- Centre for Systematic Musicology, University of Graz, Graz, Austria
Greenhouse-gas emissions are indirectly causing future deaths by multiple mechanisms. For example, reduced food and water supplies will exacerbate hunger, disease, violence, and migration. How will anthropogenic global warming (AGW) affect global mortality due to poverty around and beyond 2100? Roughly, how much burned fossil carbon corresponds to one future death? What are the psychological, medical, political, and economic implications? Predicted death tolls are crucial for policy formulation, but uncertainty increases with temporal distance from the present and estimates may be biased. Order-of-magnitude estimates should refer to literature from diverse relevant disciplines. The carbon budget for 2°C AGW (roughly 1012 tonnes carbon) will indirectly cause roughly 109 future premature deaths (10% of projected maximum global population), spread over one to two centuries. This zeroth-order prediction is relative and in addition to existing preventable death rates. It lies between likely best- and worst-case scenarios of roughly 3 × 108 and 3 × 109, corresponding to plus/minus one standard deviation on a logarithmic scale in a Gaussian probability distribution. It implies that one future premature death is caused every time roughly 1,000 (300–3,000) tonnes of carbon are burned. Therefore, any fossil-fuel project that burns millions of tons of carbon is probably indirectly killing thousands of future people. The prediction may be considered valid, accounting for multiple indirect links between AGW and death rates in a top-down approach, but unreliable due to the uncertainty of climate change feedback and interactions between physical, biological, social, and political climate impacts (e.g., ecological cascade effects and co-extinction). Given universal agreement on the value of human lives, a death toll of this unprecedented magnitude must be avoided at all costs. As a clear political message, the “1,000-tonne rule” can be used to defend human rights, especially in developing countries, and to clarify that climate change is primarily a human rights issue.
Introduction
Anthropogenic global warming (AGW) is a human rights issue (Amnesty International, n.d.; Caney, 2010). It is violating the rights of future people—especially, in developing countries that will suffer the most. Lancet Countdown on health and climate change has warned that “A rapidly changing climate has dire implications for every aspect of human life, exposing vulnerable populations to extremes of weather, altering patterns of infectious disease, and compromising food security, safe drinking water, and clean air” (Watts et al., 2018). UN Environment (2019) found that “nearly one quarter of all deaths globally in 2012 could be attributed to modifiable environmental risks, with a greater portion occurring in populations in a vulnerable situation and in developing countries” (p. 22). From a legal perspective, “a right to a healthy environment in various formulations is recognized by the constitutions of 118 nations around the world” (Kravchenko, 2007, p. 539).
Progress toward global emissions reductions has been consistently slow (Ge et al., 2019). Contrary to the primary aim of the United Nations Climate Change Conferences held yearly since 1995, emissions increased by 2.2% per year on average between 2005 and 2015 (Le Quéré et al., 2018) and peaked again in 2018 (International Energy Agency, 2019). The current rate of carbon emissions is some 10 times greater than the last time global mean surface temperature (GMST) was relatively high, 56 million years ago (Gingerich, 2019). AGW has therefore become a global emergency (Ripple et al., 2017).
In responding to this challenge, it may help to express the urgency in new terms by shifting attention from economic to human costs, which are incomparably greater (Nolt, 2011a, 2015). The aim of this contribution is to defend the human rights of present and future people from the fatal indirect consequences of AGW caused by greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions and AGW by addressing the quantitative relationship between fossil carbon burned now and future deaths attributable to AGW.
The broader context involves interculturality and anti-racism research. The failure of rich countries and corporations to adequately mitigate AGW is racist in the sense that the protagonists are mainly white and the victims are mainly black (cf. Kaijser and Kronsell, 2014). AGW may also be considered sexist, given known gender differences in effects of AGW on health and life expectancy (World Health Organisation, 2011). AGW is ageist in that the emissions of today’s older people will disproportionately affect today’s young people (Page, 1999).
How much fossil carbon must be burned to cause a future human death? Despite the inherent uncertainties, it is interesting to attempt a zeroth-order estimate, based on semi-quantitative considerations of the current state of global climate, the current global rate of emissions, and the complex, non-linear relationships among the amount of carbon burned, corresponding changes in GMST, current mortality in connection with poverty, and future death tolls. The question is explicitly interdisciplinary: it involves humanities (e.g., philosophy, history), sciences (e.g., physics, mathematics, statistics, psychology), practically oriented disciplines (e.g., law, medicine, international development), and disciplines that mix these groups (economics, sociology). “The greatest potential for contributions from psychology comes not from direct application of psychological concepts but from integrating psychological knowledge and methods with knowledge from other fields of science and technology” (Stern, 2011, p. 314).
Of all the living and non-living things that humans encounter in their everyday lives, human lives are usually considered the most valuable (Harris, 2006)—regardless of the assumed value of non-human life (Kellert, 1997). Moreover, people are universally considered inherently more important than money (cf. Sayer, 2011); this general idea holds even if a human life can be assigned monetary value corresponding to the amount that others are willing to pay to save it. The value of a quality-adjusted life year (QALY) according to this criterion may effectively be of the order of $100,000 (Hirth et al., 2000). Can the continued use of fossil fuels be justified after comparing today’s health and longevity benefits with future health and longevity deficits due to AGW?
The following text begins with a summary of ways in which AGW will shorten human lives in the future. The idea of a human life as a mathematical unit of value is then introduced. After a consideration of the use of numbers and words in public discourse on AGW, and the psychological mechanisms that might distort estimates of future death tolls, an approximate top-down estimate is presented for the relationship between carbon burned now and deaths caused in the future. Ethical and political implications are addressed.
How Anthropogenic Global Warming will Cause Premature Deaths
Historically, burning carbon has had a large positive effect on human life expectancy and quality of life (Steinberger and Roberts, 2010; Jorgenson, 2014). Without explicitly considering AGW, United Nations (2017b) estimated that from 1960 to 2100, global mean life expectancy will have increased from 46 to 83 years, among other things due to increasing availability of energy for agriculture, heating, cooking, transport, manufacture, and construction.
But carbon-based economies are also causing life-years to be lost in the future. The political challenge, therefore, is to maintain increases in life expectancy due to industrialization while minimizing losses in life expectancy due to AGW by replacing carbon-based power sources by sustainable ones.
The following brief summary of widely accepted climate impact predictions illustrates the magnitude of the problem:
1. Rising seas will threaten coastal homes and cities. Salination of agricultural soils will destroy farming land.
2. Dry areas will become drier with longer droughts, loss of ground water, and deglaciation. Agriculture will be seriously affected.
