1. Introduction
Based on his pioneering research on infants and drawing from the epistemological framework of phenomenology (Husserl, 1964; Habermas, 1972), Trevarthen has formulated a developmental theory of intersubjectivity which focuses on innate Other-awareness, inborn motives for sympathetic engagement with others, and cultural sharing—from the beginning of life (Trevarthen, 1977, 1980; Trevarthen and Aitken, 2001). I suggest that this theory of companionship has the potential to offer a rich conceptualization of loneliness, defined as the distress and social pain stemming from being alone. This potential has not been examined thus far and is the focus of this study.
2. Loneliness as a social or relational emotion
I suggest that within Trevarthen's theory of intersubjectivity loneliness can be regarded as a complex and dynamic social or relational emotion (a term introduced by Stern, 1993). It is an emotion between persons, a fellow-feeling, according to philosopher Adam Smith (1759), who inspired Trevarthen.
Social or relational emotions belong to the causes of consciousness, according to Trevarthen (2005a). This may apply to loneliness too and contrasts with the long-standing interpretations of loneliness as an outcome of cognitive processes, that is, of individuals' awareness of their relational (quantitative and/or qualitative) deficits, which, in turn, stems from the perception of the dissonance between the expected and the real level of relationships (e.g., Peplau and Perlman, 1982). Cognitive models of loneliness place emphasis on subjective cognitions as the source of loneliness. In the intersubjective framework, the order is reversed: social emotions are the causes of co-consciousness, of self-other awareness.
Loneliness is a universal experience with cognitive, emotional, contextual, and motivational dimensions (e.g., Galanaki, 2004). From an evolutionary and attachment viewpoint, it has been conceptualized as a proximity-promoting mechanism with a survival value for the human species (Cacioppo and Patrick, 2008). However, the theory of intersubjectivity has the potential to place loneliness over and above attachment (protection, comfort, and care) and survival. Thus, loneliness may be regarded as expressing not only attachment for care but also attachment for companionship and as arising and being alleviated within a circle of attachments (Trevarthen, 2004a, 2005c). In this line of thought, loneliness originates from humans' social brain (Dunbar, 2009), allocentric perception (Bråten, 2009), and innate dialogicity (Wertsch, 1991).
3. Loneliness as a moral emotion
Further, I suggest that, as a motive for sympathy, loneliness belongs to our moral core and can be regarded as a moral emotion. Unlike empathy, which is rather one-sided, sympathy is the intersubjective awareness of agency and emotion that works reciprocally between persons (Reddy and Trevarthen, 2004; Reddy, 2008) and reflects complementary emotional states that are shared with the other. It is a bridge between persons expressing their mutual assistance (Trevarthen, 2013). Sympathetic persons have moral emotions, such as pride and shame, that “can keep or break social ties, and may facilitate sharing of meanings and purposes, or make their understanding more difficult” (Gratier and Trevarthen, 2007, p. 173). Specifically, Trevarthen (2005c, p. 77) links shame and loneliness by stating that “shame in failure […] threatens loss of relationship and hopeless isolation.”
Aloneness carries stigma and signifies rejection, exclusion, and ostracism. This is often an exclusion from meaning (Trevarthen, 2005c). Therapists must keep in mind that we are born with readiness to join in kindness and playful sympathy with companions (Trevarthen, 2019). Thus, loneliness of shame (Trevarthen, 2022) may be the target of prevention and therapy from the beginning of life.
4. Loneliness as an innate intersubjective motive
If emotions and motives have strong links with each other or even overlap (Trevarthen, 1993), I suggest that loneliness can also be conceptualized as an innate intersubjective motive—a motive for seeking human company. Loneliness stems from absence and is regarded as longing for something missing. The desire to transform absence into presence—the compulsion to share the time of movement (Trevarthen, 2009)—may be what distinguishes loneliness from clinical depression (however, intense loneliness may appear as a symptom of clinical depression and take on several qualities as a function of the type and severity of depression). In depression, motives for life and companionship as well as hope for the future seem to suffer. Therefore, loneliness is a measure of companionship, not separateness (Trevarthen, 1998). It is “foundational in developing human relations, and in the growth of a sense of individuality or identity in society”—this is Trevarthen (2002, p. 175) view for the emotions of pride and shame.
