Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychol., 02 September 2022
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology
This article is part of the Research Topic Rising Ideas In: Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology View all 8 articles

Alternative Object Use in Adults and Children: Embodied Cognitive Bases of Creativity

  • Department of Education and Social Work, Institute for Lifelong Learning and Guidance, University of Luxembourg, Esch-sur-Alzette, Luxembourg

Why does one need creativity? On a personal level, improvisation with available resources is needed for online coping with unforeseen environmental stimuli when existing knowledge and apparent action strategies do not work. On a cultural level, the exploitation of existing cultural means and norms for the deliberate production of novel and valuable artifacts is a basis for cultural and technological development and extension of human action possibilities across various domains. It is less clear, however, how creativity develops and how exactly one arrives at generating new action possibilities and producing multiple alternative action strategies using familiar objects. In this theoretical paper, we first consider existing accounts of the creative process in the Alternative Uses Task and then present an alternative interpretation, drawing on sociocultural views and an embodied cognition approach. We explore similarities between the psychological processes underlying the generation of new uses in the Alternative Uses Task and children’s pretend play. We discuss possible cognitive mechanisms and speculate how the generation of new action possibilities for common objects in pretend play can be related to adults’ ability to generate new action strategies associated with object use. Implications for creativity development in humans and embodied artificial agents are discussed.

Introduction

Alongside intelligence, with which it shares common mechanisms (Haier and Jung, 2008; Benedek et al., 2014), creativity appears to be an indispensable element for individual flexibility and adaptation (Sternberg, 1999; Collins and Koechlin, 2012). Boden (1998) envisioned creativity on two levels—psychological “P-creativity,” which involves the production of novelty taken on an individual scale, and historical “H-creativity,” which is related to the production of ideas and artifacts that are fundamentally novel for the whole culture, on a historical scale.

Sociocultural (Glăveanu, 2010, 2011, 2020) and 4E cognition1 (Malinin, 2019) approaches to creativity suggest that, beyond idea generation, the function of creative cognition is to guide action. Although stemming from different philosophical backgrounds, the sociocultural approach (especially cultural-historical activity theory) and 4E cognition share common methodological endeavors. According to both approaches, human cognition is intertwined with the physical environment—objects, materials, and artifacts developed by humankind (Kaptelinin and Nardi, 2006; Glăveanu, 2013; Malafouris, 2014, 2018)2. On both accounts, cognition and action are codetermining. Modeling mental processes is thus not sufficient to understand human cognition; instead, it should be studied in relation to human activity and praxis (Bødker, 1997; Noë, 2004). Notably, an extended cognitive system containing tools becomes a key unit of analysis in the sociocultural approach and 4E cognition paradigm (Leont’ev, 1975, 1978; Vygotsky, 1983; Engeström, 1987; Clark, 1998; Glăveanu, 2013; Favela et al., 2021). Tools and manipulable physical devices are seen as an inseparable part of human cognition, extending users’ sensorimotor capabilities. Sociocultural views stress that a deliberate production of novel and valuable artifacts also relies on shared cultural means and tools, thus extending a personal adaptability account of creativity and assigning it a cultural role of transforming the sociocultural practices (Engeström, 1995, 2001; Miettinen, 1999; Miettinen and Virkkunen, 2005; Glăveanu, 2011).

The view that creativity is intimately related to tool3 use is inherent in the Alternative Uses Task (AUT), which psychologists use as a proxy to evaluate human creativity (Wilhelm and Kyllonen, 2021). Yet, the interpretation of important cognitive processes underlying the creative performance in this task has evolved mainly around associative and divergent-convergent accounts. These explanations might be viewed as “disembodied” since they disregard how ideas could be translated into actions and vice versa. Sensorimotor processes associated with object use and the contribution of sociocultural knowledge and conventions to the successful performance in the AUT have been underappreciated in creativity research. Inspired by the ideas of 4E approaches to cognition and sociocultural perspectives, we sketch an alternative, action-oriented and affordance-based interpretation of the performance in the Alternative Uses Task and speculate how sensorimotor embodiment and linguistic and social knowledge may contribute to the development of creative cognition.

In this article, we first review existing interpretations and possible accounts of successful performance in the AUT. We then attempt to interpret the creative process in the AUT through the lenses of embodied cognition and sociocultural approaches. We discuss the role of children’s pretend play in the development of creativity. Our aim is to consider how the interplay between language and action first manifests itself in children’s pretend play and is related to the mental generation of novel and useful action possibilities for common objects in adults. We also discuss implications for creativity promotion in humans and its emulation in embodied artificial agents. We conclude by pointing to the limitations of the work and outlining the future research agenda.

Existing Interpretations of the Alternative Uses Task

The idea of testing subjects’ creativity by their ability to adapt to situational constraints through improvising solutions and finding a substitute for the missing equipment has been investigated by psychologists since the beginning of the 20th century. Spearman, in his work “Creative mind” (1931), described Strasheim’s (1926) experiments, where children were placed in several situations and had to attain the same goal with different available materials. Guilford and colleagues (Wilson et al., 1953) developed the Alternative Uses Task, which has become a prototypical measure of creativity. In a sense, the AUT could be seen as a reversed Strasheim’s test: instead of fulfilling the same goal with varying objects, the AUT asks subjects to come up with multiple new purposes for the same common object or tool (within a time constraint). The novelty of Guilford’s approach consisted in the claim that what is important in this task is the divergent production—the ability to come up with many diverse, novel, and uncommon responses to an open-ended stimulus. Three metrics have been proposed to score the AUT responses, decomposing creativity into fluency (number of uses), originality (number of unique uses), and flexibility (number of conceptual categories that the generated uses could be binned into; Guilford, 1967; Kaufman et al., 2008).

Despite the “divergent thinking” origin of the AUT, it has been pointed out that the performance on this task also calls for convergent thinking (Wallach and Kogan, 1965; Wallach, 1970; Mumford et al., 1991). Specifically, in addition to idea generation, one has also to select solutions that meet the task’s constraints. Campbell’s early conceptualization of creativity described it as a process of Blind Variation and Selective Retention, which requires “a mechanism for introducing variation, a consistent selection process, and a mechanism for preserving and reproducing the selected variations” (Campbell, 1960, p. 381). According to the Blind Variation and Selective Retention (BVSR) model, the generation of novel uses in the AUT would consist of two distinct processes: an initial generation of uses and subsequent selection based on a person’s internal criteria. Johnson-Laird (1987) described three possible configurations of the BVSR account, which he called Neo-Darwinian, Neo-Lamarckian, and Multi-Stage algorithms4. The formalization of Johnson-Laird underscores the role of evaluation in the process of production of creative outcomes and points to the importance of existing domain standards and conventions as potential sources of evaluative metrics.

Another influential explanation of creativity—associative—claims that the generation of new and unconventional solutions stems from the personal ability to fluently retrieve and bridge remote concepts and ideas (Mednick, 1968; also Spearman, 1931; Koestler, 1964). According to this approach, the creative ability could be explained by the organization of an individual’s associative networks (Mednick, 1962). More specifically, in low creative people, a given verbal and/or visual stimulus (e.g., pencil) should evoke only salient and conventional items (a pattern Mednick called a steep associative hierarchy), whereas, in high creative people, a given verbal input should evoke not just a few salient associations, but also several distantly related ones (a pattern called a flat associative hierarchy). These links to more remotely connected concepts would lead to creative and unique answers. Although the theory could elegantly explain associative fluency and originality of solutions in the AUT, the approach remains relatively vague about the origins of such associative and semantic hierarchies (Kenett et al., 2014).

A possible mechanism for identifying correspondences between semantically distant domains was further specified by Gentner (1983). She proposed the concept of analogical mapping, which refers to the transfer of similar structural relations5 between elements from a known domain or situation to a new one. According to Gentner, a key element in knowledge mapping is similarity comparison between structures of the source and target situations. While Structure Mapping theory explains how analogies are made from already existing structures, the theory still does not answer the question of where the structures come from. The case-based reasoning6 approach partially remedies this gap and states that new problems draw on past experience, which is stored as cases and is retrieved, adapted, evaluated, and retained (Kolodner, 1992).

Recognizing the critical role of mapping, Sternberg (1986a,b) and Chalmers et al. (1992) drew attention to the importance of the initial encoding of information. They believed that perception must be accounted for in a model of analogical thought and creative cognition. For Davidson and Sternberg (1986), seeing visual stimulus’ features that previously have been nonobvious is crucial for updating the representation of the problem. Applying the analogy account to the solution generation process in the AUT, one of the possible strategies to come up with new uses for a brick would be to notice and encode a relevant feature in a given object (e.g., weight), retrieve knowledge from past experience where a heavy object was used, extract the goal or final effect of this use, and make a mapping of it from known to the current problem.

Benedek et al. (2014) further studied the role of attentional mechanisms that underlie the performance in the AUT. They found that two executive processes—inhibition and updating of the information in working memory—are important for the creative process. It has been argued that while updating helps to keep track of generated ideas and to refresh relevant object features (thus, facilitating idea generation), inhibition helps to filter most common and non-original responses (thus, contributing to idea evaluation and selection).

