- Department of Philosophy, Neuroscience Institute, Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA, United States
Introduction: a Difference Worth Measuring
What does it mean to have “strong beliefs”? My thesis is that it can mean two very different things. That is, there are two distinct psychological features to which “strong belief” can refer, and these often come apart. I call the first feature epistemic confidence and the second identity centrality. They are conceptually distinct and, if we take ethnographies of religion seriously, distinct in fact as well. If that's true, it's methodologically important for the psychological sciences to have measures that tease them apart.
Epistemic Confidence vs. Identity Centrality
The following hypothetical case illustrates the distinction.
Johan (a young Afrikaner man) frequently insists that his deceased father was an opponent of Apartheid in the 1970s and 1980s. This is part of the standard narrative of his family history he gives to people he meets. Yet privately he knows he doesn't have that much evidence it's true, and sometimes he suspects his father just told him that to make himself look good.
Johan also has a great deal of certain knowledge of various things that matter little to him. He knows Istanbul used to be called Constantinople, one is technically not a prime, and Toyota has manufacturing facilities in South Africa.
In this case, identity centrality and epistemic confidence come apart in both directions. Johan has a high degree of identity centrality for the idea that his father opposed Apartheid (that idea is part of his social identity), but he has a low degree of epistemic confidence in that idea (he's not sure it's true). Conversely, he has a high degree of epistemic confidence that Istanbul used to be called Constantinople, but that same idea, for him, has a low degree of identity centrality—if it has any.
The difference between the two psychological features is also apparent in real-world ethnographies of religion. I focus here on ethnographies of The Vineyard Church (a large, representative American Evangelical sect1) by Luhrmann (2012) and Bialecki (2017). A central practice of the Vineyard is “hearing” the voice of God, where this typically involves having internal auditory mental imagery. Yet Vineyard members often speak of such experiences like this: “Sometimes when we think it's the spirit moving, it's just our burrito from lunch” and “There's always a choice to believe what it is” (Luhrmann, 2012, p. 70). Relatedly, Bialecki notes that Vineyard members commonly joke about the difficulty of determining whether the feelings they're having are from God or from the pizza they had for lunch. Hence, Vineyard members are often unsure (epistemically unconfident) that God spoke to them. Uncertainty is apparent also in that they describe it as a “choice” to believe and commonly find it difficult to “believe,” as do members1 of other Christian sects (Appiah, 2019, p. 37–38). Vineyard members often struggle with doubt. One Vineyard member even said, “I don't believe it. But I'm sticking with it. That's my definition of faith” (Luhrmann, 2012, p. 316). I propose that this cluster of phenomena can best be explained by positing that many Vineyard members have a low degree of epistemic confidence in their “beliefs,” while those “beliefs” are nevertheless central to their identities, which is why they keep showing up, putting in effort, and saying things like “I'm sticking with it.” Without being confident that their “beliefs” describe how things really are, they maintain them because of who they are (cf. Heiphetz et al., 2014).
To capture the difference in question, let the following serve as working definitions that can be refined through iterative stages of empirical inquiry and theoretical reflection.
Epistemic confidence: The degree to which someone feels a belief state approximates knowledge.
(Knowledge, for purposes of this definition, implies clear contents, objective truth, and rational justification2.)
Identity centrality: The degree to which someone experiences a belief state as part of their social identity.
(Social identity, for purposes of this definition, is a cluster of psychological states and behavioral dispositions that constitute someone as a member of an actual or potential in-group, or that an individual uses to achieve a desired social position3.)
To be clear, I am not suggesting that identity centrality is more important than epistemic confidence, or vice versa. They are just different psychological features that should not be confused. So now let's examine how some current measures of “belief” in psychology of religion fare in light of this distinction4.
On Fullerton and Hunsberger's (1982) “Christian Orthodoxy Scale,” respondents write down integers ranging from −3 (“strongly disagree”) to +3 (“strongly agree”) next to various claims. For example: “God exists as: Father, Son, and Holy Spirit,” “Man is not a special creature made in the image of God, he is simply a recent development in the process of animal evolution” (where this is contrary to Christian orthodoxy), “Jesus Christ was the divine Son of God,” etc.