If emotions are reflective, “in the sense that their usefulness for each individual depends on what emotional signals come back from other individuals” (Trevarthen and Aitken, 2003, p. 9) and we can mirror each other's emotions, a person's loneliness move others. All emotions can evoke responses in sympathetic others (Reddy and Trevarthen, 2004). Therefore, I suggest that one's loneliness may be painful for all sympathetic others too but also that it is more tolerable by the lonely person who can share it. Furthermore, loneliness in one person can change the emotional state of the other (the sympathetic) person. Nevertheless, the phrase “in one person” is not accurate, because loneliness floats in-between persons, even though it is felt as a highly private experience.
If motives are observable (Trevarthen, 1998), it is possible (although not always easy) to detect when others are lonely and seek company. And if motives are transferred and used co-operatively, we can be invited by others to enter their loneliness and contribute to its alleviation.
5. The origins of loneliness and solitude
Regarding loneliness, if infants have feelings like ours (Trevarthen, 2005a), they are bound to have this experience, although they cannot use language to convey it. This may be one reason why their loneliness is neglected by researchers. Trevarthen (2005a, p. 62) wonders: “What causes an infant to display rage or sad withdrawal in a relationship that is not working as expected, and why does a contented infant's mind hide behind a silent mask of inwardness, apparently inventing thoughts?” A fear of an unsupported loneliness is considered typical of the newborn child (Trevarthen, 2003). A baby can express sadness when alone and in need (Trevarthen, 2005b, 2015) and loneliness is one of the outcomes of insensitive, neglectful, or intrusive parenting (Trevarthen, 2014). Trevarthen does not place much emphasis on infants' separation anxiety, which has been regarded as fear of loneliness (Bowlby, 1973; Quinodoz, 1993), perhaps because of his critical attitude toward attachment theory (Trevarthen, 2005c).
Furthermore, solitude is an experience related to loneliness, yet also distinct from it. It is usually conceptualized as time alone and as a state of mind, rather than a state of being [i.e., it may or may not include physical separation (Coplan et al., 2021)] and is described as a paradox because, although it can be self-enhancing, it may lead to loneliness (Galanaki, 2005, 2021). Although Trevarthen (2004b) stresses that there are no single infant heads, he states that even very young infants are capable of disengagement and detachment from sharing of impulses and feelings with other human beings and often withdraw into a solitary state of thinking, reflection, and contemplation (Trevarthen, 2011a). It is a state of self-synchrony which includes body movements, facial expressions, and vocalizations (Trevarthen, 2011a) and reflects a third type of motive (the other two are communicating with persons and doing with objects; Trevarthen, 1998). This inward or self-directed motive has been neglected by infant research (Trevarthen, 1998). Private thinking and social communicating co-exist in corresponding and complementary ways from the beginning of life. The minds of mother and infant are together while having their separate recollections and purposes and while sharing these reflective, meditative states (Hobson, 2002; Trevarthen, 2005a). I would call this shared experience of mother and infant solitude à deux and I suggest that, if sympathy means respect for the other person's autonomy even when there is disapproval (Trevarthen, 2005c), it is the sympathetic mother that sets the stage for her child's life-long capacity to benefit from solitude. The mother's respect for her child's autonomous ingenuity and invention—this respect is also an educational value (Trevarthen, 2011b)—echoes (Winnicott's, 1965) statement that the capacity to be alone in the presence of the mother is a major developmental achievement.
6. Implications for the causes and the alleviation of loneliness
Trevarthen's research and theory of intersubjectivity have the potential to offer a deeper understanding of the causes and, therefore, the alleviation of loneliness. Throughout life loneliness results from a failure in intersubjectivity and is reduced when meaningful sharing is restored and maintained.
More specifically, first, loneliness may arise when one is literally alone. Then, real time engagement with a partner in a dialogue is not possible. The needs for companionship, sharing of vitality, joy, and pleasure are not satisfied. The actual Other is missing and the implicit or virtual Other (Bråten, 1992) is inadequate or the actual Other is missing for a long period. Within the epistemological framework of phenomenology (e.g., Heidegger's being-with-others, Husserl's transcendental intersubjectivity, and Merleau-Ponty's intercorporeity), prolonged and imposed solitude, as a privation of primary and secondary intersubjectivity, throughout life, is a severe existential disruption, because it undermines our very constitution—the relational self—and, thus, leads to disturbances in the sense of realness (Gallagher, 2014).