3. Serious storms (hurricanes, cyclones, and tornadoes) will become more frequent and dangerous (Knutson et al., 2015), destroying crops and buildings, and causing floods and epidemics (cf. the cholera outbreak that followed Cyclone Idai in Mozambique in 2019; Nguyen et al., 2019).
4. Heat waves will become more frequent and intense. When wet-bulb temperatures approach human skin temperature, body temperature can no longer be regulated by perspiration—with fatal consequences.
5. The current rate of species extinction (biodiversity loss)—already 100–1,000 times faster than without humans—will continue to increase (sixth mass extinction event).
Each of these points will affect supplies of food and fresh water, increasing current death rates due to hunger and disease. In addition, AGW will affect the nutritional content of staple crops such as rice and wheat; when carbon dioxide (CO2) levels double relative to pre-industrial levels, an additional 175 million people may be zinc deficient; 122 million, protein deficient (Smith and Myers, 2018). These points may interact with each other, causing ecological cascade effects and co-extinctions. AGW will also increase the incidence and magnitude of international conflicts including water wars (Petersen-Perlman et al., 2017).
There is an additional risk of “runaway” AGW, in which GMST continues to rise after anthropogenic emissions stop—driven by natural positive feedback processes that are not canceled by negative ones:
1. When ice melts, less radiated heat from the sun is reflected back into space, so more is absorbed, causing more ice to melt (Albedo).
2. As the carbon content of oceans and soils increases, their ability to absorb CO2 falls (Gattuso et al., 2015).
3. When permafrost (tundra) peat thaws, it releases CO2, methane (CH4), and nitrous oxide (N2O), causing more warming and melting (Voigt et al., 2017). Permafrost peat contains about 1,700 Pg carbon—about twice as much as the entire atmosphere—of which 30% (68–508 Pg) could be released by 2100 (MacDougall et al., 2012). Atmospheric CH4 concentration has unexpectedly accelerated in recent years (Nisbet et al., 2018).
4. Forests will dry out at the same time as weather conditions that cause fires (dry soil, high temperature, low humidity, and high winds) become more frequent. Fires produce CO2, causing more warming and drying (Gabbert, 2018; Reidmiller, 2018). Forest dieback can be caused by a combination of drought and bark-beetle infestation, caused in turn by AGW (Sangüesa-Barreda et al., 2015). Beetle-caused dieback can switch a forest from a carbon sink to a carbon source (Hansen et al., 2013a). Between 1984 and 2016, the European forest area affected by mortality doubled—largely due to AGW and land-use changes (Senf et al., 2018).
5. Extreme temperatures caused by climate change will increase human energy consumption for heating and cooling (International Energy Agency, 2019).
When feedbacks are taken into account, the global carbon budget for limiting AGW to 2 or 1.5°C is reduced by “several years of anthropogenic carbon dioxide emissions at present rates” (Lowe and Bernie, 2018, abstract).
The Human Life as a Unit of Value
Consider the following two theses: (1) human lives are equal in value and (2) human lives are the most valuable thing that humans know. Scientific research is consistent with (1), having failed to find evidence for inherent biological or cultural differences in value or ability (e.g., intelligence) between human groups (Fairchild, 1991). Consistent with both points, Kant (1785/2011) proposed a “kingdom of ends,” in which people are always considered as ends and never as means, implying that their value is incomparable with other forms of value.
The two theses have a strong legal foundation. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted by the United Nations in 1948, repeatedly refers to human equality. The first sentence of the declaration specifies “the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family.” The preamble also mentions the “equal rights of men and women.” Article 1 proclaims that “All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.” Article 7 adds that “All are equal before the law and are entitled without any discrimination to equal protection of the law.” According to Article 10, “Everyone is entitled in full equality to a fair and public hearing by an independent and impartial tribunal.” The principle of equality also applies to marriage (Article 16), access to public service and voting rights (21), pay for work (23), and access to education (26).
This background justifies using the human life as a unit for measuring the size of a disaster or catastrophe—comparable with kilograms, meters, and seconds for physical measurements. The number of deaths associated with a given event is an objective (although approximate) measure of the suffering associated with that event, and hence with its magnitude or seriousness.
Subjective estimates are different. First, the perceived size of a number is not proportional to its actual size: “one billion” does not seem a thousand times bigger than “one million”. Second, psychic numbing (Lifton, 1982) means a large disaster may not seem bigger or more important than a small one. Neuroscientific evidence (Dehaene, 2003) points to an approximately logarithmic relationship between the number of deaths and the perceived magnitude of a disaster.
A scientifically founded humanitarian approach should aspire to overcome such subjective limitations. “This perspective presumes a linear relationship between the number of lives one can save in a given situation and the value associated with saving them. Thus an effort saving 200 lives would have twice the value of another that saves 100 lives” (Fetherstonhaugh et al., 1997, p. 285).
Estimating Future Death Tolls
Future death tolls in connection with AGW will depend on climate in various ways. Changes in extreme temperatures (lows in winter and highs in summer) at a given location are one of many possible climate-related causes of death; studies that focus on this aspect (e.g., Kalkstein and Greene, 1997; Nicholls, 2009; Huber et al., 2017) may be ignoring the main drivers. Death rates will be highest in developing countries or among people living in poverty, so studies with that focus are more relevant.
AGW interacts in complex ways with several of the Sustainable Development Goals (Nilsson et al., 2016). Many different climate impacts could directly or indirectly lead to premature death or exacerbate existing rates of premature death from hunger or avoidable disease. Vector- and rodent-borne diseases including arboviral (dengue, chikungunya, West Nile, and malaria) may change their geographic distribution with climate change (temperature, extreme weather events, and seasonality) and environmental factors (land-use, ecosystems, deforestation, hydrology, and biodiversity); rodent population density and distribution are also affected by weather conditions (Apfel, 2007, p. 4). “(H)uman illnesses due to antimicrobial-resistant infections may become a major cause of death from infectious diseases worldwide by 2050” (UN Environment, 2019, p. 12). At the same time, food demands may increase by 50% (Searchinger et al., 2018).
The positive effect of international development projects on global rates of hunger may recently have been overtaken by the negative effect of AGW. In 2015, the proportion of undernourished people on each continent varied between 7 and 19%; the world average was 11% in 2016 (Our World in Data, n.d.). This proportion decreased steadily in recent decades on all continents. But in low-income countries, the proportion of undernourished people was 27.2% in 2015, 28.2% in 2016, and 28.3% in 2017. Roser and Ritchie (2018) explained:
This increase in hunger levels is largely a result of increases in Sub-Saharan Africa (where rates have risen by several percentage points in recent years) and small increases in South America (from 4.7% in 2014 to 5% in 2017). The UN FAO have linked this increase in undernourishment in particular to the rising extent of conflict-affected countries (which is often a leading cause of famine), and compounded by climate-related factors such as the El Niño phenomenon (which can inflict both drought and flood conditions).