Finally, a different and insightful account of the performance in the AUT has been proposed by Gilhooly et al. (2007), who redescribed the AUT as a heuristic task that could be accomplished by different cognitive processes. The authors analyzed verbal reports and showed that the task could be solved via various heuristic tools—strategies—discovered by participants during the AUT response generation. Notably, these strategies determine the degree of novelty of produced ideas. Gilhooly and colleagues found that whereas an initial generation of uses relies on extant knowledge and its retrieval from episodic long-term memory, the generation of genuinely novel uses is related to more exploratory strategies that occur later in the task.7 These later strategies to create novelty are mental decomposition of the object and its property use. The authors suggested that the creation of highly novel uses may rely either on amodal semantic representations or mental imagery—much like in mental rotation and scanning tasks (Shepard and Metzler, 1971; Kosslyn, 1980; Finke, 1989; LeBoutillier and Marks, 2003).

Taken together, the alternative uses in the AUT could be the result of (1) a variety of personal experiences; (2) the ability to retrieve memories; (3) flexible attentional control—the ability to switch attention from one object’s feature to another and inhibit salient responses; (4) mapping abilities; and (5) the ability to discover and make use of strategies facilitating task completion. While the first two factors are related to long-term memory, factors 3–5 are determined by one’s working memory and executive processes (Gilhooly et al., 2007; Nusbaum and Silvia, 2011; Lee and Therriault, 2013; Benedek et al., 2014). A visual summary of the discussed accounts of the cognitive processes underlying the AUT is presented in Figure 1.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Cognitive processes posited by existing accounts of creativity. Images sourced with permission from Nfsphoto/Dreamstime; Mishoo/Dreamstime. Other images author’s own creation.

This brief overview highlights that the task demanding the production of creative responses (i.e., combining high novelty and high utility) necessitates recruiting different cognitive processes and developing strategies to achieve the proposed goal. Several important questions remained unanswered, however. Specifically, what is the role of objects in the creative process? How does one come up with novel uses without a real object and the possibility to manipulate it? Ultimately, what exactly do we test with the Alternative Uses Task?

The Complexity of the AUT and Human Object Use

What makes the Alternative Use Task difficult? First of all, in the AUT agents have to think about an object which is not currently present in the environment. Within the embodied cognition research paradigm this type of task has been called a representation-hungry problem (Clark and Toribio, 1994). The distinction has been made between offline cognition, which takes place in the mental domain and is environmentally decoupled (Wilson, 2002), and online, or situated cognition, which allows manipulating the environment in order to offload cognitive demands into the surroundings.

In the ecological-enactive cognition approach, objects use has been associated with detecting and exploiting information about affordances—what an organism can do with an object or a surface based on its capabilities (Vicente and Rasmussen, 1990; Lockman, 2000; Lockman and Kahrs, 2017; Mangalam et al., 2022). The term “affordance” was coined by Gibson (1979) to emphasize that the agent does not simply process physical properties of the environment (like color, shape, or distance) but rather picks up those dispositional properties that allow to organize the behavior and act on the environment (Rochat and Reed, 1987).

The Torrance Thinking Creatively in Action and Movement test (Torrance, 1981) could be a good example to illustrate the workings of online creative cognition in a concrete situation. The test was conceived by Torrance to rule out the requirement to answer verbally for children starting from 3 years old. As its name suggests, the test allows children to express their creativity through action and body movements with the object. One of the tasks may be seen as an embodied Alternative Uses Task: it invites a child to play with a paper cup and find different uses for it. In contrast to the AUT, which suggests that subjects will create new and original uses for a common object relying solely on unaided mental capacity, the Torrance Test for children provides a real object and allows a direct exploration of its affordances through motor activity. Children can come up with different ways to use the cup by manipulating and examining possible actions and physical properties of the cup (see also Hoicka et al., 2013). Although the test has traditionally been interpreted in terms of fluency and originality of the proposed uses, we suggest that it could alternatively reflect a child’s ability to discover new strategies for action and thus characterize a child’s engagement with a field of relevant affordances. Rietveld and Kiverstein (2014) argued that an individual field of relevant affordances may be measured by the scope of affordances the individual is open to, salience of available opportunities for action, and depth of anticipation, i.e., how far one can transcend the here and now in planning possible actions (see Rietveld and Kiverstein, 2014; Rietveld et al., 2018 for the description).

Although almost any object offers multiple possibilities for action and potential use, within the members of a given culture object’s use is typically based on a shared convention about the object’s canonical function (Moro and Rodrígez, 2005; Costall, 2012; Dimitrova et al., 2015). This view is inherent in sociocultural theory which claims that beyond providing numerous possibilities for action, human tools and artifacts also represent a way of transmission of cultural knowledge (Leont’ev, 1978; Alessandroni and Rodríguez, 2019). Specifically, according to a sociocultural perspective, the use of human artifacts and tools implies two aspects. The technical aspect refers to the operational side of tool use, with a focus on the properties of the object, its perceptual-motor requirements, and conditions for its implementation in action. The cultural dimension concerns the socially expected or canonical way of performing an action with an object8 (El’konin, 1978; Ramstead et al., 2016; see also McNeill, 1992; Clark, 1996; Goldin-Meadow, 2003; Kendon, 2004).

This distinction between an object’s cultural function and other possible operations afforded by the object (Tomasello, 1999) allows capturing the second main source of difficulty in the AUT. The so-called phenomenon of “functional fixedness” entails that the canonical function associated with an object—what the object is commonly used for—may constrain other potential and non-canonical uses and make it difficult to conceptualize and apply the object in other than conventional ways (Luchins, 1942; Duncker, 1945). The phenomenon is thus related to the salience dimension of an individual’s affordances field and manifests itself in the perceptual dominance of a particular action possibility in relation to other affordances.

It has been proposed that an object’s conventional function is inherent in the key meaning of the word used to name it (Awaad et al., 2015; Srinivasan and Rabagliati, 2021). Specifically, Awaad et al.’s (2015, p. 423) insight consists in the proposition that canonical affordances are captured and could thus be “mined” from language dictionaries as “they provide concise and unambiguous definitions of objects that almost always include their function.” This view is in dialogue with a pragmatic perspective, which considers objects’ cultural functions as a conceptual foundation (Alessandroni and Rodríguez, 2019; Alessandroni, 2021). This entails that when reasoning about objects, one typically refers to their conventional affordances. The difficulty to reinterpret the object use may thus be partially explained by language and how one extracts affordances from words.

Experiments in psycholinguistics provide indirect evidence to support this claim. Studies show that the way one categorizes and names the experimental objects affects the principal way how these objects are used (Katz and Hussey, 2011), and what action possibilities are perceived as available. For example, categorizing and naming an object as a “box of tacks” in Dunker’s candle problem (Duncker, 1945) would not allow the same action possibilities as labeling it as a “box and the tacks” and would result in different solution rates.

This hypothesis linking language, affordances, and the conventional way of performing an action suggests that these variables may be equally important and relevant for understanding the performance in the AUT.

Vygotsky (1983) has expressed the linguistic and cultural mediation of higher mental functions by a scheme (Figure 2) which illustrates how symbols are grounded in perception and suggests that human cognitive processes are vicariant, i.e., functionally substitutable (Cole and Engestrom, 1993; see also Hammond, 1981). In other words, any pursued goal involving object use could be attained by relying on direct perception (Vygotsky called it the “natural route”), on the one hand, and by leveraging crystallized knowledge (the “cultural route,” which includes mediation by sign and symbols), on the other hand.9 This schema indicating the existence of dual routes for action (see also Humphreys, 2001) may help to envision a way to bypass the pitfalls and complexities of the AUT.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Mediational triangle. Adapted from Vygotsky (1983).

The Alternative Interpretations of the AUT

Sociocultural, embodied, and enactive accounts of difficulties in the AUT allow us to reconsider the cognitive bases of the AUT. Instead of opting for purely cognitive accounts or suggesting that the Alternative Uses Task tests the ability to come up with new and original ideas, we argue that the AUT actually measures an individual’s ability to create and extend one’s action possibilities with an object. In our view, the process of generating new uses for a common object unfolds as an alternation between exploitation of existing knowledge and exploration of potentialities. This hypothesis is supported by the findings of Gilhooly et al. (2007), which show that cognitive strategies leading to novel solutions are inextricably action-oriented. They can be viewed as virtual actions, where participants divide and reassemble an object, investigate its properties, and examine potential movements it affords. Figure 3 depicts a possible mapping of strategies on the exploitation-exploration continuum according to the potential novelty of their outcome.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. Cognitive strategies used by participants in the Alternative Uses Task (AUT).

