini and Lysaker, 2007; Fuchs, 2010; Frith, 2015; Gallagher and Varga, 2015; Van Duppen, 2017), i.e., difficulties in participating in conversational exchanges, explicit other-understanding via theory of mind, and an intense sense of threat coming from the social realm. In sum, the outlook of phenomenological psychopathology can help reorient the discourse on schizophrenia from its surface level features (delusional belief content) back to the underlying changes in the structure of experience.

What can such a phenomenological outlook contribute to understanding incomprehensibility in schizophrenia? First of all, conceiving of schizophrenia as an altered framework for experiencing allows to identify “a developmental continuity from early non-psychotic self-disorders to the fully formed first-rank symptoms” (Parnas and Henriksen, 2013, p. 324). It is important to note that this continuity is neither one of physical causation (nexus of causality), nor one of mental motivation (nexus of finality), but rather an eidetic continuity (Parnas and Henriksen, 2013). Hence, the ipseity disturbance model (Nelson et al., 2014; Nordgaard et al., 2023) conceives of schizophrenia in terms of a disorder at the level of the minimal self and attempts to identify experiential structures that are present in the sub-clinical and clinical picture of the disorder. In terms of a phenomenological act-analysis, this means that the disturbance on the level of the minimal self-corresponds to a dialectical process in which perturbations of the intentional structure of experience (e.g., an excessively self-referential act-structure) elicit compensatory symptoms (e.g., hyperreflexivity or excessive introspection) and disturbances of the pre-reflective, passive synthesis of meaning.

Delusional belief contents, then, can be viewed as an attempt to thematize these underlying changes and, hence, exhibit a so-called “delusional logic” (“Wahnsinnslogik”) (Wulff, 1992). By unearthing these foundational layers to psychopathological shifts in consciousness, phenomenological psychopathology contributes not only to a better understanding of the patient's experience from his or her own perspective, but also offers conceptual and methodological means for the early detection of schizophrenic psychosis (Parnas et al., 2005; Sass et al., 2017), which is sometimes prematurely reserved for neurobiological approaches to psychopathology (Insel, 2010; Heinssen and Insel, 2015). By shedding light on this eidetic continuity, phenomenological psychopathology provides a framework that furthers scientific understanding of incomprehensibility by illuminating its development.

Over the course of the discourse's development, the “theorem of incomprehensibility” (Kupke, 2008)—sometimes also referred to as Jaspers's theorem—has been criticized and ultimately rejected by several competing psychopathological approaches, for instance, systems approach (Bateson et al., 1956) and psychoanalysis (Freud, 1911), but also other, phenomenologically inclined approaches such as anthropological psychiatry (Zutt, 1963) or Daseinsanalyse (Binswanger, 1957). The very concept of incomprehensibility has been perceived to push psychopathology toward irrationalism and, correspondingly, acknowledging schizophrenic incomprehensibility has been equated to abandoning the scientific enterprise altogether. Before this backdrop, the concept of incomprehensibility was reduced to that of delusional content and psychopathological interest in the notion has shrunk down to its operational value for diagnosis.

Why, then, did Jaspers and his successors insist on maintaining the concept of incomprehensibility in phenomenological psychopathology?

Firstly, an overemphasis on resolving incomprehensibility runs the danger of misconstruing the clinical picture of schizophrenia. Schizophrenic incomprehensibility lies at the root of nothing less than what Jaspers holds to be “[t]he most profound distinction in psychic life,” namely “that between what is meaningful and allows empathy and what in its particular way is ununderstandable, ‘mad' in the literal sense, schizophrenic psychic life” (Jaspers, 1997, p. 577). Accordingly, this pertains to “the basic problem of psychopathology” (Jaspers, 1997, p. 702) that consists in learning to differentiate unified personality developments from disruptive processes that break with life's continuity.

“[T]he facts are overlooked in an endeavor to see the individual as understandable […]. [W]e […] should recognize what is not understandable in all its complex heterogeneity and grasp it methodically according to what its nature may be” (Jaspers, 1997, p. 705).

Therefore, recognizing schizophrenic incomprehensibility must not be confused with giving up on its psychopathological investigation, but rather is an integral part of a strict and sober clinical description.