Future death tolls due to AGW will also involve conflicts such as water wars (Gleick, 2014). Hence, both reasons for the recent increase in hunger offered by Roser and Ritchie involve climate.
DARA International (2012) linked 400,000 annual deaths worldwide to AGW. World Health Organisation (2017) found that “Between 2030 and 2050, climate change is expected to cause approximately 250,000 additional deaths per year, from malnutrition, malaria, diarrhea and heat stress.” These estimates seem conservative when considered relative to existing death rates in connection with poverty. Three million children are still dying of hunger every year (Black et al., 2013). AGW is already affecting food and fresh water supplies, increasing the death rate from hunger (McMichael et al., 2006, 2008). Many deaths are caused by a combination of poverty and AGW.
World Health Organization (2009) explained that “Over time, major risks to health shift from traditional risks (e.g. inadequate nutrition or unsafe water and sanitation) to modern risks (e.g. overweight and obesity). Modern risks may take different trajectories in different countries, depending on the risk and the context” (p. 3). From a global perspective, traditional risks have been declining, whereas modern risks are increasing. But AGW is causing traditional risks to rise again relative to modern risks, and predictions of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) in different scenarios suggest that this trend will continue until 2100.
The death rate from hunger will increase not only due to AGW itself but also due to efforts to mitigate and adapt to AGW:
Food insecurity can be directly exacerbated by climate change due to crop-production-related impacts of warmer and drier conditions that are expected in important agricultural regions. However, efforts to mitigate climate change through comprehensive, economy-wide GHG emissions reductions may also negatively affect food security, due to indirect impacts on prices and supplies of key agricultural commodities (Hasegawa et al., 2018, p. 699).
Climate Change Impacts and Risk Analysis (2015) found that a global agreement to reduce AGW could prevent 70,000 premature American deaths annually by 2100. But death rates in developing countries will be much higher, especially when infections, parasites, AIDS, diarrhea, tuberculosis, malaria, and childhood diseases are considered. Predictions for richer countries do not tend to focus on the combined effects of poverty, hunger, and water supplies, but instead on factors such as air quality, extreme temperatures, water quality, extreme weather events, air pollution from wildfires, and vector-borne disease.
In a media discussion over a decade ago, journalist George Monbiot commented that “If we don’t deal with climate change we condemn hundreds of millions of people to death” (Democracy Now, 2007). Given current extrapolations and speculations about future poverty, hunger, disease, migration, and war, this top-down estimate seems reasonable. Nolt (2011a) found that the emissions of a typical US-American over the course of a lifetime cause the suffering or death of one or two future people in poor countries during the next millennium. Of course, not only Americans are to blame, although their emissions are roughly twice those of Europeans; in round figures, 109 rich people are in the process of prematurely ending the lives of 109 future poor people. Nolt (2015) summarized other attempts to estimate future death tolls in connection with AGW, concluding that “the methodologies of these studies are imperfect … clearly there is need for critique and further refinement of such estimates” (p. 353).
Summarizing this section, existing estimates of future AGW death tolls suffer from various limitations. Many focus on mortality due to extreme temperatures, but mortality from poverty combined with AGW could be much higher. Many focus on rich countries, detracting attention from the more serious plight of developing countries. Most are limited to the next few decades, but the problem will probably become more acute every decade until at least 2100, given that the half-life or atmospheric lifetime of anthropogenic CO2 in the atmosphere is of the order of a century (Archer et al., 2009).
Reliable Versus Valid Prediction of Future Death Tolls
Existing predictions of future AGW death tolls are bottom-up in two senses: analytic, considering deaths from individual causes in separate regions or countries, and empirical, based on past experience. Conversely, a top-down estimate is holistic, considering the entire global population, and extrapolatory, considering unprecedented future developments. A top-down estimate is inductive, beginning with an initial guess that is refined after comparison with sources of evidence; it mixes hermeneutics (humanities) with active inference (psychology; Friston and Frith, 2015).
By analogy, psychological measures and tests can be reliable or valid. A reliable test gives a similar result on different occasions. A valid test tests what it is intended to test and not something else (internal validity) and is generalizable beyond a given sample (external validity) (Drost, 2011). A reliable test is not necessarily valid, and vice-versa.
A bottom-up analysis of future deaths attributable to AGW has the advantage of reliability based on locally relevant details and documented past experience. In Bangladesh, for example, DARA International (2012) predicted 2,600 annual deaths from environmental disasters and 20,000 from various diseases attributable to AGW per year by 2030. But a top-down analysis that attempts to see the big picture while extrapolating current trends may be more valid, better estimating what it intends to estimate (the death toll in a future unprecedented situation), attempting to generalize non-linearly beyond a limited sample, and including the highly uncertain possibility of unprecedented, catastrophic developments. A top-down analysis may produce a more realistic grand total but lack a detailed breakdown.
For these reasons, a more rigorous multivariate analysis that considers relevant territorial, geographic, population, health, epidemiological, economic, and geopolitical aspects of the problem will not be attempted here. Instead, I will present a big-picture, top-down estimate. Nor will I attempt a separate consideration of IPCC emissions scenarios (rapid economic growth; global environmental sustainability; regionally oriented economic development; local environmental sustainability; Nakicenovic et al., 2000) or the Representative Concentration Pathways (different levels of radiative forcing in the year 2100; Van Vuuren et al., 2011). My focus will instead be on a single scenario in which GMST rises to 2°C above pre-industrial temperatures. Limiting calculations to order-of-magnitude estimates (OMEs) means that mortality predictions based on different 2°C scenarios—different global-emission or CO2-concentration trajectories that lead to the same maximum GMST—are unlikely to differ. Moreover, by contrast to IPCC scenarios, my approach includes the possibility of highly uncertain outcomes such as climate-based wars and catastrophic ecological events.
As an example of highly uncertain outcomes, consider the effect of AGW on displaced persons. The Environmental Justice Foundation warned that AGW could create 150 million climate refugees in the next 40 years (Guardian, 2009), or 3 to 4 million per year. Many climate refugees will die before finding a new home. Current EU policy on refugees from Africa, driven by the rise of the political far right, suggests that the average European citizen is more concerned about stopping illegal immigration than preventing deaths at sea; “non-Europeans from poor countries seeking entry into Italy are categorized as outsiders and therefore non-human” (Carter and Merrill, 2007). Future far-right governments, having consolidated power by undermining democratic infrastructures, will explore new ways of preventing immigration (Jones, 2016)—possibly with fatal consequences for enormous numbers of people.