What mechanisms may support the ability to plan and explore potential actions with an object without direct access to it? Three kinds of explanations have been proposed from an embodied cognition perspective (Sanches de Oliveira et al., 2019). According to the first approach, novel uses may consist in the simulation of sensorimotor experience associated with tools (Matheson and Kenett, 2020). Although the simulation used to be considered a potential heuristic to deal with problems involving high uncertainty (Kahneman and Tversky, 1982; Galinsky and Moskowitz, 2000; Ball and Christensen, 2009), Matheson and Kenett (2020) reviewed neuroimaging studies and provided neural evidence of simulations of tool-related actions during the generation of creative uses in the AUT. This data is in line with studies of episodic future thinking (Schacter et al., 2017; see also Schacter et al., 2012), which stress the role of an individual’s ability to recollect past personal experiences. The authors suggested that sensorimotor re-enactment and mental exploration of outcomes of such actions (Matheson and Kenett, 2021; see also Jeannerod, 2001; Witt and Proffitt, 2008) may be an effective strategy to come up with novel alternative uses.

The second approach claims that temporarily scaled-up affordances may support long-horizon planning, the ability to go beyond the here and now and anticipate several steps into the future (Kiverstein and Rietveld, 2018; see also Gibson, 1979; Gallagher, 2017). This idea is reflected in the aforementioned depth dimension of an individual’s set of relevant affordances proposed by Rietveld and Kiverstein (2014) which refers to individuals’ temporal horizon of anticipation and the ability to engage in distal actions. The evidence shows that high creativity is indeed associated with the expertise in imagining distal futures (Meyer et al., 2019).

The third explanation proposed by the Material Engagement Theory radically states that material artifacts mediate, enact, and constitute cognitive processes (Malafouris, 2014, 2018). Creative cognition is thus best understood not as thinking about objects but as creative thinging, i.e., thinking with, through, and about materials and things. According to this theory, online cognition (i.e., thinking through and with material things) is not conceptually different from offline cognition (thinking about things) but has a “developmental and evolutionary priority” (Malafouris, 2021, p. 108; see also Gill, 2010).

Finally, based on Vygotsky’s idea of two routes of action, we suggest the fourth account, according to which new strategies for action may be the result of combining sensorimotor information related to affordances with the information pertaining to the canonical object use. In other words, language may be used as a tool to reinterpret the meaning of an object and construct new ad hoc categories (Barsalou, 1983, 1991; Borghi et al., 2019). A tentative model of response generation in the AUT is shown in Figure 4.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. A tentative model of response generation in the AUT. Similar to the naming and action model (Yoon et al., 2002), it posits an interaction between semantic and sensorimotor routes to action. Images sourced with permission from Syda Productions/Adobe Stock; Icefront/Dreamstime; Nfsphoto/Dreamstime; Mishoo/Dreamstime. Other images author’s own creation.

Pretend Play and the Creation of New Affordances

Vygotsky (1967) argued that children’s play combines symbolic, contextual, and sensorimotor components and may thus hold the key to understanding an imaginative construction of hypothetical events and actions. Below we will follow Vygotsky’s proposal and investigate how the internal mechanics of play could enact creative cognition and contribute to the development of the ability to generate non-conventional uses.

It has been proposed that early prelinguistic sensorimotor explorations of objects’ properties and experience of action on objects are necessary prerequisites for play and creative endeavors (Kravtsova, 1996; Pellegrini and Hou, 2011; Pellegrini, 2013; Nonaka and Goldfield, 2018). This manipulative motor experience allows a child to learn about the effects of their actions on objects (Keen, 2011; Schulz, 2015; Stahl and Feigenson, 2015) and explore the relationship between multiple hidden objects’ affordances, which will be later used in play and creative problem-solving endeavors involving tool use (Smith and Dutton, 1979; Lockman, 2000; Lobo and Galloway, 2008; Adolph and Robinson, 2015; Lockman and Kahrs, 2017). Such active interaction with objects may be seen as the vehicle by which children learn complex action-environment links and means-ends relationships. This idea has been empirically confirmed by Bruner (1975), who showed that the possibility to manipulate materials allowed children to use these materials as tools to solve an unseen practical problem. Bruner observed that playful exploration of materials prior to problem presentation led to problem-solving rates comparable to children who saw how adults performed the task (see also Dansky and Silverman, 1973, 1975; Li, 1978; Dansky, 1980). A similar positive effect of object exploration on test performance has been obtained in the domain of mental rotation. When allowed to perform manual rotations during the training phase, school-aged children performed better at the subsequent mental rotation test (Wiedenbauer and Jansen-Osmann, 2008). Such results suggest that active interaction with objects enacts creative cognition and allows children to build associations between actions and effects in multi-modal sensorimotor spaces and thus better predict the outcome of their actions.

In parallel with self-directed multimodal explorations, children’s direct perception is also shaped by adults. The core mechanism of learning cultural norms and conventional affordances is the synergy of language (Vygotsky, 1983) and joint action (Tomasello, 1999, 2014; Ramstead et al., 2016; Nonaka and Stoffregen, 2020). This synergy allows adults to guide and “educate” children’s attention toward the relevant object’s affordances and demonstrate their socially expected use. As a result, children create referential connections between an object’s conventional function and its name (Nelson, 1974), and by the age of two toddlers become aware that each object has its function (Russ and Christian, 2011, but see Rossmanith et al., 2014 for the evidence that this happens much earlier), recognize and spontaneously produce key (iconic) movements associated with objects’ use (Harris et al., 1993; Rakoczy and Tomasello, 2006; Tolar et al., 2008; Behne et al., 2014), and generalize the objects’ names in accordance with their functions10 (Kemler Nelson et al., 2000). Presumably, conventional affordances and socially accepted properties of objects guide an individual’s attention in everyday situations where objects become perceived by their most common action possibilities (Defeyter and German, 2003; Ye et al., 2009).

According to the sociocultural theory, in pretend play two routes of development converge and allow a child to create novelty by leveraging mechanisms of sociocultural conventions and direct perception (Figure 2). The basic feature of play, according to Vygotsky, is the creation of an imaginary situation—a situation where visual and semantic fields diverge (Vygotsky, 1967; Bodrova and Leong, 2007). This feature may be found in one form of pretend play, object substitution, which requires temporarily suppressing the canonical action of the object while performing an action that is typical for another object (Tomasello et al., 1999). When a child enacts an imaginary situation and claims: “This is not a shoehorn, this is a bow!” she demonstrates not only her knowledge of a canonical affordance of the object but also the ability to deliberately transfer it from one object to another (Davydov, 1992; Kravtsova, 1996; see also Rodríguez et al., 2014; Palacios and Rodríguez, 2015). In this process, language plays an important role in allowing the child to manipulate information about an object that is not present in the immediate environment and label her interpretation of the object over the visual field. At the same time, perceptual experience also has an important role in object substitution in pretend play. The mechanism for transfer function from one object to another is not arbitrary. It has been shown that to be used instead of another one, a prop in pretend play should afford the same action or gesture as a missing object11 (El’konin, 1978; Vygotsky, 1983; see also Landau et al., 1988; Smith, 2005). Hence, in pretend play involving object substitution, a child has to first perceive a particular affordance of the prop (Dent-Read, 1997; Szokolszky and Read, 2021).

The substitution mechanism could be described in terms of the double-stimulation method12 (Vygotsky, 1983; van der Veer and Valsiner, 1991; Engeström, 2007; Sannino, 2015), which implies turning an initially neutral stimulus into a relevant tool. The method has been developed to show that when given a challenging task (first stimulus), children pick up and exploit available materials (secondary or “sign” stimuli) as effective means to solve the task. In pretend play, when resources are limited and the desired object is not available in the immediate environment, children are likely to pick up and exploit affordances of available props. If some object allows for an action similar to that of a missing one, they attribute a linguistic label of the missing entity to this object. For example, if an object (e.g., pencil) affords piercing, it could be reinterpreted as a needle or awl (Gibson, 1979, p. 133; see also Kemler Nelson, 1999). As a result, in pretense, a child brings into being a new use for a common object based on intended (by the child) and afforded (by the object) action. This mechanism bears resemblance with the aforementioned strategy to generate new uses in the AUT, where a person could pick up an affordance of a common object and then label it with the word corresponding to another object’s canonical affordance.

What competencies related to creativity may the mechanics of pretend play possibly affect? First, in pretend play, children learn that beyond its conventional function and name, a physical object could be designated by different words depending on the intended use and afforded by an object’s action. Language use and associated motor and sensory experiences that arise in multimodal object-oriented play may affect how easily one extracts affordances from words and promote the development of lexical polysemy and behavioral flexibility. This hypothesis is in line with recent evidence showing that children can leverage their sensorimotor (especially visuospatial) experience to infer the new meaning of words (Xu et al., 2017; Starr et al., 2021; see also Srinivasan and Rabagliati, 2021). Thus, beyond playing with objects in pretend play, children are also playing with words and creating new meanings, bridging otherwise “remote” concepts. Word-referent mappings and links created between words’ meanings in pretend play may influence how knowledge is structured and retrieved from memory, and presumably may underlie the aforementioned “flatter” associative hierarchies in creative people (Mednick, 1962; Kenett et al., 2014).

Second, by transferring canonical functions from one object to another, children generate new object substitutions and practice a deliberate creation of new action possibilities for objects beyond their usual uses. This feature has been emphasized as crucially important for creativity (Pellegrini, 2013). Withagen and van der Kamp (2018, p. 1), for example, defined creativity as “the discovery and creation of unconventional affordances of objects and materials.” In a similar vein, Glăveanu (2012) associated creativity with the exploration of environmental affordances otherwise unavailable to the person due to their unperceived, uninvented, or unexploited character.