This brings us, secondly, to the potential of establishing a psychopathological agnotology that revolves around the concept of incomprehensibility. This means that acknowledging incomprehensibility is no longer viewed as an endpoint of the scientific treatment of schizophrenia, but as marking the starting point of a new field that differentiates forms of incomprehensibility and investigates the mechanisms that underlie and produce it. Not unlike the adventurers of the Age of Discovery, who charted unknown parts of the globe, the so-called terra incognita, psychopathological agnotology can provide guidance and direction for studying schizophrenic incomprehensibility, analogously: mens incognita. In its strongest form, however, such a psychopathological agnotology goes beyond the mere mapping of what might one day be rendered understandable and homes in on the “positive message of incomprehensibility” (Wulff, 1992, p. 7; cf. Schlegel, 1800; Bauer, 2011).

For the most part, this remains a desideratum for further research. Nevertheless, genetic phenomenology and the analysis of disturbed patterns of passive synthesis in schizophrenia afford promising research perspectives. In this vein, Wulff spells out the delusional logic in terms of “acts of paradoxicalization” (1992, p. 9) that describe how subjective-situational meaning (“Sinn”) and objective-general meaning (“Bedeutung”) become decoupled and reconfigured. Similarly, Moskalewicz and Gozé turn to a genetic analysis of “bizarreness of contact” (Moskalewicz and Gozé, 2022, p. 144) as a pre-reflective and ante-predicative atmospheric quality that surrounds the encounter with schizophrenic patients and corresponds to Rümke's (1941) infamous praecox feeling by the clinician (cf. Varga, 2013; Gozé and Naudin, 2017). Relatedly, Fuchs (2020a) advanced a genetic analysis from an enactive perspective that conceives of the experiential change at the beginning of psychosis in terms of a subjectivization of perception that results in a disembodiment and derealization of experience. Instead of capitulating before schizophrenic incomprehensibility, genetic phenomenology provides the theoretical scaffolding for acknowledging and analyzing its experience.

4. Equivocations

Considering the phenomenological discussion of the praecox feeling is telling, because it allows to shed light on an equivocation troubling schizophrenia research (see Table 1). The praecox feeling has been described as a feeling of bizarreness and unease when encountering schizophrenic patients and, ultimately, as the impossibility of empathizing with them (Rümke, 1941). Albeit being subject to considerable criticism, both concerning the prospect of its phenomenological rehabilitation (Parnas, 2011) and regarding its empirical and diagnostic validity (Grube, 2006; Gozé et al., 2019), the notion of the praecox feeling has recently been reconsidered in light of interactionist interpretations of direct perception theory of empathy (Haker and Rössler, 2009; Gallagher and Varga, 2015). Within this framework, the praecox feeling is explicated as a lack of interaffective and interbodily resonance, ultimately leading to a breakdown of enactive sense-making and social understanding (Varga, 2013). Hence, the patient's schizophrenic disembodiment is empathically experienced by the clinician through the praecox feeling (Fuchs, 2020b) or, following Moskalewicz and Gozé (2022), the preceding “bizarreness of contact.”

From a historical perspective, the debate concerning the praecox feeling connects to the discourse on obscurity (“Uneinfühlbarkeit”), viz. the impossibility to empathize. In the beginning of the 20th century, a controversy ensued regarding the conceptualization of schizophrenic incomprehensibility within phenomenological psychopathology (Schmitt, 2018), sometimes referred to as the Jaspers-Binswanger controversy (Basso, 2016). Essentially, Binswanger (1913; 1914, cf. 1957) opposed Jaspers' theorem of incomprehensibility and conceived of schizophrenia as a specific and deficient, yet understandable mode of being-in-the-world. Binswanger's (1913, 1914) and Jaspers (1913a,b) exchange during 1913–1914 was embedded in ongoing debates in the vicinity of Kraepelin's and Bleuler's schools as well as the broader context of the method dispute that started at the end of the 19th century. A number of psychopathologists influenced by Scheler's notion of sympathy, Bergson's concept of intuition and Heideggers' term of being-with took issue with Jaspers' framing of schizophrenic incomprehensibility via the distinction between static and genetic understanding, since it remained indebted to Dilthey's understanding, Lipps's Einfühlung and Freud's interpretation (cf. Kupke, 2008; Henriksen, 2013).