Second, loneliness emerges from the imperfections or distortions of co-regulation with partners, from lack of harmony. Trevarthen often uses the terms mirroring (Winnicott, 1971) and attunement (Stern, 2000) to describe this co-regulation. “Reading” the Other and being “read” by the Other is impaired in loneliness. Our initiative, as an invitation and provocation of the Other, is not reciprocated. Our anticipation is frustrated and our offerings (initially, as research has shown, in imitation and proto-conversation; Murray and Trevarthen, 1985; Kugiumutzakis et al., 2005; Kugiumutzakis and Trevarthen, 2015) are not acknowledged. No loving voice is heard or there is no one to hear our voice (perhaps because of mother's own sense of loneliness and not belonging; Gratier et al., 2015) and to reciprocate our gaze and touch. There is a failure to participate in shared time (Trevarthen, 2016). Synrhythmia—the Greek term that Trevarthen et al. (2006) used to capture the graceful poly-rhythmic resonance with the Other and expresses our innate communicative musicality (Malloch and Trevarthen, 2009)—is lost.
Third, I suggest that distortions of sharing may be mutually related to loneliness. Optimal sharing of emotions, motives, interests, purposes, actions, etc. is regarded to reflect a balance between engagement and disengagement. When disengagement is more or less than desired, loneliness emerges. These difficulties in self- and co-regulation may manifest as conflicts regarding whether to share or not to share; what to share and what not; when, where, in what pace and with whom to share. In other instances, sharing is asymmetrical or the partners' expectations for the amount of sharing do not match, or sharing is excessive (i.e., one feels “transparent” in an encounter). When chronic and intense, loneliness, in turn, may lead to distortions of sharing. For example, in less fortunate cases, the motivational force of loneliness is not so strong as to facilitate the sharing of our loneliness story with others or, even more, the sharing of the illusion of sharing (Kugiumutzakis, 2012; see also Reddy, 2008).
Fourth, because of the distortions of sharing, we cannot co-create meaning. Acts of meaning (Bruner, 1990) are impeded or discouraged. Meaning is created when we participate in emotional narratives with the Other (starting early in infancy; Stern, 2000) and these embodied narratives gradually become social schemas with cultural significance (Delafield-Butt, 2018). Trevarthen (2004b, p. 23) states that the search for meaning “can fall prey to fear and distress, loneliness and self-doubt.” From the beginning of life, we crave for reliable and affectionate others who can sustain the memories we created with them. Sometimes, however, we cannot draw from treasured memories of a special relationship (Trevarthen, 2008), perhaps because there are no such memories, or we cannot sustain the co-discovered memories. In loneliness, we are not meaningful to a significant Other (initially, less fortunate infants are not meaningful to their mothers in the mother-infant proto-conversation).
Finally, apart from the presence of an actual Other, synrhythmia, sharing and co-construction of meaning, it is cultural membership, that is, finding one's place in the world as a doer and knower (Trevarthen, 2004b), that reduces loneliness. In the cultural context (initially, the mini-culture of the mother-infant dyad), we satisfy our social curiosity by sharing mental spaces and thoughtfulness. We find sympathetic and trusted partners to share our stories and our sense of beauty (Trevarthen and Delafield-Butt, 2017). “Loneliness, shame, depression and sadness are the emotions that identify loss of this collective story-telling, which can be called ‘socionoesis”' (Trevarthen, 2013, p. 204; see also Delafield-Butt and Trevarthen, 2015). But if we manage to co-create a narrative about cosmos and feel our co-existence in symbolic and collaborative awareness (Trevarthen et al., 2006) and our contribution (doing and knowing) is valued by others, cultural learning is facilitated and pride in meaning (Trevarthen, 2001), instead of shame, is felt. Trevarthen (2004b, p. 36) suggests that “all human cultural achievements arise shared meanings, even when they appear to be lonely products, of creatively dreaming or of adventurous risk-taking in thought or action”. To conclude, loneliness arises in a community of minds and is moderated by cultural membership and cultural sharing.
Author contributions
The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to Professor Giannis Kugiumutzakis for his insightful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
Conflict of interest
The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Publisher's note
All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.