Third, the discovery and use of nonapparent object proprieties and their potential effects in pretend play could enable building better predictive models of the world (Andersen et al., 2021), leading to better action planning and the ability to mentally enact possible future actions. Inevitably, better abilities to predict the effects of their actions and mentally enact possible future actions would enable better coping with unexpected events.

Finally, playing with objects’ conventional functions may help to further acquire the information about expected and, more importantly, socially unexpected, i.e., novel or surprising object applications. Osiurak et al. (2009) have found a strong association between the ability to demonstrate the conventional use of objects and the ability to generate the unusual use for them, suggesting that a correct way of performing an action establishes a kind of benchmark for evaluating novel uses (see also Chylińska and Gut, 2020 for a relevant discussion). In fact, the level of surprise could be defined as the difference between the expected (i.e., normative, conventional) use of an object and the actual use performed by the child. Creative actors could leverage this information about “normativity” (Rietveld and Kiverstein, 2014, p. 332) to predict better the potential surprise of their actions. This may manifest in the deliberate selection among multiple potential object uses of those that would violate expectancies and be original.

To summarize, the interplay between the perception of contextual cues and top-down cognitive influences makes pretend play activity an ideal training ground for the development of creativity and associated cognitive and behavioral flexibility (Dietrich, 2004; Zabelina and Robinson, 2010; Collins and Koechlin, 2012; Diamond, 2013) where the creative actors generate new action strategies using both language and sensorimotor elements (reconstructed or recruited directly from perception).

Implications for Creativity Development

Our theoretical essay reveals the importance of grounding cognitive strategies for creating novelty in action and perception and underlines the role of cultural conventions and norms in the production of novel uses for common objects. We have reviewed the existing accounts of creativity and suggested that creative cognition could not be well understood without considering the inter-related issues of object use, affordances, and sociocultural conventions (see also Buxbaum et al., 1997; Buxbaum, 2016; Osiurak and Badets, 2016 for related discussions).

We have proposed that whereas the creation of new uses for objects in pretend play could be described as a 2-fold process based on the interplay between the direct exploration of an object’s affordances and conventional knowledge, adults could accomplish the same action mentally via planning and mental enacting of multisensory experiences associated with an object (Osiurak and Badets, 2016; Matheson and Kenett, 2020). It is plausible that creative people as measured by the AUT may have a larger repertoire of possible actions or means-ends hierarchies of affordances (Cisek, 2007; Wagman et al., 2016), which allow them to better select actions and anticipate or pick up movements that could produce surprise and yield a novel use. A broader range of possible actions and better access to possible action outcomes could be in part dependent on the amount of action-related information acquired during object exploration and pretend play. It is also plausible that creative individuals could better leverage their sensorimotor (especially visuospatial) experience to create new meanings of words (Xu et al., 2017; Starr et al., 2021), which results in their higher behavioral flexibility.

This work has important implications for the development of models of the creative process and creative expertise. In our view, the real-life creative process unfolds as the alternation between offline cognition, where the person mentally generates ideas, hypotheses and plans, and online cognition, where the actor verifies predictions, but also experiments with the environment’s characteristics and allows materials to guide action (Gubenko and Houssemand, in press; Gubenko et al., in press). Whereas offline creative cognition guides action and unfolds in the mental domain as a form of predictive planning based on existing models of the environment, online creative cognition is linked to the properties of the environment and makes use of it, which allows to build better cognitive models of the world and generate better hypotheses (Spiridonov et al., 2019; see also Klahr and Dunbar, 1988). Although the performance in the offline mode is dependent on one’s executive capacities, offloading of cognitive demand via external manipulations and tool use in the online mode may alleviate individual differences in working memory (Armitage and Redshaw, 2022). This observation may account for the low association between measures of offline divergent thinking and real-life creative achievement reported in the literature (Zabelina, 2018).

Turning to the development of creative expertise, the critical role of material objects, embodied interactions, and crystallized knowledge stresses the necessity to address both “natural” and “cultural” routes in fostering creativity. In addition to interventions based on language-derived (symbolic, amodal) knowledge combination and idea generation, we find it necessary to include object-oriented activities with a high degree of motor-sensory experience and perceptual learning (e.g., construction, educational robotics, hands-on scientific experimentations) into programs aiming at creativity development. Self-directed explorations in conjunction with formative interventions, where instructors would guide and direct learners’ attention to hidden means-ends links and action possibilities, could target the so-called zone of proximal development (Vygotsky, 1978). In such interventions, hidden affordances become learners’ potential action strategies (Figure 5).

FIGURE 5
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 5. The zone of proximal development as an extension of children’s action possibilities.

The critical role of action on objects for the development of creative cognition suggests that embodied and socially situated autonomous agents may significantly complement symbolic computer systems aiming to emulate creativity computationally (Pezzulo et al., 2013; Lubart et al., 2021). Of particular interest is the research in developmental and cognitive robotics, which underscores the role of embodied interactions and human scaffolding in the development of cognitive competencies in artificial agents (Fong et al., 2002; Lindblom and Ziemke, 2003; Lungarella et al., 2004; Dautenhahn, 2007; Cangelosi et al., 2015; Kumar et al., 2021). Recent works on modeling language grounding (Roy et al., 2004; Krunic et al., 2009; Shridhar et al., 2020), robotic creative (Antunes et al., 2016; Nyga et al., 2018; Nair and Chernova, 2020) and conventional tool use (Awaad et al., 2015; Chu et al., 2016; Neemeh, 2019), as well as the ability to transfer objects’ functions (Agostini et al., 2015) could help to verify and test the models of the creative process and further unveil the role of visual perception, motor components and language in the genesis and development of creativity.

Conclusion

In this paper, we have attempted to look at the creative performance in the AUT from a different perspective and place the concept of creativity into a broader theoretical context. We have argued that possible interpretations of the creative process should include an effort to reveal the underlying mechanisms and trace their origins. While not being mutually exclusive with existing accounts of creativity, we believe that some insights drawn from the sociocultural perspective and 4E paradigm may extend and augment the existing views of the creative process.

Inevitably, this enterprise required a good deal of speculation. Although presenting a theoretical decomposition of the task, the effort was made toward a functional and, hopefully, more holistic and enriched view of creativity. Synergistic efforts of cognitive and developmental psychologists and scientists in computational and robotic creativity could extend the further research agenda and empirically validate the outlined ideas.

Data Availability Statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material; further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Ethics Statement

Written informed consent was obtained from the individual(s), and minor(s)’ legal guardian/next of kin, for the publication of any potentially identifiable images or data included in this article.

Author Contributions

AG conceived and wrote the manuscript. CH supervised the work, revised the manuscript, and commented on the text. All authors contributed to the article and approved the submitted version.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s Note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Footnotes

1. ^The 4E cognition aligns four contemporary approaches in human cognition—embodied, embedded, enactive, and extended—under one heading (Newen et al., 2018).

2. ^The relation between cognition and material culture is at the fore of Cultural-Historical Activity Theory (CHAT) and Material Engagement Theory (MET). Using different vocabularies, both theories state that cognition is mediated and constituted by material objects and place it in human activity in which the individual is engaged (Bødker, 1997; Malafouris, 2018). CHAT and MET deny the opposition of mind and matter, psychological and material (Leont’ev, 1975; Malafouris, 2019). A key notion of “thinging” which in MET stands for “the active participatory process by which things are presented to us through acts of engagement and enactive participation” (Malafouris, 2014, p. 143) is very close to the notion of “object-orientedness” in CHAT. In CHAT, human activity is always directed at a certain object, and “the mind emerges, exists and could be understood only in the context of the subject-object relationship” (Leont’ev, 1975; Kaptelinin and Nardi, 2006, p. 66).

3. ^Here and further in the text, we use the term “tool” in the sense of an artifact, i.e., a material object with a specific function (e.g., brick, newspaper, and pencil).

4. ^Although Johnson–Laird proposed that the Neo-Lamarkian process best corresponds to the creative process, we suggest that all three could coexist and co-occur in a real-life creative endeavor. Likewise, the algorithm could be a function of expertise and evolve over time.

5. ^Gick and Holyoak (1983) argued that it could be goals that are transferred, while Carbonell (1983) pointed to the role of relations.

6. ^In contrast to cross-domain mappings suggested by Structure Mapping theory, Case-Based reasoning can be considered a form of intra-domain analogy.

7. ^This finding suggests that motivation and personality traits, such as perseverance (Sternberg and Lubart, 1995) or openness to experience (McCrae, 1987), play an important part in the creative process, allowing a person to continue the search when resources of experiential strategy have been exhausted.

8. ^This canonical way of using an object or tool is usually demonstrated to a child by an adult in early triadic infant-caregiver-object interactions (El’konin, 1978; Rossmanith et al., 2014; Palacios and Rodríguez, 2015; Nonaka and Goldfield, 2018; Belza et al., 2020).