Temporal Issues
An estimate of the total death toll due to AGW should consider the period during which deaths will occur relative to human life expectancy. Current emissions will probably cause future deaths for between a century and a millennium. CO2 emissions (mainly from fossil fuels) stay in the atmosphere for 2–20 centuries (Walker, 1985; Archer et al., 2009); CH4 (mainly from ruminant livestock), for about decade (Prather et al., 2012). The third most important anthropogenic GHG, N2O, has an atmospheric half-life of roughly a century and is emitted by agricultural soils, tropical soils, and melting permafrost (Wilkerson et al., 2019). If all anthropogenic emissions suddenly stopped, half the anthropogenic CO2 would disappear in the following decades, the duration depending on the state of the world’s oceans and forests; a smaller fraction would remain for thousands of years. It is possible that the effects of AGW will continue for tens of thousands or even a hundred thousand years (Solomon et al., 2009; Zeebe, 2013).
Another temporal issue is the relationship between lives lost and years of life lost. Years of life lost are used in medicine to evaluate the impact of a disease (e.g., Fontaine et al., 2003) and suggest that that the death of a child more serious than the death of an adult.
Without AGW, the life expectancy of a child born today in a developing country depends on country, varying from 35 to 70 years (Central Intelligence Agency, n.d.). Of those children and adults that die in connection with AGW in coming decades or centuries, the average number of life-years they will lose can only be guessed. The many negative consequences of AGW and the special vulnerability of the very young (Black et al., 2013) and the very old (Carter et al., 2016) suggest that the age distribution of future victims of climate change will be bimodal. In a zeroth-order estimate, an average future AGW-victim in a developing country might lose half of a lifetime or 30–40 life-years. An additional factor is the population pyramid (Cohen, 2003).
When disability is taken into account (disability-adjusted life years or DALYs; Murray, 1994), the rate at which life years are effectively lost depends on the severity of the illness or injury. But DALYs have an important practical disadvantage:
The public does not understand them. If to the question, “how much harm will climate change do in the next decade (or century)” one answers with a certain large number of DALYs lost, this will mean nothing to most people. If, on the other hand, one answers with a casualty or fatality estimate, nearly everyone will understand. (Nolt, 2015, p. 351).
Nolt (2015) listed three advantages of limiting the discussion to simple numbers of deaths: such estimates are empirical (based on hard facts), universally understood, and “more likely … to elicit constructive public concern” (p. 353). After comparing deontological (duty- or rule-based) and consequentialist approaches to this problem, Nolt concluded that “casualty estimates are … significant no matter which ethical framework we use” (p. 354).
Use of Clear, Direct Language
The consequences of climate change are more serious than the neutrally/positively connotated words “climate” and “change” suggest. In that sense, “climate change” may be considered a euphemism. AGW sounds more serious, although the words “anthropogenic,” “global,” and “warming” each sound neutral or positive. The apparently innocent word “adaptation” is problematic if its implementation leads to global social injustice (Kagawa and Selby, 2010).
Terminologies such as “lost life-years” and “climate and health” are euphemisms if they disguise or soften discourses that are really about killing or death (cf. Abbott, 2010). In everyday language, the word “kill” means to cause death by any means, direct or indirect, regardless of any associated intention. The word may be avoided or modified in scientific discourse to soften its illocutionary force (Holmes, 1984). But if the scientific questions being asked involve future people’s lives that are being shortened by AGW, or the effect of today’s consumerist, mobile lifestyles on future deaths, it is important to state the facts clearly. To protect the basic rights of children alive now or soon to be born, living in poverty in developing countries such as Congo, Liberia, Zimbabwe, Afghanistan, or Haiti, we must directly and openly consider the mechanisms that might cause their deaths.
Conversely, exaggeration should be avoided. Sociologist and human rights activist Jean Ziegler claimed that every child who dies of hunger is “murdered” (United Nations, 2002). He was right to attract attention to a very serious problem. But in everyday and legal usage, “murder” involves premeditated malicious intention, whereas “manslaughter” does not. The politicians and corporate CEOs most responsible for child mortality through hunger do not intend to kill anyone.
For similar reasons, it is problematic to compare AGW with genocide, and Nazi Holocaust comparisons are rightly taboo (Maier, 1988). The Holocaust was unique due to the deliberate and premeditated nature of the killing (Sweeney, 2012). AGW is not about killing specific people. The identity of future victims can be predicted only approximately: they are more likely to live in developing or tropical countries or high-risk regions. The timeframe is similarly approximate (the coming century or two).
A quantitative human-rights perspective based on expected death rates enables the following comparisons. While the Nazi Holocaust was a greater crime than AGW due to its deliberate and premeditated nature, AGW will be a bigger disaster or tragedy if it causes ten or a hundred times more deaths. Both the number of lives lost per year and the duration of the crisis will be greater for AGW than for the Holocaust. Both the Holocaust and AGW are/were enabled by public indifference combined with active deception by powerful individuals in government or corporations. Historical, psychological, and sociological comparisons of this kind can help overcome both the indifference (Booth, 2012) and the deception (Sandman, 2009).
Estimating Future Death Tolls
For the mathematical relationship between CO2 concentration and GMST, there is no single, widely accepted formula (Knutti et al., 2017). In an exponential approximation, GMST rises by a certain amount (equilibrium climate sensitivity) every time CO2 concentration doubles and stabilizes: roughly 3°C, or between 1.5 and 4.5°C (Myhre et al., 2017). In a linear approximation, the change in GMST (in °C or K) is proportional to the mass of carbon burned (Allen et al., 2009; Tokarska et al., 2016). The linear approximation takes into account carbon cycle feedbacks: as GMST increases, the ability of oceans and soils to absorb and store carbon decreases (Friedlingstein et al., 2006; Gregory et al., 2009). The resultant gradient of temperature rise as a function of carbon burned (transient climate response to cumulative CO2 emissions or carbon-climate response) is roughly constant at between 1 and 2°C per trillion (1012) tons of burned carbon. This is approximately true up to several trillion tons, or the end of reasonably accessible carbon reserves (Matthews et al., 2009). “(U)uncertainty in land-use CO2 emissions and aerosol forcing … means that higher observationally constrained values cannot be excluded” (p. 829), justifying the common estimate of 2°C per trillion tonnes1. Thus, burning 5 × 1012 tons (an estimate of all available fossil fuel) will cause roughly 10°C of warming (Tokarska et al., 2016).
Linear and exponential approaches make divergent predictions for several degrees of warming, but both are roughly consistent with the following prediction. When humanity burns a trillion tonnes of carbon (of which about half has been burned so far), GMST will rise by about 2°C altogether relative to pre-industrial times (the carbon budget; Harvey et al., 2013).