Indeed Jaspers' notion of incomprehensibility never properly connected with the phenomenological tradition of empathic other-experience that originated with Scheler's (1913) proposal of unmediated expression-perception, i.e., in the same year as Jaspers' psychopathology was first published. Accordingly, Minkowski (1927) proposed a “diagnosis by penetration,” Wyrsch (1946) advanced the notion of “diagnosis by intuition” and Binswanger (1955) argued for a “diagnosis by feeling” (cf. Parnas, 2011; Moskalewicz and Gozé, 2022):

“The question of whether the psychic life of the mentally ill follows the same laws as that of healthy people is intimately connected to the question of whether and to what extend we can empathize [“einfühlen”] with the psychic life of the mentally ill; with other words: we will approximate a decision regarding this question to the degree that we learn to empathize with the psychic life of the mentally ill” (Binswanger, 1914, p. 596).

On the one hand, these concepts aimed at establishing a specific role of empathy in conceiving of schizophrenic incomprehensibility that is distinct from the role of understanding. On the other hand, they challenged Jaspers's theorem of radical incomprehensibility and attributed a broader epistemic scope to the phenomenological analysis of schizophrenia. Taking this into account and connecting it with the argument from (1), the canonical framing of the Jaspers-Binswanger controversy as evolving around the understanding-explanation dichotomy can be recast in terms of a trichotomy of empathy-understanding-explanation. Consequently, this allows to differentiate three senses of schizophrenic incomprehensibility that are routinely conflated, namely obscurity (“Uneinfühlbarkeit”), un-understandablility (“Unverständlichkeit”) and inexplicability (“Unerklärbarkeit”; see Table 1). Learning to structure the debate accordingly is helpful for accounting for whether schizophrenic shifts in consciousness are best conceived of as explorable transformations or unfathomable disorganizations.

Author contributions

All authors listed have made a substantial, direct, and intellectual contribution to the work and approved it for publication.

Funding

We acknowledge support for the Article Processing Charge from the DFG (German Research Foundation, 491454339).

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Alexander Wendt, who pointed us toward the Jaspers-Binswanger controversy as a central historical dispute revolving around the notion of obscurity (“Uneinfühlbarkeit”).

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

American Psychiatric Association (2007). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual ofMental Disorders: DSMIV. Text Revision, 4th ed. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.

Google Scholar

Andreasen, N. C., and Flaum, M. (1991). Schizophrenia: the characteristic symptoms. Schizophr. Bull. 17, 27–49. doi: 10.1093/schbul/17.1.27

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Basso, E. (2016). Jaspers et Binswanger. un débat sur phénoménologie et psychanalyse (1913-1914). Cultura Rev. Hist. Teoria Ideias 35, 211–230. doi: 10.4000/cultura.2611

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bateson, G., Jackson, D.D., Haley, J., and Weakland, J. (1956). Toward a theory of schizophrenia. Behav. Sci. 1, 251–264. doi: 10.1002/bs.3830010402

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bauer, M. (ed). (2011). “Zwischen Hermeneutikkritik und Verstehensoptimismus: Über die Unverständlichkeit,” in Schlegel und Schleiermacher (Paderborn: Verlag Ferdinand Schöningh), 108–126. Available online at: https://brill.com/display/title/49916. doi: 10.30965/9783657771226_008

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Binswanger, L. (1913). Bemerkungen zu der Arbeit Jaspers' “Kausale und ‘verständliche' Zusammenhänge zwischen Schicksal und Psychose bei der Dementia praecox (Schizophrenie)”. Int. Z. Ärztl. Psychoanal. 1, 383–390.

Google Scholar

Binswanger, L. (1914). Psychologische Tagesfragen innerhalb der klinischen Psychiatrie. Z. Gesamte Neurol. Psychiatr. 26, 574–599. doi: 10.1007/BF02874474

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Binswanger, L. (1955). “Welche Aufgaben ergeben sich für die Psychiatrie aus den Forschungen der neueren Psychologie?” in Ausgewählte Vorträge und Aufsätze, Vol. 2, eds Binswanger, L., and Ausgewählte, (Bern: Francke), 111–146.