9. ^“[T]he emergence of mediated action does mean that the mediated path replaces the natural one … the incorporation of tools into the activity creates a new structural relation in which the cultural (mediated) and natural (unmediated) routes operate synergistically” (Cole, 1996, p. 119).

10. ^See also Alessandroni (2021), who argued that canonical uses should be treated as enactive cases of conceptual thinking through which children extend functional behaviors. Along this line of reasoning, functional-based generalizations may occur beyond object names.

11. ^See also Ye et al. (2009) for the same pattern in adults’ object substitution.

12. ^The method of double stimulation is referred to with different terms such as experimental genetic method, functional method of double stimulation, functional method of twofold stimulation, and historical–genetic method (Sannino, 2015).

References

Adolph, K. E., and Robinson, S. R. (2015). “Motor development,” in Handbook of Child Psychology and Developmental Science (Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.), 1–45.

Google Scholar

Agostini, A., Aein, M., Szedmak, S., Aksoy, E. E., Piater, J., and Worgotter, F. (2015). “Using structural bootstrapping for object substitution in robotic executions of human-like manipulation tasks.” in 2015 IEEE/RSJ International Conference on Intelligent Robots and Systems (IROS). September 28 - October 2, 2015.

Google Scholar

Alessandroni, N. (2021). Object concepts and their functional core: Material engagement and canonical uses of objects in early childhood education. Hu. Arenas 4, 172–195. doi: 10.1007/s42087-020-00119-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Alessandroni, N., and Rodríguez, C. (2019). On perception as the basis for object concepts: a critical analysis. Pragmat. Cogn. 26, 321–356. doi: 10.1075/pc.19027.ale

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Andersen, M. M., Kiverstein, J., Miller, M., and Roepstorff, A. (2021). Play in predictive minds: a cognitive theory of play. PsyArXiv [Preprint]. doi: 10.31234/osf.io/u86qy

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Antunes, A., Jamone, L., Saponaro, G., Bernardino, A., and Ventura, R. (2016). “From human instructions to robot actions: formulation of goals, affordances and probabilistic planning.” in Proc. IEEE ICRA. May 16-21, 2016; 5449–5454.

Google Scholar

Armitage, K. L., and Redshaw, J. (2022). Children boost their cognitive performance with a novel offloading technique. Child Dev. 93, 25–38. doi: 10.1111/cdev.13664

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Awaad, I., Kraetzschmar, G. K., and Hertzberg, J. (2015). The role of functional affordances in socializing robots. Int. J. Soc. Robot. 7, 421–438. doi: 10.1007/s12369-015-0281-3

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ball, L. J., and Christensen, B. T. (2009). Analogical reasoning and mental simulation in design: two strategies linked to uncertainty resolution. Des. Stud. 30, 169–186. doi: 10.1016/j.destud.2008.12.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barsalou, L. W. (1983). Ad hoc categories. Mem. Cogn. 11, 211–227. doi: 10.3758/BF03196968

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barsalou, L. W. (1991). “Deriving categories to achieve goals,” in The Psychology of Learning and Motivation. Vol. 27. ed. G. H. Bower (London: Academic Press).

Google Scholar

Behne, T., Carpenter, M., and Tomasello, M. (2014). Young children create iconic gestures to inform others. Dev. Psychol. 50, 2049–2060. doi: 10.1037/a0037224

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Belza, H., Herrán, E., and Anguera, M. T. (2020). Early childhood, breakfast, and related tools: analysis of adults’ function as mediators. Eur. J. Psychol. Educ. 35, 495–527. doi: 10.1007/s10212-019-00438-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Benedek, M., Jauk, E., Sommer, M., Arendasy, M., and Neubauer, A. C. (2014). Intelligence, creativity, and cognitive control: The common and differential involvement of executive functions in intelligence and creativity. Intelligence 46, 73–83. doi: 10.1016/j.intell.2014.05.007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berthold, M. R. (ed.) (2012). Bisociative Knowledge Discovery: An Introduction to Concept, Algorithms, Tools, and Applications. Berlin, Germany: Springer.

Google Scholar

Boden, M. A. (1998). Creativity and artificial intelligence. Artif. Intell. 103, 347–356. doi: 10.1016/S0004-3702(98)00055-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bødker, S. (1997). Computers in mediated human activity. Mind Cult. Act. 4, 149–158. doi: 10.1207/s15327884mca0403_2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bodrova, E., and Leong, D. J. (2007). Tools of the Mind: The Vygotskian Approach to Early Childhood Education. 2nd Edn. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson.

Google Scholar

Borghi, A. M., Barca, L., Binkofski, F., Castelfranchi, C., Pezzulo, G., and Tummolini, L. (2019). Words as social tools: language, sociality and inner grounding in abstract concepts. Phys Life Rev 29, 120–153. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2018.12.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bruner, J. S. (1975). Play is serious business. Psychol. Today 1, 81–83.

Google Scholar

Buxbaum, L. J. (2016). Learning, remembering, and predicting how to use tools: Distributed neurocognitive mechanism. Comment on Osiurak and Badets, 124, 346–360. doi: 10.1037/rev0000051

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Buxbaum, L. J., Schwartz, M. F., and Carew, T. G. (1997). The role of memory in object use. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 14, 219–254. doi: 10.1080/026432997381565

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Campbell, D. T. (1960). Blind variation and selective retentions in creative thought as in other knowledge processes. Psychol. Rev. 67, 380–400. doi: 10.1037/h0040373

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cangelosi, A., Schlesinger, M., and Smith, L. B. (2015). Developmental Robotics: From Babies to Robots. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Carbonell, J. G. (1983). “Learning by analogy: formulating and generalizing plans from past experience,” in Machine Learning. Symbolic Computation. eds. R. S. Michalski, J. G. Carbonell, and T. M. Mitchell (Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer), 137–161.

Google Scholar

Chalmers, D. J., French, R. M., and Hofstadter, D. R. (1992). High-level perception, representation, and analogy: A critique of artificial intelligence methodology. J. Exp. Theor. Artif. Intell. 4, 185–211. doi: 10.1080/09528139208953747

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chu, V., Fitzgerald, T., and Thomaz, A. L. (2016). “Learning object affordances by leveraging the combination of human-guidance and self-exploration.” in 11th ACM/IEEE International Conference on Human-Robot Interaction (HRI). March 7-10, 2016; 221–228.

Google Scholar

Chylińska, M., and Gut, A. (2020). Pretend play as a creative action: on the exploratory and evaluative features of children’s pretense. Theory Psychol. 30, 548–566. doi: 10.1177/0959354320931594

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cisek, P. (2007). Cortical mechanisms of action selection: the affordance competition hypothesis. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond., B, Biol. Sci. 362, 1585–1599. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2007.2054

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clark, A. (1998). Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Clark, H. H. (1996). Using Language. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Clark, A., and Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese 101, 401–431. doi: 10.1007/BF01063896

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cole, M. (1996). Cultural Psychology: A Once and Future Discipline. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Cole, M., and Engestrom, Y. (1993). “A cultural-historical approach to distributed cognition,” in Distributed Cognitions: Psychological and Educational Considerations. ed. G. Salomon (New York: Cambridge University Press), 1–46.

Google Scholar

Costall, A. (2012). Canonical affordances in context. Avant. 3, 85–93.

Google Scholar

Collins, A., and Koechlin, E. (2012). Reasoning, learning, and creativity: frontal lobe function and human decision-making. PLoS Biol. 10:e1001293. doi: 10.1371/journal.pbio.1001293

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dansky, J. L. (1980). Make-believe: a mediator of the relationship between play and associative fluency. Child Dev. 51, 576–579. doi: 10.2307/1129296

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dansky, J. L., and Silverman, I. W. (1973). Effects of play on associative fluency in preschool-aged children. Dev. Psychol. 9, 38–43. doi: 10.1037/h0035076

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dansky, J. L., and Silverman, I. W. (1975). Play: a general facilitator of associative fluency. Dev. Psychol. 11:104. doi: 10.1037/h0076108

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dautenhahn, K. (2007). Socially intelligent robots: dimensions of human-robot interaction. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. B Biol. Sci. 362, 679–704. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2006.2004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Davidson, J. E., and Sternberg, R. J. (1986). What is insight? Educ. Horiz. 64, 177–179.

Google Scholar

Davydov, V. V. (1992). Genezis i razvitie lischnosti v detskom vozraste [The genesis and development of personality in the child age]. Voprocy Psykjologii [Questions of Psychology] 1, 22–33.

Google Scholar

Defeyter, M. A., and German, T. P. (2003). Acquiring an understanding of design: evidence from children’s insight problem solving. Cognition 89, 133–155. doi: 10.1016/s0010-0277(03)00098-2

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dent-Read, C. H. (1997). “A naturalistic study of metaphor development: seeing and seeing as,” in Evolving Explanations of Development: Ecological Approaches to Organism–Environment Systems. eds. C. E. Dent-Read and P. E. Zukow-Goldring (Washington, DC: American Psychological Association), 255–296.