Given that the time period during which anthropogenic CO2 remains in the atmosphere is inherently uncertain—spanning decades, centuries, or even millennia—it is difficult to predict how many people will die prematurely as a result of 2°C of AGW. Consider the following radically simplified scenarios:
1. If the deaths were confined to the 21st and 22nd centuries, the AGW death rate during that period might vary between zero and the current global death rate in connection with poverty, which is roughly 107 per year. Storms alone—more intense and frequent due to AGW—could cause millions of deaths per year. Given the multiple serious consequences of AGW and their separate and collective effects on food and water supplies, forced migration, and armed conflict, it is reasonable to assume the AGW will double the death rate in connection with poverty for a period of a century, causing 109 deaths altogether. According to the World Bank, “By 2050, population growth and rapid urbanization could put 1.3 billion people and $158 trillion in assets at risk from river and coastal floods alone” (Phillips et al., 2018, p. 5).
2. If AGW increased the death rate by 50% for two centuries, the total number of deaths due to AGW would also be 109. If the death rate was smaller (106 per year) but continued for 10 centuries, the final death toll would again be 109.
3. Combining the previous approaches, future death rates attributable to current and past emissions may vary between 106 and 107 per year for a period of several centuries. Mathematical integration of this kind is used in risk assessment (Henley and Kumamoto, 1981) and expected value calculations (Fankhauser, 1994). The expected value of the future death toll (a measure of risk) is calculated by adding products of estimated death rate and estimated probability for different scenarios.
Figure 1. Assumed probability distribution of AGW-driven mortality. Predicted distribution of the total global number of premature deaths attributable to 2°C of AGW. 108 is an extreme best-case estimate, 3 × 108 is likely best case, 109 is median, 3 × 109 is likely worst case, and 1010 is extreme worst case.
Assuming a broad distribution of possible future death rates, a given death-rate estimate is plausible if considerably higher and lower estimates are also plausible. We should therefore consider best- and worst-case estimates before arriving at a most-likely estimate or expected value. In the following, a top-down approach will be presented in which the expected value of the total global death toll caused by 2°C AGW lies logarithmically midway between a likely best-case scenario of 3 × 108 and a likely worst-case scenario of 3 × 109.
These are no more than order-of-magnitude estimates. OMEs are commonly used in physics for approximate calculations involving very large or very small numbers (e.g., Serway and Jewett, 2018). The uncertainty of an OME is itself uncertain. Consider the number 1.36, correct to two decimal places or three significant figures. Depending on definition, this number lies either between 1.35 and 1.37 or between 1.355 and 1.365. Similarly, the order of magnitude “104” lies either between 103 and 105 or between 103.5 ≈ 3 × 103 and 104.5 ≈ 3 × 104. The following argument assumes the smaller range (a factor of 3 in either direction).
Best-Case Estimate
A likely best-case estimate of the future death toll due to 2°C AGW may be made by considering IPCC predictions for 2°C by comparison to 1.5° (Pirani et al., 2018). The long tradition of interdisciplinary peer-reviewed scientific research behind these predictions makes them reliable. Death rates predicted on the basis of IPCC data may be considered “best-case” if they ignore uncertainties involving interactions between different climate impacts, climate feedback processes, or “tipping points.”
Each of the following climate impacts listed by Masson-Delmotte and colleagues can be expected to contribute significantly to the AGW death toll at +2°C by comparison to 1.5°C:
1. direct weather impacts: higher extreme temperatures, longer heatwaves, more flooding and drought, more and more intense tropical cyclones;
2. oceans: higher sea level, temperature, acidity; dying coral reefs;
3. aquatic life: long-lasting or irreversible impacts on biodiversity and ecosystems including species loss and extinction, habitat, reproduction, disease, invasive species, and coral bleaching;
4. land: geographic range of insects, plants and vertebrates, degradation and loss of high-latitude tundra and boreal forests, thawing of permafrost;
5. for humans: effects on health, livelihoods, food security, water supply, security, economic growth; higher heat-related and ozone-related mortality; greater spread of vector-borne diseases (malaria, dengue fever); lower yields of maize, rice, wheat, soy; lower nutritional quality of rice and wheat; greater negative effects on livestock including changes in feed quality, spread of diseases, and water resource availability.
In a zeroth-order OME, each such point might be associated with a death toll of 106 per year or 108 per century that is attributable to AGW. A relatively optimistic, but also very approximate, best-case estimate of 3 × 108 deaths is consistent with this approach if we also assume the success of diverse adaptive strategies in different geographic locations, depending on economic possibilities. Relevant adaptations might include smart housing, urban heat refuges, tree planting, water storage, desalination, medical/ecological suppression of vector-born disease, solar-powered air conditioning, flood defenses, agricultural innovations, and the creation of new habitats for endangered species. Given the lower adaptive capacity of poorer countries, adaption may also be promoted by alleviating poverty and inequalities and improving education; but the success of adaptive strategies is also limited by cultural factors (Adger et al., 2013).
Another approach is to consider existing death tolls from related causes. As a cause of death, AGW will hardly be inseparable from poverty, which is also linked to air pollution (Egondi et al., 2018). Outdoor air pollution (mostly by PM2.5) is now causing 3 × 106 premature deaths per year, mainly in Asia; in a business-as-usual scenario, this figure could double by 2050 (Lelieveld et al., 2015). If the effect remained constant for a century, air pollution would kill 3 × 108 people altogether. This estimate may be conservative: World Health Organisation (2018) estimated 4.2 × 106 deaths per year due to ambient (outdoor) air pollution plus 3.8 × 106 due to household cookstoves and fuels. UN Environment (2019) estimates that air pollution is causing 6 to 7 × 106 deaths annually (1 in 9 deaths worldwide). About 91% of the world’s population lives in places, where air pollution exceeds WHO guideline limits.
A best-case scenario should also be optimistic about expected progress in coming years toward reducing the death toll from AGW. It should in particular assume improvements in:
1. technology, supported by sufficient finance, to sustainably improve food production and distribution in developing countries,
2. medicines and infrastructures to treat vector-borne diseases,
3. international diplomacy to promote the peaceful conflict resolution,
4. support services for climate refugees in transit and on arrival in new homelands, and
5. popular acceptance of refugees reflected in more liberal, internationally oriented government policies.
Taken together, these arguments are consistent with a best-case scenario in which AGW increases the current death rate in connection with poverty (roughly 107 per year) by 30% to 1.3 × 107 per year, the difference between the two rates (with and without AGW) remaining roughly constant for a century. The total death toll due to AGW of 2°C would therefore be 100 × (3 × 106) = 3 × 108.