Binswanger, L. (1957). Schizophrenie. Neske: Pfullingen.

Google Scholar

Burgin, S., Reniers, R., and Humpston, C. (2022). Prevalence and assessment of self-disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Sci. Rep. 12, 1165. doi: 10.1038/s41598-022-05232-9

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cermolacce, M., Naudin, J., and Parnas, J. (2007). The “minimal self” in psychopathology: re-examining the self-disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum. Conscious. Cogn. 16, 703–714. doi: 10.1016/j.concog.2007.05.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cermolacce, M., Sass, L., and Parnas, J. (2010). What is bizarre in bizarre delusions? A critical review. Schizophr. Bull. 36, 667–679. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbq001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dilthey, W. (1894). Ideen Ueber eine Beschreibende und Zergliedernde Psychologie. W. Dilthey: Die Philosophie des Lebens, 131–229.

Feyaerts, J., Henriksen, M. G., Vanheule, S., Myin-Germeys, I., and Sass, L. A. (2021). Delusions beyond beliefs: a critical overview of diagnostic, aetiological, and therapeutic schizophrenia research from a clinical-phenomenological perspective. Lancet Psychiatry, 8, 237–249. doi: 10.1016/S2215-0366(20)30460-0

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Freud, S. (1911). “Psychoanalytische Bemerkungen über einen autobiographisch beschriebenen Fall von Paranoia (Dementia paranoides),” in Studienausgabe, Vol. 7, eds A. Mitscherlich, A. Richards, J. Strachey, et al. (Frankfurt am Main: Fischer), 239–320.

Frith, C. D. (2015). The Cognitive Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia: Classic Edition. London: Psychology press. doi: 10.4324/9781315785011

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fuchs, T. (2010). “Phenomenology and psychopathology,” in Handbook of Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, eds S. Gallagher, and D. Schmicking (New York, NY: Springer), 546–573. doi: 10.1007/978-90-481-2646-0_28

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fuchs, T. (2020a). Delusion, reality and intersubjectivity: a phenomenological and enactive analysis. Phenomenol. Mind 120–143. doi: 10.17454/pam-1810

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fuchs, T. (2020b). “Embodied interaffectivity and psychopathology,” in The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotion, eds T. Szanto and H. Landweer (London: Routledge), 323–336. doi: 10.4324/9781315180786-31

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallagher, S. (2003). “Self-narrative in schizophrenia,” in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, eds T. Kircher, and A. David (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.), 336–357. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511543708.017

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallagher, S., and Varga, S. (2015). Social cognition and psychopathology: a critical overview. World Psychiatry 14, 5–14. doi: 10.1002/wps.20173

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gozé, T., Moskalewicz, M., Schwartz, M. A., Naudin, J., Micoulaud-Franchi, J.-A., Cermolacce, M., et al. (2019). Reassessing “praecox feeling” in diagnostic decision making in schizophrenia: a critical review. Schizophr. Bull. 45, 966–970. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sby172

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gozé, T., and Naudin, J. (2017). Discussing Rümke's “Praecox Feeling” from the clinician's experience of schizophrenic contact. Rev. Psicopatol. Fenomenol. Contemporânea 6, 112–123. doi: 10.37067/rpfc.v6i2.981

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Grube, M. (2006). Towards an empirically based validation of intuitive diagnostic: Rümke's ‘praecox feeling'across the schizophrenia spectrum: preliminary results. Psychopathology 39, 209–217. doi: 10.1159/000093921

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Haker, H., and Rössler, W. (2009). Empathy in schizophrenia: impaired resonance. Eur. Arch. Psychiatry Clin. Neurosci. 259, 352–361. doi: 10.1007/s00406-009-0007-3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Heinimaa, M. (2002). Incomprehensibility: the role of the concept in DSM-IV definition of schizophrenic delusions. Med. Health Care Philos. 5, 291–295. doi: 10.1023/A:1021164602485