Google Scholar

Diamond, A. (2013). Executive functions. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 64, 135–168. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-113011-143750

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dietrich, A. (2004). The cognitive neuroscience of creativity. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 11, 1011–1026. doi: 10.3758/BF03196731

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dimitrova, N., Moro, C., and Mohr, C. (2015). Caregivers interpret infants’ early gestures based on shared knowledge about referents. Infant Behav. Dev. 39, 98–106. doi: 10.1016/j.infbeh.2015.02.015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Duncker, K. (1945). On problem-solving. Psychol. Monogr. 58, i–113. doi: 10.1037/h0093599

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

El’konin, D. B. (1978). Psychologija igry [Psychology of Play]. Moscow: Pedagogika.

Google Scholar

Engeström, Y. (1987). Learning by Expanding: An Activity-Theoretical Approach to Developmental Research. Helsinki: Orienta-Konsultit.

Google Scholar

Engeström, Y. (1995). Objects, contradictions and collaboration in medical cognition: an activity-theoretical perspective. Artif. Intell. Med. 7, 395–412. doi: 10.1016/0933-3657(95)00012-U

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Engeström, Y. (2001). Expansive learning at work: toward activity-theoretical reconceptualization. J. Educ. Work. 14, 133–156. doi: 10.1080/13639080020028747

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Engeström, Y. (2007). “Putting vygotsky to work: the change laboratory as an application of double stimulation,” in The Cambridge Companion to Vygotsky. eds. H. Daniels, M. Cole, and J. V. Wertsch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 363–382.

Google Scholar

Favela, L. H., Amon, M. J., Lobo, L., and Chemero, A. (2021). Empirical evidence for extended cognitive systems. Cogn. Sci. 45:e13060. doi: 10.1111/cogs.13060

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Finke, R. A. (1989). Principles of Mental Imagery. London, England: The MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Fong, T., Nourbakhsh, I., and Dautenhahn, K. (2002). A Survey of Socially Interactive Robots: Concepts, Design, and Applications. Technical report no. CMU-RI-TR-02-29. Robotics Institute, Carnegie Mellon University.

Google Scholar

Galinsky, A. D., and Moskowitz, G. B. (2000). Counterfactuals as behavioral primes: priming the simulation heuristic and consideration of alternatives. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 36, 384–409. doi: 10.1006/jesp.1999.1409

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist Interventions: Rethinking the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Gentner, D. (1983). Structure-mapping: A theoretical framework for analogy. Cogn. Sci. 7, 155–170.

Google Scholar

Gibson, J. J. (1979). Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

Google Scholar

Gick, M. L., and Holyoak, K. J. (1983). Schema induction and analogical transfer. Cogn. Psychol. 15, 1–38. doi: 10.1016/0010-0285(83)90002-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gilhooly, K. J., Fioratou, E., Anthony, S. H., and Wynn, V. (2007). Divergent thinking: strategies and executive involvement in generating novel uses for familiar objects. Br. J. Psychol. 98, 611–625. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8295.2007.tb00467.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gill, T. M. (2010). Conceptual Blending, Metaphors, and the Construction of Meaning in Ice Age Europe: An Inquiry Into the Viability of Applying Theories of Cognitive Science to Human History in Deep Time (Doctoral Dissertation, UC Berkeley).

Google Scholar

Glăveanu, V. P. (2010). Paradigms in the study of creativity: introducing the perspective of cultural psychology. New Ideas Psychol. 28, 79–93. doi: 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2009.07.007

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glăveanu, V. P. (2011). Creativity as cultural participation. J. Theory Soc. Behav. 41, 48–67. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-5914.2010.00445.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glăveanu, V. P. (2012). What can be done with an egg? Creativity, material objects, and the theory of affordances. J. Creat. Behav. 46, 192–208. doi: 10.1002/jocb.13

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glăveanu, V. P. (2013). Rewriting the language of creativity: the five A’s framework. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 17, 69–81. doi: 10.1037/a0029528

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Glăveanu, V. P. (2020). A sociocultural theory of creativity: bridging the social, the material, and the psychological. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 24, 335–354. doi: 10.1177/1089268020961763

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Goldin-Meadow, S. (2003). Hearing Gesture: How Our Hands Help Us Think. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Gubenko, A., and Houssemand, C. (in press). “Towards a framework for human-robot co-creation.” in Proceedings of Robophilosophy 2022. August 16-19, 2022.

Google Scholar

Gubenko, A., Kirsch, C., Smilek, J. N., Lubart, T., and Houssemand, C. (2021). Educational robotics and robot creativity: an interdisciplinary dialogue. Front. Robot. AI 8:662030. doi: 10.3389/frobt.2021.662030

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gubenko, A., Lubart, T., and Houssemand, C. (in press). “From social robots to creative humans and back.” in Proceedings Int. Conference on Computational Creativity (ICCC). June 27-July 1, 2022.

Google Scholar

Guilford, J. P. (1967). The Nature of Human Intelligence. McGraw-Hill.

Google Scholar

Haier, R. J., and Jung, R. E. (2008). Brain imaging studies of intelligence and creativity: what is the picture for education? Roeper Rev. 30, 171–180. doi: 10.1080/02783190802199347

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hammond, K.R. (1981). Principles of Organization in Intuitive and Analytical Cognition (Technical Report 231). Center for Research on Judgement and Policy. Boulder, CO: University of Colorado.

Google Scholar

Harris, P. L., Kavanaugh, R. D., Wellman, H. M., and Hickling, A. K. (1993). Young children‘s understanding of pretense. Monogr. Soc. Res. Child Dev. 58, i–107. doi: 10.2307/1166074

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hoicka, E., Berg, S., Kerr, T., and Carberry, M. (2013). “The unusual box test: a non-verbal, non-representational divergent thinking test for toddlers.” in AAAI Spring Symposium Series. March 25-27, 2013.

Google Scholar

Humphreys, G. W. (2001). Objects, affordances, action. Psychologist 14, 408–412.

Google Scholar

Jeannerod, M. (2001). Neural simulation of action: a unifying mechanism for motor cognition. NeuroImage 14, S103–S109. doi: 10.1006/nimg.2001.0832

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1987). Reasoning, imagining, and creating. Bull. Br. Psychol. Soc. 40, 121–129.

Google Scholar

Kahneman, D., and Tversky, A. (1982). “The simulation heuristic,” in Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. eds. D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, and A. Tversky (New York: Cambridge Univ. Press), 201–208.

Google Scholar

Kaptelinin, V., and Nardi, B. A. (2006). Acting With Technology: Activity Theory and Interaction Design. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Katz, A. N., and Hussey, K. A. (2011). “Psycholinguistics,” in Encyclopedia of Creativity: Two-Volume Set: Online Version (2nd Edn.), eds. M. A. Runco and S. R. Pritzker (Academic Press), 271–278.

Google Scholar

Kaufman, J. C., Plucker, J. A., and Baer, J. (2008). Essentials of Creativity Assessment. 1st Edn. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

Google Scholar

Keen, R. (2011). The development of problem solving in young children: a critical cognitive skill. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 62, 1–21. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.031809.130730

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kemler Nelson, D. G. (1999). Attention to functional properties in toddlers’ naming and problem-solving. Cogn. Dev. 14, 77–100. doi: 10.1016/S0885-2014(99)80019-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kemler Nelson, D. G., Russell, R., Duke, N., and Jones, K. (2000). Two-year-olds will name artifacts by their functions. Child Dev. 71, 1271–1288. doi: 10.1111/1467-8624.00228

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kendon, A. (2004). Gesture: Visible Action as Utterance. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Kenett, Y. N., Anaki, D., and Faust, M. (2014). Investigating the structure of semantic networks in low and high creative persons. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:407. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00407

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kiverstein, J. D., and Rietveld, E. (2018). Reconceiving representation-hungry cognition: an ecological-enactive proposal. Adapt. Behav. 26, 147–163. doi: 10.1177/1059712318772778

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Klahr, D., and Dunbar, K. (1988). Dual space search during scientific reasoning. Cogn. Sci. 12, 1–48. doi: 10.1207/s15516709cog1201_1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Koestler, A. (1964). The Act of Creation. New York, NY: Macmillan.

Google Scholar

Kolodner, J. L. (1992). An introduction to case-based reasoning. Artif. Intell. Rev. 6, 3–34. doi: 10.1007/bf00155578

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Kravtsova, E. E. (1996). Razbudi v rebenke volshebnika [Wake Up a Wizard in a Child]. Moscow. Prosveschenie.

Google Scholar

Krunic, V., Salvi, G., Bernardino, A., Montesano, L., and Santos-Victor, J. (2009). “Affordance based word-to-meaning association.” in 2009 IEEE International Conference on Robotics and Automation. May 12-17, 2009.

Google Scholar

Kumar, S., Giagkos, A., Shaw, P., Braud, R., Lee, M., and Shen, Q. (2021). Discovering schema-based action sequences through play in situated humanoid robots. IEEE Trans. Cogn. Develop. Syst. doi: 10.1109/TCDS.2021.3094513

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Landau, B., Smith, L. B., and Jones, S. S. (1988). The importance of shape in early lexical learning. Cogn. Dev. 3, 299–321. doi: 10.1016/0885-2014(88)90014-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

LeBoutillier, N., and Marks, D. F. (2003). Mental imagery and creativity: a meta-analytic review study. Br. J. Psychol. 94, 29–44. doi: 10.1348/000712603762842084

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lee, C. S., and Therriault, D. J. (2013). The cognitive underpinnings of creative thought: a latent variable analysis exploring the roles of intelligence and working memory in three creative thinking processes. Intelligence 41, 306–320. doi: 10.1016/j.intell.2013.04.008

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Leont’ev, A. N. (1975). Dejatel’nost’. Soznanie. Lichnost’ [Activity. Consciousness. Personality]. Moscow: Politizdat.