No doubt the Fullerton and Hunsberger scale captures something important about religious psychology in that it measures Christian orthodoxy in some sense. But suppose a researcher administered the scale to a group of participants and most of them put “+3” next to all orthodox items and “−3” next to all contra-orthodox items. Would that researcher know whether the “+3” and “−3” responses were driven more by epistemic confidence or more by identity centrality? She would not. The reason why is that either psychological feature could cause a participant to put down “+3” next to the orthodox items. People who are epistemically confident an idea is true will typically be motivated to express “strong agreement” with it (conversely for disagreement), but so will people for whom that idea is central to their identity. So the Fullerton and Hunsberger scale doesn't capture this important difference.
To put the point abstractly, for any proposition p, a person with a high degree of epistemic confidence that p and a person with a high degree of identity centrality for p are both likely to put “+3” next to a sentence expressing p. So the scale does not discriminate.
Furthermore, if we trust the ethnographies just mentioned, this is a domain in which we might expect the two features to come apart. A researcher might hypothesize that many orthodox Christians are high in identity centrality with respect to orthodox beliefs, while being low or lower in epistemic confidence. The scale itself, however, would not help test that hypothesis.
This is not the place for an exhaustive catalog of belief measures, but it is worth observing how some prominent measures tilt toward one psychological feature or another, while others are entirely ambiguous between them.
In developmental psychology, Paul Harris has initiated a cross-cultural research program that compares people's confidence (probed in various ways) in the existence of scientific entities (e.g., germs, oxygen, etc.) to their confidence in the existence of supernatural entities of their religions (God, angels, etc.). Findings indicate that, even in religious societies like the United States and Iran, children and adults alike generally have lower degrees of confidence in religious than in scientific entities (Harris et al., 2006; Davoodi et al., 2018; Clegg et al., 2019). Measurement instruments in this line of research tilt in the direction of tracking epistemic confidence, but it is hard to rule out that identity centrality is also playing a role in driving some of the “confident” responses concerning religious entities. Hence, the findings could understate people's difference in epistemic confidence concerning scientific and religious entities.
Within social psychology of religion, some measures do help track identity centrality. Lindeman et al. (2020), for example, have items that probe how desirable religiosity is for respondents, whether they take religion to be harmful, and the degree of strong emotions elicited by religion. They also ask directly: “How important are religious attitudes to your identity?” Such questions are indeed useful in tracking the identity centrality. But they do not offer much in terms of assessing whether and how epistemic confidence and identity centrality converge or diverge. They also do not assess those psychological features in relation to specific religious doctrines and stories, such as the existence of a triune God or the Virgin Birth.
In psychology of religion more generally, there are indeed measures that track adherence to specific belief contents, but (like Fullerton and Hunsberger) without distinguishing epistemic confidence and identity centrality. Jong et al. (2013), for example, include these items: “There exists an all-powerful, all-knowing, loving God,” “Some people will go to Heaven when they die,” etc. Their scale runs from −4 (strongly disagree) to +4 (strongly agree). They write, “The two ends of the scale are therefore designed to indicate extreme disbelief or atheism... and confident belief... whereas the midpoint of the scale (i.e., 0) implies agnosticism or uncertainty” (496). Other measures of “belief” have similar Likert scales (Tobacyk, 2004; Pennycook et al., 2012; e.g., Lindeman et al., 2015). The “strongly” in these scales is what's problematic: strong in which way—epistemic confidence or identity centrality? We don't know.
Discussion: Where Do We Go From Here?
But why, one might ask, should we want measures that separate those features? The answer is that the difference matters for both descriptive psychological research and for normative philosophical research.
With regards to descriptive psychology, I submit that epistemic confidence and identity centrality are likely to differ along the following practically important dimensions: formation conditions (how a given attitude is formed), extinction conditions (how a given attitude is extinguished), and action guidance (what sorts of behaviors that attitude generates and how). In other words, an epistemically confident belief that p is likely to be formed, be revised, and generate action differently from a belief that p that is central to one's identity.
The table above (Table 1) lays out likely differences. (Here, the properties of epistemic confidence are standard in literature on “degrees of belief” in decision theory and formal epistemology5.)
Much more can be said about each of these dimensions of variation. But the broad outlines are clear: Epistemic confidence is, with various exceptions, likely to respond to evidence and guide instrumentally rational actions; identity centrality is likely to respond to social pressures and guide in-group-oriented behavior and self-presentation. So this is a distinction that makes a host of differences.