References
Bowlby, J. (1973). Attachment and Loss: Vol. 2. Separation: Anxiety and Anger. London: Hogarth Press.
Bråten, S. (1992). “The virtual other in infants' minds and social feelings,” in The Dialogical Alternative: Towards a Theory of Language and Mind, ed A. H. Wold (Oslo: Scandinavian University Press), 77–97.
Bråten, S. (2009). The Intersubjective Mirror in Infant Learning and Evolution of Speech. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing. doi: 10.1075/aicr.76
Cacioppo, J. T., and Patrick, W. (2008). Loneliness: Human Nature and the Need for Social Connection. New York, NY: Norton.
Coplan, R. J., Bowker, J. C., and Nelson, L. J. (2021). “Alone again: revisiting psychological perspectives on solitude,” in The Handbook of Solitude: Psychological Perspectives on Social Isolation, Social Withdrawal, and the Experience of Being Alone, 2nd ed., eds R. J. Coplan, C. J. Bowker, and L. J. Nelson (New York, NY: Wiley-Blackwell), 3–15. doi: 10.1002/9781119576457.ch1
Delafield-Butt, J. (2018). “The emotional and embodied nature of human understanding: sharing narratives of meaning,” in The Child's Curriculum: Working with the Natural Voices of Young Children, eds C. Trevarthen, J. Delafield-Butt, and A. W. Dunlop (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 59–84. doi: 10.1093/oso/9780198747109.003.0004
Delafield-Butt, J. T., and Trevarthen, C. (2015). The ontogenesis of narrative: from moving to meaning. Front. Psychol. 16, 1157. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01157
Dunbar, R. I. M. (2009). The social brain hypothesis and its implications for social evolution. Ann. Hum. Biol. 36, 562–572. doi: 10.1080/03014460902960289
Galanaki, E. (2004). Are children able to distinguish among the concepts of aloneness, loneliness, and solitude? Int. J. Behav. Dev. 28, 435–443. doi: 10.1080/01650250444000153
Galanaki, E. P. (2005). Solitude in the school: a neglected facet of children's development and education. Child. Educ. 81, 128–132. doi: 10.1080/00094056.2005.10522255
Galanaki, E. P. (2021). “The origins of beneficial solitude: psychoanalytic perspectives,” in The Handbook of Solitude: Psychological Perspectives on Social Isolation, Social Withdrawal, and the Experience of Being Alone, 2nd ed., eds R. J. Coplan, C. J. Bowker, and L. J. Nelson (New York, NY: Wiley-Blackwell), 58–74. doi: 10.1002/9781119576457.ch5
Gallagher, S. (2014). The cruel and unusual phenomenology of solitary confinement. Front. Psychol. 5, 585. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00585
Gratier, M., Devouche, E., Dominguez, S., and Apter, G. (2015). “What words can't tell: emotion and connection between ‘borderline' mothers and infants,” in Emotion in Language: Theory - Research - Application, ed U. M. Lüdtke (Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company), 399–420. doi: 10.1075/ceb.10.20gra
Gratier, M., and Trevarthen, C. (2007). Voice, vitality and meaning: on the shaping of the infant's utterances in willing engagement with culture. Comment on Bertau's “On the notion of voice”. Int. J. Dialogical Sci. 2, 169–181.
Hobson, P. (2002). The Cradle of Thought: Exploring the Origins of Thinking. Oxford, UK: Macmillan Education.
Husserl, E. (1964). The Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness (ed M. Heidegger). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (2012). “Shared voices,” in Dialogic Formations: Investigations into the Origins and Development of the Dialogical Self, eds M.-C. Bertau, M. M. Goncalves, and P. T. F. Raggatt (Charlotte, NC: Information Age), 69–82.
Kugiumutzakis, G., Kokkinaki, T., Makrodimitraki, M., and Vitalaki, E. (2005). “Emotions in early mimesis,” in Emotional Development: Recent Research Advances, eds J. Nadel, and D. Muir (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press), 161–182. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198528845.003.0006
Kugiumutzakis, G., and Trevarthen, C. (2015). “Neonatal imitation,” in International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 16, 2nd ed., ed J. D. Wright (Oxford, UK: Elsevier), 481–488. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.23160-7
Malloch, S., and Trevarthen, C. (eds), (2009). Communicative Musicality: Exploring the Basis of Human Companionship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Murray, L., and Trevarthen, C. (1985). “Emotional regulation of interactions between two-month-olds and their mothers,” in Social Perception in Infants, eds T. M. Field, and N. A. Fox (Norwood, NJ: Ablex), 177–197.