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Heinssen, R. K., and Insel, T. R. (2015). Preventing the onset of psychosis: not quite there yet. Schizophr. Bull. 41, 28–9. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbu161

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Heinze, M., and Kupke, C. (2006). Philosophie in der psychiatrie. Nervenarzt 77, 346–349. doi: 10.1007/s00115-005-2016-4

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G. (2013). On incomprehensibility in schizophrenia. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 12, 105–129. doi: 10.1007/s11097-010-9194-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G. (2018). “Schizophrenia, psychosis, and empathy,” in Phenomenology and the Social Context of Psychiatry, ed M. Englander (London: Bloomsbury), 27–47.

Google Scholar

Henriksen, M. G., Raballo, A., and Nordgaard, J. (2021). Self-disorders and psychopathology: a systematic review. Lancet Psychiatry 8, 1001–1012. doi: 10.1016/S2215-0366(21)00097-3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hur, J.-W., Kwon, J. S., Lee, T. Y., and Park, S. (2014). The crisis of minimal self-awareness in schizophrenia: a meta-analytic review. Schizophr. Res. 152, 58–64. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2013.08.042

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Insel, T. R. (2010). Rethinking schizophrenia. Nature 468, 187–193. doi: 10.1038/nature09552

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jaspers, K. (1913a). Allgemeine Psychopathologie. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.

Google Scholar

Jaspers, K. (1913b). Kausale und “verständliche” Zusammenhänge zwischen Schicksal und Psychose bei der dementia praecox (Schizophrenie). Z. Gesamte Neurol. Psychiatr. 14, 158–263. doi: 10.1007/BF02867884

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jaspers, K. (1997). General Psychopathology. Transl. by J. Hoenig and M. W. Hamilton. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.

Google Scholar

Kupke, C. (2008). Was ist so unverständlich am Wahn? Philosophisch-kritische Darstellung des Jaspers'schen Unverständlichkeitstheorems. J. Philos. Psychiatr. 1, 1–12.

Minkowski, E. (1927). La Schizophrénie. Psychopathologie des Schizoïdes et des Schizophrenes. Paris.

Google Scholar

Moskalewicz, M., and Gozé, T. (2022). “Clinical judgment of schizophrenia: praecox feeling and the bizarreness of contact—open controversies,” in The Clinician in the Psychiatric Diagnostic Process, eds Biondi, M., Picardi, A., Pallagrosi, M., and Fonzi, L. (Cham: Springer International Publishing), 135–149. doi: 10.1007/978-3-030-90431-9_9

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nelson, B., Parnas, J., and Sass, L. A. (2014). Disturbance of minimal self (ipseity) in schizophrenia: clarification and current status. Schizophr. Bull. 40, 479–482. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbu034

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nordgaard, J., Berge, J., Rasmussen, A. R., Sandsten, K. E., Zandersen, M., Parnas, J., et al. (2023). Are self-disorders in schizophrenia expressive of a unifying disturbance of subjectivity: a factor analytic approach. Schizophr. Bull. 49, 144–150. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbac123

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Owen, G., Harland, R., Antonova, E., and Broome, M. (2004). Jaspers' concept of primary delusion. Br. J. Psychiatry 185, 77–78. doi: 10.1192/bjp.185.1.77-a

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J. (2011). A disappearing heritage: the clinical core of schizophrenia. Schizophr. Bull. 37, 1121–1130. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbr081

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J. (2012). The core gestalt of schizophrenia. World Psychiatry 11, 67–69. doi: 10.1016/j.wpsyc.2012.05.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., and Henriksen, M. G. (2013). Subjectivity and schizophrenia: another look at incomprehensibility and treatment nonadherence. Psychopathology 46, 320–329. doi: 10.1159/000351837

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., Møller, P., Kircher, T., Thalbitzer, J., Jansson, L., Handest, P., et al. (2005). EASE: examination of anomalous self-experience. Psychopathology 38, 236. doi: 10.1159/000088441

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Parnas, J., and Zandersen, M. (2018). Self and schizophrenia: current status and diagnostic implications. World Psychiatry 17, 220. doi: 10.1002/wps.20528