With regards to normative philosophical research, it is fair to say that this distinction raises a range of questions. The most basic one is this: Should the norms of evidence and truth that seem clearly to apply to epistemic confidence transfer over to identity centrality? In point of fact, it seems that identity centrality is far less constrained by evidence. But should it be? This is an important question, whose answer I don't know, that the present work at least puts us in a position to ask more clearly. And if it turns out that the proper norms for the respective psychological features do differ, it is even more important to develop measurement tools that would detect which of the two phenomena we are dealing with for any given “belief” set. Otherwise we wouldn't know which norms are applicable in any given case.
One of the reasons, I suspect, why such tools are lacking is that teasing out the distinction using survey instruments is likely to be extremely hard. That is why the difference is easier to notice in ethnographies, which incorporate observation of non-verbal behavior and of more nuanced verbal behavior.
Yet building measurement scales would still be worth the attempt, and I suggest that the above chart could be used to generate proxies for the features in question in relation to specific belief contents. To what extent is one's belief (say) that God is triune constrained by evidence vs. being voluntarily chosen? To what extent is it likely to be rejected due to contrary evidence vs. value conflict with group leaders? Does it guide instrumental or symbolic actions? No doubt any such scale would elicit some noise in addition to signal. Nevertheless, appropriate measurement tools could well be crafted that get at important and striking differences in the ways people can and do have “strong” beliefs.
Author Contributions
The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.
Funding
This article is funded by Dr. Rüdiger Seitz, via the Volkswagen Foundation, Siemens Healthineers, and the Betz Foundation.
Conflict of Interest
The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Publisher's Note
All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.
Acknowledgments
The author thanks his research assistants who helped with this project: David Casey, Bilal Khan, and Trevor Rukwava. For feedback on earlier drafts, the author thanks Franz Dietrich, Kenny Easwaran, Paul Harris, Jonathan Jong, Gordon Pennycook, Rüdiger Seitz, and a referee. The author thanks Bence Nanay and the audience at the Center for Philosophical Psychology for discussion of a version I presented there. The author thanks Rüdiger Seitz, Hans-Ferdinand Angel, and the other participants at the Credition 2021 conference for discussion of the very first version of this paper.
Footnotes
1. ^The Vineyard is now an international movement, but it originated in the US and still has many features characteristic of American Evangelicalism.
2. ^This characterization of “knowledge” is intended for purposes of this definition only and not as a fundamental analysis of that term. Note also that I am not saying that an epistemically confident belief state must be knowledge—only that the person who has it must feel (to some degree) like it approximates knowledge.
3. ^The in-group in Johan's case would be socially liberal South Africans. I should also note that there are interesting relations between the two kinds of “strength.” In particular, one uses one's perceived knowledge about one's group to figure out what “beliefs” should be accorded identity centrality. So epistemic confidence does play a foundational role in relation to identity centrality, even if identity centrality guides symbolic behaviors that often seem to go against it. This is similar to the anti-symmetric cognitive governance relation I discuss in my (2014) paper, and I thank one anonymous referee for raising the issue.
4. ^I focus here on psychology of religion, but my points are likely to generalize to other sub-fields as well.
5. ^See also Van Leeuwen, 2014, 2017a,b, 2018 for parallel comparisons between factual belief, which has epistemic confidence, and religious credence, which has identity centrality.