Worst-Case Estimate
A likely worst-case scenario should consider all reasonably possible catastrophic outcomes that might be caused directly or indirectly by AGW, even if limited to 2°C.
1. Today, about 30% of global population experiences deadly heat for over 20 days per year. By 2100, this will rise to 48% if GHG emissions are drastically reduced and 74% if they continue to grow (Mora et al., 2017).
2. The combination of AGW and high population growth in developing African countries such as Equatorial Guinea, Omar, Niger, Uganda, Angola, and Congo will lead to unprecedented death rates due to poverty (hunger, disease, and violence) and massive population displacement. Africa’s population (currently 1.3 × 109) will rise to roughly 2.5 × 109 by 2050 and 4 × 109 by 21002. Between 2017 and 2050, 26 African countries may double their populations (United Nations, 2017b). Even without AGW, it will not be possible to produce and deliver sufficient food and fresh water (Godfray et al., 2010). AGW will exacerbate the crisis—even without considering population growth (McMichael et al., 2006, 2008). By 2100, the total death toll due to 2°C AGW may approach 109 in Africa alone.
3. There will be severe climate impacts in the Middle East and Northern Africa, with mean temperature increases well above GMST and displacement of large human populations (Economist, 2018).
4. Thomas et al. (2004) estimated that 15% of all species will be extinct by 2050 if AGW is limited to 1.5°C; 37% if limited to 2°C. Ecological dependencies may multiply the direct effects of environmental change on the collapse of planetary diversity by 10 (Strona and Bradshaw, 2018). Loss of biodiversity will make it impossible to feed a larger African population (Frison et al., 2011).
5. Insect populations will be affected by a combination of AGW and insecticides (Boggs, 2016). Forty percent of the world’s insect species may go extinct in coming decades (Resnick, 2019; Sánchez-Bayo and Wyckhuys, 2019). In the past 50 years, bee pollinations have declined as demand for agricultural pollination has approximately tripled, triggering a pollination crisis that affects crop yields (Goulson et al., 2015). Extinction of bee species could lead to the extinction of plant species that depend on bees for pollination, leading to other animal, plant, and insect extinctions, which in turn affects insect-eating bird populations (Goulson, 2014).
6. Biodiverse coral reefs will be degraded due to pollution, overfishing, and rising temperature and acidity of ocean waters (Hughes et al., 2017). Oceanic oxygen concentration is also falling (Poppick, 2019). Most reefs will be seriously threatened or irreversibly damaged by 2050 (Burke et al., 2011) and the rest may die by 2100.
7. Sekerci and Petrovskii (2015) showed that “the oxygen production by marine phytoplankton can stop suddenly if the water temperature exceeds a certain critical value. Since the ocean plankton produces altogether more than one half of the total atmospheric oxygen, it would mean oxygen depletion not only in the water but also in the air. Should it happen, it would obviously kill most of life on Earth” (p. 2349).
8. Soil will be degraded by chemical-heavy farming techniques and deforestation-induced erosion, reducing crop yields (Arsenault, 2014). “There is rapidly escalating competition between the demand for land functions that provide food, water, and energy, and those services that support and regulate all life cycles on Earth” (United Nations, 2017c, p. 8).
9. Groundwater (Dalin et al., 2017) is the largest available store of global freshwater and 2 × 109 people rely on it. About 6% of global groundwater is readily available and can be replenished with a human lifespan (Gleeson et al., 2016). Where groundwater is depleted, recovery may take centuries or millennia (Cuthbert et al., 2019, p. 140).
10. About 10% of global land is covered by glaciers, and 109 people depend on their meltwater (Qui, 2019). AGW will cause non-polar glacier volume to fall by 29–41% in 2100; “glaciers in Central Europe, low-latitude South America, Caucasus, North Asia, Western Canada, and US are projected to lose more than 80% of their volume by 2100” with “major implications for regional hydrology and water availability in the near future” (Radić et al., 2014). Clarke et al. (2015) predicted that by 2100 Western Canadian glaciers will shrink by 70% relative to 2005, affecting aquatic ecosystems, agriculture, forestry, and water quality. Iceland’s glaciers will shrink by 40% in 2100 and 100% in 2200 (Poore et al., 2000). Accelerated deglaciation in Greenland from 2003 to 2013 suggests a tipping point driven by changes in air temperature and solar radiation (Bevis et al., 2019).
11. Pathogens such as anthrax may emerge from melting permafrost (Revich and Podolnaya, 2011; Legendre et al., 2015) and cause regional or global pandemics (Wu et al., 2016). Humans have little immune resistant to zoonoses—diseases transmitted between human and non-human animals, such as ebola and salmonellosis. In the 14th century, bubonic plague (spread by fleas or body fluids from plague-infected animals) killed 25–40% of European children and adults (Galvani and Slatkin, 2003).
12. 2°C AGW will trigger conflicts over natural resources (Barnett and Adger, 2007). Political destabilization could lead to use of nuclear weapons, causing radioactive fallout and ozone depletion (Mills et al., 2008).
In a zeroth-order estimate, one or more of these points could alone cause 107 deaths per year for a century—a total of 109 deaths each. If that is true, a worst-case estimate of 3 × 109 for the worst-case AGW death toll may be realistic. That would correspond to roughly 30% of future world population, which will reach 9.8 × 109 in 2050 and 11.2 × 109 in 2100 (or between 8 × 109 and 15 × 109; United Nations (2017a). Given the high degree of uncertainty, a more precise estimate is hardly realistic.
Incorporating the above best- and worst-cases into a simple mathematical model, the probability distribution of different possible global mortality outcomes may be normal (Gaussian) relative to a logarithmic axis, as shown in Figure 1. This distribution is no more than an educated guess or top-down estimate based on the following assumptions. Approximately 2/3 of possible outcomes lie within one standard deviation of the mean and 95% within two standard deviations. The number of premature deaths attributable to AGW (when limited to +2°C) may lie between 3 × 108 and 3 × 109 (likely best- and worst-case outcomes) with a probability of 2/3, and between 108 and 1010 (extreme best- and worst-case outcomes) with a probability of 95%. Regarding the lower limit of 108, even if GMST suddenly stabilized at +1°C, we might reasonably predict 106 deaths per year for a century due to AGW, making the 108 estimate obviously too low. The upper limit of 1010 is obviously too high: in the absence of unexpected climate feedbacks or tipping points, the probability that 2°C AGW will kill most or all humans is negligible.