Peplau, L. A., and Perlman, D. (1982). “Perspectives on loneliness,” in Loneliness: A Sourcebook of Current Theory, Research and Therapy, eds L. A. Peplau, and D. Perlman (New York, NY: Wiley), 1–18.
Quinodoz, J. M. (1993). The Taming of Solitude: Separation Anxiety in Psychoanalysis. London: Routledge.
Reddy, V. (2008). How Infants Know Minds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. doi: 10.4159/9780674033887
Reddy, V., and Trevarthen, C. (2004). What we learn about babies from engaging with their emotions. Zero Three 24, 9–15.
Smith, A. (1759). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. London: Printed for A. Millar, and A. Kincaid and J. Bell. doi: 10.1093/oseo/instance.00042831
Stern, D. N. (1993). “The role of feelings for an interpersonal self,” in The Perceived Self: Ecological and Interpersonal Sources of the Self-Knowledge, ed U. Neisser (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press), 205–215. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511664007.012
Stern, D. N. (2000). The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology (with a new introduction by the author D. N. Stern). New York, NY: Basic Books.
Trevarthen, C. (1977). “Descriptive analyses of infant communicative behavior,” in Studies in Mother-Infant Interaction, ed H. R. Schaffer (London: Academic Press), 227–270.
Trevarthen, C. (1980). “The foundations of intersubjectivity: development of interpersonal and cooperative understanding in infants,” in The Social Foundation of Language and Thought, ed D. Olson (New York: Norton), 316–342.
Trevarthen, C. (1993). “The function of emotions in early infant communication and development,” in New Perspectives in Early Communicative Development, eds J. Nadel, and L. Camaioni (London: Routledge), 48–81. doi: 10.4324/9781315111322-5
Trevarthen, C. (1998). “The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity,” in Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny, ed. S. Bräten (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press), 15–46.
Trevarthen, C. (2001). Intrinsic motives for companionship in understanding: their origin, development, and significance for infant mental health. Infant Ment. Health J. 22, 95–131. doi: 10.1002/1097-0355(200101/04)22:1<95::AID-IMHJ4>3.0.CO;2-6
Trevarthen, C. (2002). Making sense of infants making sense. Intellectica 1, 161–188. doi: 10.3406/intel.2002.1078
Trevarthen, C. (2003). Infant psychology is an evolving culture. Hum. Dev. 46, 233–246. doi: 10.1159/000070372
Trevarthen, C. (2004a). “How infants learn how to mean,” in A Learning Zone of One's Own, eds M. Tokoro, and L. Steels (Amsterdam: IOS Press), 37–69.
Trevarthen, C. (2005a). “Action and emotion in development of the human self, its sociability and cultural intelligence: why infants have feelings like ours,” in Emotional Development: Recent Research Advances, eds J. Nadel, and D. Muir (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 61–91. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198528845.003.0003
Trevarthen, C. (2005b). First things first: infants make good use of the sympathetic rhythm of imitation, without reason or language. J. Child Psychother. 31, 91–113. doi: 10.1080/00754170500079651
Trevarthen, C. (2005c). “Stepping away from the mirror: pride and shame in adventures of companionship - reflections on the nature and emotional needs of infant intersubjectivity,” in Attachment and Bonding: A New Synthesis, eds C. S. Carter, L. Ahnert, K. E. Grossmann, S. B. Hrdy, M. E. Lamb, S. W. Porges, et al. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 55–84.