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Phillips, J. (2003). “Schizophrenia and the narrative self,” in The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, eds Kircher, T., and David., A. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 319–335. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511543708.016

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rümke, H. C. (1941). The nuclear symptom of schizophrenia and the praecoxfeeling. Hist. Psychiatry 1, 331–341. doi: 10.1177/0957154X9000100304

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text

Sass, L., Pienkos, E., Skodlar, B., Stanghellini, G., Fuchs, T., Parnas, J., et al. (2017). EAWE: examination of anomalous world experience. Psychopathology 50, 10–54. doi: 10.1159/000454928

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Scheler, M. (1913). Zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Sympathiegefühle und von Liebe und Hass. Mit einem Anhang über den Grund zur Annahme der Existenz des fremden Ich. Halle: Max Niemeyer.

Google Scholar

Schlegel, F. (1800). Über die Unverständlichkeit. in Kritische Friedrich-Schlegel-Ausgabe. Erste Abteilung: Kritische Neuausgabe. München, Paderborn, Wien: Verlag Ferdinand Schöningh, 363–373.

Schmitt, S. (2018). Das Ringen um das Selbst: Schizophrenie in Wissenschaft, Gesellschaft und Kultur nach 1945. Oldenburg: Walter de Gruyter GmbH and Co KG. doi: 10.1515/9783110531565

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Spitzer, R. L., First, M. B., Kendler, K. S., and Stein, D. J. (1993). The reliability of three definitions of bizarre delusions. Ame. J. Psychiatry 150, 880–884. doi: 10.1176/ajp.150.6.880

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stanghellini, G., and Lysaker, P. H. (2007). The psychotherapy of schizophrenia through the lens of phenomenology: intersubjectivity and the search for the recovery of first-and second-person awareness. Am. J. Psychother. 61, 163–179. doi: 10.1176/appi.psychotherapy.2007.61.2.163

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Thoma, S. (2013). “Phänomenologische Psychiatrie in der Kritik: Karl Jaspers, Arthur Tatossian und Wolfgang Blankenburg,” in Karl Jaspers - Phänomenologie und Psychopathologie (Schriftenreihe der Deutschen Gesellschaft für phänomenologische Anthropologie, Psychiatrie und Psychotherapie (DGAP)), eds T. Fuchs, S. Micali, and B. Wandruszka (München: Karl Alber), 41–67.

Google Scholar

Van Duppen, Z. (2017). The intersubjective dimension of schizophrenia. Philos. Psychiatr. Psychol. 24, 399–418. doi: 10.1353/ppp.2017.0058

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Varga, S. (2013). Vulnerability to psychosis, I-thou intersubjectivity and the praecox-feeling. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 12, 131–143. doi: 10.1007/s11097-010-9173-z

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

World Health Organization (1992). The ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioural Disorders: Clinical Description and Diagnostic Guidelines. Geneva: World Health Organization.

Google Scholar

Wulff, E. (1992). Zur Konstitution schizophrener Unverständlichkeit. Fotum Kritische Psychol. 30, 6–28.

Google Scholar

Wyrsch, J. (1946). Über die Intuition bei der Erkennung des schizophrenen. Schweiz. Med. Wochenschr. 46, 1173–1176.

Google Scholar

Zutt, J. (1963). Auf dem Wege zu Einer Anthropologischen Psychiatrie: Gesammelte Aufsätze. Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag. doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-85694-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: schizophrenia, obscurity, inexplicability, Karl Jaspers, Ludwig Binswanger, phenomenological psychopathology, praecox feeling, un-understandability

Citation: Wendler H and Fuchs T (2023) Understanding incomprehensibility: Misgivings and potentials of the phenomenological psychopathology of schizophrenia. Front. Psychol. 14:1155838. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1155838

Received: 31 January 2023; Accepted: 28 February 2023;
Published: 28 March 2023.

Edited by:

Christopher Gutland, Zhejiang University, China

Reviewed by:

Mads Gram Henriksen, University of Copenhagen, Denmark

Copyright © 2023 Wendler and Fuchs. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Hannes Wendler, aHdlbmRsZXImI3gwMDA0MDt1bmkta29lbG4uZGU=

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.