Google Scholar

Leont’ev, A. N. (1978). Activity, Consciousness, and Personality. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Google Scholar

Li, A. K. (1978). Effects of play on novel responses in kindergarten children. Alberta J. Educ. Res. 24, 31–36.

Google Scholar

Lindblom, J., and Ziemke, T. (2003). Social situatedness of natural and artificial intelligence: Vygotsky and beyond. Adapt. Behav. 11, 79–96. doi: 10.1177/10597123030112002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lobo, M. A., and Galloway, J. C. (2008). Postural and object-oriented experiences advance early reaching, object exploration, and means-end behavior. Child Dev. 79, 1869–1890. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2008.01231.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lockman, J. J. (2000). A perception-action perspective on tool use development. Child Dev. 71, 137–144. doi: 10.1111/1467-8624.00127

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lockman, J. J., and Kahrs, B. A. (2017). New insights into the development of human tool use. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 26, 330–334. doi: 10.1177/0963721417692035

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lubart, T., Esposito, D., Gubenko, A., and Houssemand, C. (2021). Creativity in humans, robots, humbots. Creat. Theor. - Res. - Appl. 8, 23–37. doi: 10.2478/ctra-2021-0003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Luchins, A. (1942). Mechanisms of problem solving: the effect of Einstellung. Psychol. Monogr. 54, i–95. doi: 10.1037/h0093502

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lungarella, M., Metta, G., Pfeifer, R., and Sandini, G. (2004). Developmental robotics: a survey. Connect. Sci. 15, 151–190. doi: 10.1080/09540090310001655110

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Malafouris, L. (2014). Creative thinging: the feeling of and for clay. Pragmat. Cogn. 22, 140–158. doi: 10.1075/pc.22.1.08mal

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Malafouris, L. (2018). “Bringing things to mind: 4Es and material engagement,” in The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition. eds. A. Newen, De Bruin L., and S. Gallagher (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 754–772.

Google Scholar

Malafouris, L. (2019). Mind and material engagement. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 18, 1–17. doi: 10.1007/s11097-018-9606-7

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Malafouris, L. (2021). How does thinking relate to tool making? Adapt. Behav. 29, 107–121. doi: 10.1177/1059712320950539

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Malinin, L. H. (2019). How radical is embodied creativity? Implications of 4E approaches for creativity research and teaching. Front. Psychol. 10:2372. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02372

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mangalam, M., Fragaszy, D. M., Wagman, J. B., Day, B. M., Kelty-Stephen, D. G., Bongers, R. M., et al. (2022). On the psychological origins of tool use. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 134:104521. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2022.104521

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Matheson, H. E., and Kenett, Y. N. (2020). The role of the motor system in generating creative thoughts. NeuroImage 213:116697. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2020.116697

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Matheson, H., and Kenett, Y. N. (2021). A novel coding scheme for assessing responses in divergent thinking: an embodied approach. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 15, 412–425. doi: 10.1037/aca0000297

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McCrae, R. R. (1987). Creativity, divergent thinking, and openness to experience. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 52, 1258–1265. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.52.6.1258

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McNeill, D. (1992). Hand and Mind: What Gestures Reveal About Thought. Chicago: University of Chicago.

Google Scholar

Mednick, S. A. (1962). The associative basis of the creative process. Psychol. Rev. 69, 220–232. doi: 10.1037/h0048850

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mednick, S. A. (1968). The remote associates test. J. Creat. Behav. 2, 213–214. doi: 10.1002/j.2162-6057.1968.tb00104.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Meyer, M. L., Hershfield, H. E., Waytz, A. G., Mildner, J. N., and Tamir, D. I. (2019). Creative expertise is associated with transcending the here and now. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 116, 483–494. doi: 10.1037/pspa0000148

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Miettinen, R. (1999). The riddle of things: activity theory and actor-network theory as approaches to studying innovations. Mind Cult. Act. 6, 170–195. doi: 10.1080/10749039909524725

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Miettinen, R., and Virkkunen, J. (2005). Epistemic objects, artefacts and organizational change. Organization 12, 437–456. doi: 10.1177/1350508405051279

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Moro, C., and Rodríguez, C. (2005). L’objet et la construction de son usage chez le bébé: Une approche sémiotique du développement préverbal. Peter Lang, Berne/New York.

Google Scholar

Mumford, M. D., Mobley, M. I., Reiter-Palmon, R., Uhlman, C. E., and Doares, L. M. (1991). Process analytic models of creative capacities. Creat. Res. J. 4, 91–122.

Google Scholar

Nair, L., and Chernova, S. (2020). Feature guided search for creative problem solving through tool construction. Front. Robot. AI 7:592382. doi: 10.3389/frobt.2020.592382

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Neemeh, Z. A. (2019). “Cultural affordances in AI perception.” in CogSci. July 24-27, 2441–2446.

Google Scholar

Nelson, K. (1974). Concept, word, and sentence: interrelations in acquisition and development. Psychol. Rev. 81, 267–285. doi: 10.1037/h0036592

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Newen, A., De Bruin, L., and Gallagher, S. (eds.) (2018). The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Noë, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Nonaka, T., and Goldfield, E. C. (2018). Mother-infant interaction in the emergence of a tool-using skill at mealtime: a process of affordance selection. Ecol. Psychol. 30, 278–298. doi: 10.1080/10407413.2018.1438199

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nonaka, T., and Stoffregen, T. A. (2020). Social interaction in the emergence of toddler’s mealtime spoon use. Dev. Psychobiol. 62, 1124–1133. doi: 10.1002/dev.21978

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nusbaum, E. C., and Silvia, P. J. (2011). Are intelligence and creativity really so different?: fluid intelligence, executive processes, and strategy use in divergent thinking. Intelligence 39, 36–45. doi: 10.1016/j.intell.2010.11.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nyga, D., Roy, S., Paul, R., Park, D., Pomarlan, M., and Beetz, M. (2018). “Grounding robot plans from natural language instructions with incomplete world knowledge.” in Conference on Robot Learning (Zurich). July 24-27, 714–723.

Google Scholar

Osiurak, F., and Badets, A. (2016). Tool use and affordance: manipulation-based versus reasoning-based approaches. Psychol. Rev. 123, 534–568. doi: 10.1037/rev0000027

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Osiurak, F., Jarry, C., Allain, P., Aubin, G., Etcharry-Bouyx, F., Richard, I., et al. (2009). Unusual use of objects after unilateral brain damage. The technical reasoning model. Cortex 45, 769–783. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2008.06.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Palacios, P., and Rodríguez, C. (2015). The development of symbolic uses of objects in infants in a triadic context: a pragmatic and semiotic perspective. Infant Child Dev. 24, 23–43. doi: 10.1002/icd.1873

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pellegrini, A. D. (2013). Object use in childhood: development and possible functions. Behaviour 150, 813–843. doi: 10.1163/1568539X-00003086

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pellegrini, A. D., and Hou, Y. (2011). The development of preschool children's (Homo sapiens) uses of objects and their role in peer group centrality. J. Comp. Psychol. 125, 239–245. doi: 10.1037/a0023046

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., Barsalou, L. W., Cangelosi, A., Fischer, M. H., McRae, K., and Spivey, M. J. (2013). Computational grounded cognition: a new alliance between grounded cognition and computational modeling. Front. Psychol. 3:612. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00612

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rakoczy, H., and Tomasello, M. (2006). Two-year-olds grasp the intentional structure of pretense acts. Dev. Sci. 9, 557–564. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2006.00533.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ramstead, M. J. D., Veissière, S. P. L., and Kirmayer, L. J. (2016). Cultural affordances: scaffolding local worlds through shared intentionality and regimes of attention. Front. Psychol. 7:1090. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01090

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rietveld, E., Denys, D., and Van Westen, M. (2018). “Ecological-enactive cognition as engaging with a field of relevant affordances: The skilled intentionality framework (SIF),” in The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition. eds. A. Newen, De Bruin L., and S. Gallaghe (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 40–70.

Google Scholar

Rietveld, E., and Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecol. Psychol. 26, 325–352. doi: 10.1080/10407413.2014.958035

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rochat, P., and Reed, E. S. (1987). Le concept d’affordance et les conaissances du nourrisson. Psychol. Fr. 32, 97–104.

Google Scholar

Rodríguez, C., Palacios, P., Cárdenas, K., and Yuste, N. (2014). “Les symboles: Des formes de second ou de troisiéme sens?” in Sémiotique, Culture Et Développement Psychologique. eds. C. Moro and N. Müller-Mirza (Lausanne: Presses Universitaires du Septentrion), 99–116.