References
Alcorta, C. S., and Sosis, R. (2005). Ritual, emotion, and sacred symbols. Hum. Nat. 16, 323–359. doi: 10.1007/s12110-005-1014-3
Bialecki, J. (2017). A Diagram for Fire. Oakland, CA: University of California Press. doi: 10.1525/california/9780520294202.001.0001
Bulbulia, J. (2004). The cognitive and evolutionary psychology of religion. Biol. Philos. 19, 655–686. doi: 10.1007/s10539-005-5568-6
Bulbulia, J. (2012). Spreading order: religion, cooperative niche construction, and risky coordination problems. Biol. Philos. 27, 1–27. doi: 10.1007/s10539-011-9295-x
Clegg, J. M., Cui, Y. K., Harris, P. L., and Corriveau, K. H. (2019). God, germs, and evolution: Belief in unobservable religious and scientific entities in the U.S. and China. Integr. Psychol. Behav. Sci. 53, 93–106. doi: 10.1007/s12124-019-9471-0
Davoodi, T., Jamshidi-Sianaki, M., Abedi, F., Payir, A., Cui, Y. K., Harris, P. L., and Corriveau, K. H. (2018). Beliefs about religious and scientific entities among parents and children in Iran. Soc. Psychol. Personal. Sci. 10, 847–855. doi: 10.1177/1948550618806057
Fullerton, J. T., and Hunsberger, B. (1982). A unidimensional measure of Christian orthodoxy. J. Sci. Study Relig. 21, 317–326. doi: 10.2307/1385521
Harris, P. L., Pasquini, E. S., Duke, S., Asscher, J. J., and Pons, F. (2006). Germs and angels: the role of testimony in young children's ontology. Dev. Sci. 9, 76–96. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2005.00465.x
Heiphetz, L., Spelke, E. S., Harris, P. L., and Banaji, M. R. (2014). What do different beliefs tell us? An examination of factual, opinion-based, and religious beliefs. Cognit. Dev. 30, 15–29. doi: 10.1016/j.cogdev.2013.12.002
Henrich, J. (2009). The evolution of costly displays, cooperation and religion. Evol. Hum. Behav. 30, 244–260. doi: 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2009.03.005
Jong, J., Bluemke, M., and Halberstadt, J. (2013). Fear of death and supernatural beliefs: Developing a new Supernatural Belief Scale to test the relationship. Eur. J. Pers. 27, 495–506. doi: 10.1002/per.1898
Lindeman, M., Marin, P., Schjoedt, U., and van Elk, M. (2020). Nonreligious identity in three Western European countries: a closer look at nonbelievers' self-identifications and attitudes towards religion. Int. J. Psychol. Relig. 30, 288–303. doi: 10.1080/10508619.2020.1746984
Lindeman, M., Svedholm-Häkkinen, A. M., and Lipsanen, J. (2015). Ontological confusions but not mentalizing abilities predict religious belief, paranormal belief, and belief in supernatural purpose. Cognition. 134, 63–76. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2014.09.008
Luhrmann, T. M. (2012). When God Talks Back: Understanding the American Evangelical Relationship With God. New York, NY: Vintage Books. doi: 10.24260/alalbab.v1i1.16
Luhrmann, T. M. (2020). How God Becomes Real: Kindling the Presence of Invisible Others. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. doi: 10.1515/9780691211985
Pennycook, G., Cheyne, J. A., Seli, P., Koehler, D. J., and Fugelsang, J. A. (2012). Analytic cognitive style predicts religious and paranormal belief. Cognition. 123, 335–346. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2012.03.003
Sauvayre, R. (2011). “Le changement de croyance extremes: du cadre cognitive aux conflits de valeurs,” Revue européenne des sciences sociales. Eur. J. Soc. Sci. 49, 61–82. doi: 10.4000/ress.830
Sosis, R., and Alcorta, C. (2003). Signaling, solidarity, and the sacred: the evolution of religious behavior. Evol. Anthropol. 12, 264–274. doi: 10.1002/evan.10120
Stark, R., and Finke, R. (2000). Acts of Faith: The Human Side of Religion. Oakland, CA: University of California Press.
Tobacyk, J. J. (2004). A revised paranormal belief scale. Int. J. Transpers. Stud. 23, 94–98. doi: 10.24972/ijts.2004.23.1.94
Van Leeuwen, N. (2014). Religious credence is not factual belief. Cognition. 133, 698–715. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2014.08.015
Van Leeuwen, N. (2017a). Do religious “beliefs” respond to evidence? Philos. Explor. 20, 52–72. doi: 10.1080/13869795.2017.1287294
Van Leeuwen, N. (2017b). Two paradigms for religious representation: the physicist and the playground (a reply to Levy). Cognition. 164, 206–211. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2017.03.021
Van Leeuwen, N. (2018). The factual belief fallacy. Contemp. Pragmatism. 15, 319–343. doi: 10.1163/18758185-01503004
Keywords: belief, credence, measurement, identity, epistemic confidence, identity centrality
Citation: Van Leeuwen N (2022) Two Concepts of Belief Strength: Epistemic Confidence and Identity Centrality. Front. Psychol. 13:939949. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.939949
Received: 10 May 2022; Accepted: 30 May 2022;
Published: 29 June 2022.
Edited by:
Rüdiger J. Seitz, Heinrich Heine University of Düsseldorf, GermanyReviewed by:
Carlos Montemayor, San Francisco State University, United StatesCopyright © 2022 Van Leeuwen. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Neil Van Leeuwen, nvan@gsu.edu