Visualizing the Unfolding Global Tragedy
Figure 2 is a conceptual sketch of the death rate in connection with global poverty and AGW as it might develop during the 21st century. Again, the graph is no more than an educated guess or top-down estimate based on a small number of holistic assumptions. The lower line is a rough estimate of the projected death rate in connection with poverty (hunger, curable disease, preventable disease, violence, and air pollution) in developing countries. Depending on assumptions and operationalizations, this rate is currently roughly 107 per year. It has been gradually falling for decades, due to economic growth combined with the efforts of developmental aid organizations, partly in the framework of the Millennium Development Goals and Sustainable Development Goals of the United Nations (Sachs, 2008).
Figure 2. Predicted development of global mortality due to poverty and AGW. Very approximate projection of global annual death rates during the 21st century. The lower line represents deaths due to poverty without AGW. As the negative effect of AGW overtakes the positive effect of development, the death rate will increase, as shown by the upper line. In a more accurate model, the upper line might be concave upward on the left (exponential increase) and concave downward on the right (approaching a peak).
Without AGW, the lower line of Figure 2 would continue to descend. But the emerging combination of poverty and AGW means it will probably rise in coming decades (McMichael et al., 2006, 2008). Given the multiple serious effects of AGW on global food and water supplies, and its expected effect on international conflict and migration, the death rate attributable to AGW (the difference between the two lines) may approach 107 per year by 2100. If so, the total AGW death toll in the 21st century will be 5 × 108 (the area between the two lines). Assuming another 5 × 108 climate deaths in the 22nd and later centuries, the total death toll due to historic and current emissions will be roughly 109.
The 1,000-Tonne Rule
If burning 1012 tonnes of fossil carbon causes the premature deaths of 109 future people, one future person is killed every time a 1,000 tonnes of carbon are burned. This OME is consistent with Nolt’s (2011a) finding that the average American produces 1,840 tonnes CO2 equivalent (from burning 500 tonnes of carbon) during her or his lifetime, which then causes the suffering or death of one or two future people. If it takes 1,000 tonnes of carbon (or 3,700 tonnes of CO2) to kill a future person, and Nolt’s calculation is correct, the average American is killing half of a future person.
The 1,000-tonne rule can be understood by the following thought experiment. Imagine what would happen if humanity suddenly and completely stopped producing GHGs. Today’s people would suddenly stop causing atmospheric GHG concentration to increase, which is killing future people. Relative to that scenario, the 1,000-tonne rule says that every additional 1,000 tonnes of carbon burned causes one future death. The rule predicts that the death will happen in the next 1–2 centuries, probably in a developing country. Beyond that, it says nothing about the time and place of death.
The horizontal axis of Figure 3 shows the total mass of carbon burned since the start of industrialization. The vertical axis shows the predicted number of future deaths due to AGW. This sketch is based on two assumptions: (1) burning 1012 tonnes of carbon will probably cause 109 future premature deaths, and (2) burning 5 × 1012 tonnes of carbon will eventually kill most or all humans (1010 deaths). All values are OMEs. In the lower left corner, the assumed linear relationship between the number of future deaths caused and the mass of carbon burned corresponds to the 1,000-tonne rule. The concave-upward shape of the graph as a whole suggests that the amount of carbon to kill a future person is slowly decreasing.
Figure 3. Predicted future global mortality as a function of carbon burned. Rough sketch of the assumed relationship. The 1,000-tonne rule applies to the left portion of the graph, before the first 1012 tonnes of carbon have been burned.
Consider a medium-level “business as usual” scenario (e.g., IPCC Assessment Report 5, Working Group II, Representative Concentration Pathways) with a GMST increase of 3–4°C by 2100. If business as usual were continued into the future until all reasonably accessible carbon reserves (5 × 1012 tonnes according to Tokarska et al., 2016) were exhausted, GMST would increase by some 10°C, killing most or all humans (Sherwood and Huber, 2010; the right side of Figure 3). In that extreme case, roughly 500 tons of carbon will have been sufficient to kill one person.
Avoiding Bias
Is it reasonable to predict that 10% of a future world population of 1010 will die prematurely following 2°C AGW? The prediction may be conservative for the following reasons:
1. The fatal future consequences of current human emissions have been assumed to last for 1–2 centuries; they may last for a millennium.
2. The 1,000-tonne rule has been derived on the assumption that AGW will double the global death rate in connection with poverty. The current death rate has been estimated at 107 per year; but Pogge (2001) placed it at 1.8 × 107.
3. The prediction relies on IPCC predictions, which tend to be conservative (Rahmstorf et al., 2007, 2012; Rahmstorf, 2010; Scherer, 2012; Brysse et al., 2013; Saba et al., 2016). Current ocean warming is at the high end of previous IPCC estimates (Resplandy et al., 2018), contributing to increases in rainfall intensity, sea level, and reef destruction, and decreases in ocean oxygen levels, mass of ice sheets, glaciers and ice caps (Cheng et al., 2019). Not all GMST models cited by IPCC have factored in the expected fall in carbon absorption rates by plants in the second half of the 21st century (Green et al., 2019). Conservative estimates may be a response to political and financial pressure from fossil fuel industries and the global climate denial community; climate scientists who publish the truth may even risk losing their jobs (Shogren, 2019).
If the present claims seem exaggerated relative to public current discourse on AGW, the reason may be denial in public discourse (Sandman, 2009)—a complex psychological, sociological, political, economic, and ethical phenomenon. Misleading claims by high-profile climate deniers (“contrarians,” “skeptics”) have appeared commonly in the media during the past two decades. Many non-experts still think AGW is one side of an unresolved discussion (Oreskes, 2004). Middle-class Westerners creatively justify their failure to reduce personal emissions, citing financial cost, the responsibility of others including governments, or the uncertain efficacy personal action (Stoll-Kleemann et al., 2001). Further “dragons of inaction” include limited knowledge, skepticism, non-ecological ideological worldviews, and risk underestimation (Gifford, 2011). Perceptions of climate risk depend strongly on psychosocial identity—whether political conservative or progressive, farmer, scientist, environmentalist, or businessperson (Fielding and Hornsey, 2016). Identity mediates the link between social representations of climate change and mitigating/adapting behaviors (Jaspal et al., 2014).
Any estimate of massive unprecedented risk is subject to psychological distortions (Yudkowsky, 2008), depending on “gender, political party, knowledge of the causes, impacts and responses to climate change, social norms, value orientations, affect and personal experience with extreme weather” (Van der Linden, 2015, p. 112). Humans tend to overestimate small risks and underestimate large risks (Hakes and Viscusi, 2004). For example, people living in earthquake zones tend to purchase inadequate insurance (Lehman and Taylor, 1987); “people refuse to buy flood insurance even when it is heavily subsidized and priced far below an actuarially fair value” (Yudkowsky, 2008, p. 92). The dangers to society and aviation posed by volcanic ash dispersal are typically underestimated (Bourne et al., 2016). Smokers underestimate the personal risk of smoking (Viscusi, 1990).