Trevarthen, C. (2008). The musical art of infant conversation: narrating in the time of sympathetic experience, without rational interpretation, before words. Musicae Sci. 12, 15–46. doi: 10.1177/1029864908012001021
Trevarthen, C. (2009). “Human biochronology: on the source and functions of ‘musicality',” in Music that works: Contributions of Biology, Neurophysiology, Psychology, Sociology, Medicine, and Musicology, eds R. Haas, and V. Brandes (New York, NY: Springer), 221–265. doi: 10.1007/978-3-211-75121-3_16
Trevarthen, C. (2011a). What it is like to be a person who knows nothing? Defining the active intersubjective mind of a newborn human being. Infant Child Dev. 20, 119–135. doi: 10.1002/icd.689
Trevarthen, C. (2011b). What young children give to their learning, making education work to sustain a community and its culture. Eur. Early Child. Educ. Res. 19, 173–193. doi: 10.1080/1350293X.2011.574405
Trevarthen, C. (2013). “Section I: commentary: born for art, and the joyful companionship of fiction,” in Evolution, Early Experience and Human Development: From Research to Practice and Policy, eds D. Narvaez, J. Panksepp, A. N. Schore, and T. R. Gleason (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 202–218. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199755059.003.0012
Trevarthen, C. (2014). “XII. Communicative musicality and infant mental health,” in Recherches en Périnatalité, eds. N. Presme, P. Delion, and S. Missonnier (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France), 213–246. doi: 10.3917/puf.pres.2014.01.0213
Trevarthen, C. (2015). Awareness of infants: what do they, and we, seek? Psychoanal. Inq. 35, 395–416. doi: 10.1080/07351690.2015.1022488
Trevarthen, C. (2016). “From the intrinsic motive pulse of infant actions, to the life time of cultural meanings,” in Philosophy and Psychology of Time, eds B. Mölder, V. Arstila, and P. Øhrstrom (Dordrecht: Springer), 225–265. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-22195-3_12
Trevarthen, C. (2019). “The psychobiology of the human spirit,” in Early Interaction and Developmental Psychopathology: Vol. 1. Infancy, eds G. Apter, E. Devouche, and M. Gratier (Cham, Switzerland: Springer), 1–18. doi: 10.1007/978-3-030-04769-6_1
Trevarthen, C. (2022). “Caring for the human spirit in pride and shame,” in Shame Matters: Attachment and Relational Perspectives for Psychotherapists, ed O. B. Epstein (New York, NY: Routledge), 21–45. doi: 10.4324/9781003175612-3
Trevarthen, C., and Aitken, K. J. (2001). Infant intersubjectivity: research, theory, and clinical applications. J. Child Psychol. Psychiatry 42, 3–48. doi: 10.1111/1469-7610.00701
Trevarthen, C., and Aitken, K. J. (2003). “Regulation of brain development and age-related changes in infants' motives: the developmental function of regressive periods,” in Regression Periods in Human Infancy, ed M. Heimann (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum), 107–184.
Trevarthen, C., Aitken, K. J., Vandekerckhove, M., Delafield-Butt, J., and Nagy, E. (2006). “Collaborative regulations of vitality in early childhood: stress in intimate relationships and postnatal psychopathology,” in Developmental Psychopathology: Developmental Neuroscience, eds D. Cicchetti, and D. J. Cohen (New York, NY: Wiley), 65–126. doi: 10.1002/9780470939390.ch2
Trevarthen, C., and Delafield-Butt, J. (2017). “Development of consciousness,” in Cambridge Encyclopedia of Child Development, 2nd ed., eds B. Hopkins, E. Geangu, and S. Linkenauger (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press), 821–835. doi: 10.1017/9781316216491.131
Trevarthen, C. (2004b). “Learning about ourselves, from children: why a growing human brain needs interesting companions?” in Research and[[Inline Image]] Clinical Center for Child Development, Annual Report, 26, 9–44.
Wertsch, J. V. (1991). Voices of the Mind: A Sociocultural Approach to Mediated Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Winnicott, D. W. (1965). The Maturational Processes and the Facilitating Environment. New York, NY: International Universities Press.
Keywords: loneliness, solitude, intersubjectivity, emotion, motive, sharing, culture
Citation: Galanaki E (2023) Loneliness and intersubjectivity: A view from Trevarthen's theory. Front. Psychol. 14:1145739. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.1145739
Received: 16 January 2023; Accepted: 17 February 2023;
Published: 09 March 2023.
Edited by:
Jonathan T. Delafield-Butt, University of Strathclyde, United KingdomReviewed by:
Shaun Gallagher, University of Memphis, United StatesCopyright © 2023 Galanaki. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Evangelia Galanaki, ZWdhbGFuYWtpJiN4MDAwNDA7cHJpbWVkdS51b2EuZ3I=