Google Scholar

Rossmanith, N., Costall, A., Reichelt, A. F., López, B., and Reddy, V. (2014). Jointly structuring triadic spaces of meaning and action: book sharing from 3 months on. Front. Psychol. 5:1390. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01390

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Roy, D., Hsiao, K.-Y., and Mavridis, N. (2004). Mental imagery for a conversational robot. IEEE Trans. Syst. Man Cybern.: Syst. 34, 1374–1383. doi: 10.1109/tsmcb.2004.823327

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Russ, S. W., and Christian, K. M. (2011). “Play,” in Encyclopedia of Creativity: Two-Volume Set: Online Version. 2nd Edn. eds. M. A. Runco and S. R. Pritz (Academic Press), 238–243.

Google Scholar

Sanches de Oliveira, G., Raja, V., and Chemero, A. (2019). Radical embodied cognitive science and ‘real cognition’. Synthese 198, 115–136. doi: 10.1007/s11229-019-02475-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sannino, A. (2015). The principle of double stimulation: a path to volitional action. Learn. Cult. Soc. Interact. 6, 1–15. doi: 10.1016/j.lcsi.2015.01.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schacter, D. L., Addis, D. R., Hassabis, D., Martin, V. C., Spreng, R. N., and Szpunar, K. K. (2012). The future of memory: remembering, imagining, and the brain. Neuron 76, 677–694. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2012.11.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schacter, D. L., Benoit, R. G., and Szpunar, K. K. (2017). Episodic future thinking: mechanisms and functions. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci. 17, 41–50. doi: 10.1016/j.cobeha.2017.06.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schulz, L. E. (2015). Infants explore the unexpected. Science 348, 42–43. doi: 10.1126/science.aab0582

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Shepard, R. N., and Metzler, J. (1971). Mental rotation of three-dimensional objects. Science 171, 701–703. doi: 10.1126/science.171.3972.701

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Shridhar, M., Mittal, D., and Hsu, D. (2020). INGRESS: interactive visual grounding of referring expressions. Int. J. Robot. Res. 39, 217–232. doi: 10.1177/0278364919897133

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, L. B. (2005). Action alters shape categories. Cogn. Sci. 29, 665–679. doi: 10.1207/s15516709cog0000_13

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, P. K., and Dutton, S. (1979). Play and training in direct and innovative problem solving. Child Dev. 50, 830–836. doi: 10.2307/1128950

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Spearman, C. (1931). Creative Mind. New York: Appleton-Century.

Google Scholar

Spiridonov, V., Loginov, N., Ivanchei, I., and Kurgansky, A. V. (2019). The role of motor activity in insight problem solving (the case of the nine-dot problem). Front. Psychol. 10:2. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Srinivasan, M., and Rabagliati, H. (2021). The implications of polysemy for theories of word learning. Child Dev. Perspect. 15, 148–153. doi: 10.1111/cdep.12411

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stahl, A. E., and Feigenson, L. (2015). Observing the unexpected enhances infants’ learning and exploration. Science 348, 91–94. doi: 10.1126/science.aaa3799

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Starr, A., Cirolia, A. J., Tillman, K. A., and Srinivasan, M. (2021). Spatial metaphor facilitates word learning. Child Dev. 92, e329–e342. doi: 10.1111/cdev.13477

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sternberg, R. J. (1986a). Intelligence Applied. Orlando. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Publishers.

Google Scholar

Sternberg, R. J. (1986b). Toward a unified theory of human reasoning. Intelligence 10, 281–314. doi: 10.1016/0160-2896(86)90001-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sternberg, R. J. (1999). The theory of successful intelligence. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 3, 292–316. doi: 10.1037/1089-2680.3.4.292

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sternberg, R. J., and Lubart, T. I. (1995). Defying the Crowd: Cultivating Creativity in a Culture of Conformity. New York: Free Press.

Google Scholar

Strasheim, J. J. (1926). A New Method of Mental Testing. Baltimore: Warwick & York.

Google Scholar

Szokolszky, A., and Read, C. (2021). Pretend play with objects: an ecological approach. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 1–26. doi: 10.1007/s11097-021-09755-w

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tolar, T. D., Lederberg, A. R., Gokhale, S., and Tomasello, M. (2008). The development of the ability to recognize the meaning of iconic signs. J. Deaf. Stud. Deaf. Educ. 13, 225–240. doi: 10.1093/deafed/enm045

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tomasello, M. (1999). “The cultural ecology of young children’s interactions with objects and artifacts,” in Ecological Approaches to Cognition: Essays in Honor of Ulric Neisser. eds. E. Winograd, R. Fivush, and W. Hirst (Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum), 153–170.

Google Scholar

Tomasello, M. (2014). A Natural History of Human Thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Tomasello, M., Striano, T., and Rochat, P. (1999). Do young children use objects as 8 symbols? Br. J. Dev. Psychol. 17, 563–584. doi: 10.1348/026151099165483

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Torrance, E. P. (1981). Thinking Creatively in Action and Movement. Bensenville, IL: Scholastic Testing Service.

Google Scholar

Van der Veer, R., and Valsiner, J. (eds.) (1991). “Vygotsky and gestalt psychology,” in Understanding Vygotsky (Oxford: Backwell), 155–180.

Google Scholar

Vicente, K. J., and Rasmussen, J. (1990). The ecology of human-machine systems II: mediating direct perception'in complex work domains. Ecol. Psychol. 2, 207–249. doi: 10.1207/s15326969eco0203_2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vygotsky, L. S. (1967). Play and its role in the mental development of the child. Sov. Psychol. 5, 6–18. doi: 10.2753/rpo1061-040505036

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vygotsky, L. S. (1983). History of the Development of Higher Mental Functions. Vol. 3. Moscow: Pedagogika.

Google Scholar

Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in Society: The Development of Higher Psychological Processes. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

Google Scholar

Wagman, J. B., Caputo, S. E., and Stoffregen, T. A. (2016). Hierarchical nesting of affordances in a tool use task. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 42, 1627–1642. doi: 10.1037/xhp0000251

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wallach, M. A. (1970). “Creativity,” in Carmichael’s Manual of Child Psychology. (Vol. 1). ed. P. H. Mussen (New York: Wiley).

Google Scholar

Wallach, M. A., and Kogan, N. (1965). Modes of Thinking in Young Children: A Study of the Creativity-Intelligence Distinction. NYC: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

Google Scholar

Wiedenbauer, G., and Jansen-Osmann, P. (2008). Manual training of mental rotation in children. Learn. Instr. 18, 30–41. doi: 10.1016/j.learninstruc.2006.09.009

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilhelm, O., and Kyllonen, P. (2021). To predict the future, consider the past: revisiting Carroll (1993) as a guide to the future of intelligence research. Intelligence 89:101585. doi: 10.1016/j.intell.2021.101585

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 9, 625–636. doi: 10.3758/BF03196322

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, R. C., Guilford, J., and Christensen, P. R. (1953). The measurement of individual differences in originality. Psychol. Bull. 50, 362–370. doi: 10.1037/h0060857

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Withagen, R., and Van Der Kamp, J. (2018). An ecological approach to creativity in making. New Ideas Psychol. 49, 1–6. doi: 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2017.11.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Witt, J. K., and Proffitt, D. R. (2008). Action-specific influences on distance perception: a role for motor simulation. J. Exp. Psychol. Hum. Percept. Perform. 34, 1479–1492. doi: 10.1037/a0010781

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Xu, Y., Malt, B. C., and Srinivasan, M. (2017). Evolution of word meanings through metaphorical mapping: systematicity over the past millennium. Cogn. Psychol. 96, 41–53. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2017.05.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ye, L., Cardwell, W., and Mark, L. S. (2009). Perceiving multiple affordances for objects. Ecol. Psychol. 21, 185–217. doi: 10.1080/10407410903058229

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Yoon, E. Y., Heinke, D., and Humphreys, G. W. (2002). Modelling direct perceptual constraints on action selection: the naming and action model (NAM). Vis. Cogn. 9, 615–661. doi: 10.1080/13506280143000601

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zabelina, D. (2018). “Attention and creativity,” in The Cambridge Handbook of the Neuroscience of Creativity. eds. O. Vartanian and R. Jung (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 161–179.

Google Scholar

Zabelina, D. L., and Robinson, M. D. (2010). Creativity as flexible cognitive control. Psychol. Aesthet. Creat. Arts 4, 136–143. doi: 10.1037/a0017379

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: embodied creativity, affordances, creative process, tool use, action strategies, pretend play

Citation: Gubenko A and Houssemand C (2022) Alternative Object Use in Adults and Children: Embodied Cognitive Bases of Creativity. Front. Psychol. 13:893420. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2022.893420

Received: 10 March 2022; Accepted: 31 May 2022;
Published: 02 September 2022.

Edited by:

Anna M. Borghi, Sapienza University of Rome, Italy

Reviewed by:

Nicolás Alessandroni, Concordia University, Canada
Mihaela Taranu, Aarhus University, Denmark

Copyright © 2022 Gubenko and Houssemand. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Alla Gubenko, YWxsYUBndWJlbmtvLmV1

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.