There is a similar tendency to underestimate risks based on description by comparison to those based on visceral experience (Weber, 2006). Unprecedented events are an example, and given that AGW will last for centuries, historical examples are relevant. In 1912, the Titanic provided 20 lifeboats for 1,178 people. In 1914, the Great Powers estimated that a modern war would be over in a few weeks. In 1939, following further improvements in military technology, the Nazis planned to win a two-front war. In 2003, Bush and Blair predicted their high-tech Iraq invasion would be fast and efficient with few casualties. Most economists failed to predict the 2008 financial crisis.
According to the availability heuristic (Tversky and Kahneman, 1973), people are more likely to judge an event as likely or frequent if instances are easy to imagine or recall. This gives people first-hand experiences of the event’s consequences (Spence et al., 2011. In the case of AGW, no such instances are available, because the situation is unprecedented and hindsight is not possible. “Risks of human extinction may tend to be underestimated since, obviously, humanity has never yet encountered an extinction event” (Yudkowsky, 2008, p. 93).
Many believe that AGW will be mitigated by technological advances (Hulme, 2014). Technology has solved many problems before, radically improving standards of living—in both rich and poor countries. But reliance on technology to solve future problems is an example of the logical fallacy of “hasty generalization.” Many technological solutions to AGW are possible, but all are subject to physical, social, and economic limitations (Huesemann, 2003). All currently known climate-engineering solutions have limited effectiveness and/or dangerous byproducts (Keller et al., 2014). Technology can hardly solve behavioral problems grounded in evolution such as xenophobia and selfishness that alone could lead to human self-destruction (cf. Persson and Savulescu, 2013).
Finally, a lack of positive active engagement with climate issues may cause individuals to underestimate the magnitude of the problem. Passivity may be promoted by public information that induces fear rather than “non-threatening imagery and icons that link to individuals’ everyday emotions and concerns” (O'Neill and Nicholson-Cole, 2009, p. 355).
Semi-Quantitative Prediction
The predicted death rates are semi-quantitative, lying between qualitative and quantitative and relying on OMEs. An underlying assumption is that a very rough estimate is better than none at all. It is more informative to speak of “very roughly a million people,” and to base ethical, political, and economic arguments on such estimates, than merely to consider “a very large number of people.”
A semi-quantitative approach to ethics can clarify the magnitude and importance of AGW by comparison to other dangers. For example, since 2001 the threat of terrorism has influenced politics and policy more than the threat of climate change (Sunstein, 2007). In Western or richer countries, terrorists sometimes kill ten or a hundred people, attracting extensive media coverage. While every such attack is a tragedy, it is small compared to other cases of violence. The ongoing crisis in Iraq receives relatively little media attention despite the roughly 10,000 violent documented deaths every year since the 2003 US-UK invasion (Iraq Body Count, internet). Yet even that national tragedy is small compared to the human cost of poverty and AGW. The global number of under-five deaths per year decreased from over 1.2 × 107 in 1990 to 7.6 × 106 in 2010 (Pérez-Moreno et al., 2016). Between 5 and 14 years of age, 106 children are dying yearly from mainly preventable causes (Fadel et al., 2019). The present analysis suggests that global GHG emissions are killing future people (mainly children) at a comparable rate.
Conclusion
Convergent evidence from diverse approaches suggests that 2°C AGW, caused by burning 1012 tonnes of carbon (equivalent), will kill roughly 109 people over a period of one to two centuries. Therefore, one future person is killed every time roughly 103 tonnes of carbon are burned. This “1,000-tonne rule” implies that every fossil fuel industry whose productivity can be expressed in millions of tonnes of burned carbon is causing the premature deaths of thousands of future people. Consider the following examples:
1. A typical passenger jet carries 300,000 l of fuel and consumes 200,000 on a long flight, creating 500 tonnes of CO2 corresponding to 135 tonnes of carbon. That is about 1/8 of 1,000 tonnes, or 1/8 of a human life, according to the 1,000-tonne rule. Aircraft also emit other GHGs, and the high altitude at which the GHGs are emitted must also be considered. If the overall warming effect is at least twice the effect of the CO2 alone (Penner et al., 1999), a future person dies for every four long flights, on average. Therefore, flying should be made more expensive (e.g. by carbon taxes) and reserved for emergencies and life-saving projects.
2. Every year, Australia exports 4 × 108 tonnes of coal. If that coal is 80% carbon, the country is exporting about 3 × 108 tonnes of carbon per year. When that coal is burned, 3 × 105 future deaths are caused every year. Clearly, this and comparable industries must be rapidly wound down to protect the rights of future generations. Employees can be retrained for the growing sustainable energy industry (Louie and Pearce, 2016).
3. The 1,000-tonne rule allows the 2015 Paris agreement to be newly interpreted as an agreement to limit the number of deaths caused by AGW to 109. A statement of that kind has enormous political and ethical implications.
Quantitative mortality estimates allow policy decisions to draw more systematically on comparisons between AGW with other anthropogenic causes of premature death. Cigarettes currently kill 7 × 106 people per year (Rentería et al., 2016). Comprehensive cigarette advertising bans can significantly reduce the incidence of smoking (Saffer and Chaloupka, 2000). GHG emissions are killing future people at a comparable or higher rate, and fossil fuel consumption has been likened to addiction (Suranovic, 2013). Therefore, advertising for fossil cars and distant holidays (implying flying) should be comprehensively banned.
The 1,000-tonne rule can help estimate energy risks and guide policy decisions in other ways. In 2014, world energy consumption comprised fossil fuels (86%), hydro/bioenergy/geothermal (8%), nuclear (4%), and wind/solar (2%) (Moriarty and Honnery, 2016). In 2017, the proportions were oil 34%, coal 28%, natural gas 23%, and renewables 4% (BP, 2018). What proportions would be sustainable in the 22nd century? The question may be reduced to one of mathematical optimization (cf. Nordhaus, 1994). A human-rights approach would minimize the number of lives lost per energy unit.
Also relevant is the question of whether nuclear energy is a reasonable alternative to fossil fuels in the anthropocene (Hansen et al., 2013b). The answer depends on predicted long-term mortality per unit energy for each source. For nuclear power, one might estimate the probability of different accident scenarios and the number of deaths caused by each, including scenarios in which nuclear wastes impact future generations. The nuclear industry estimated the cancer death toll from the Chernobyl meltdown in 1986 to be a few thousands, but it could have exceeded 105 (Yablokov et al., 2010). Considering other nuclear accidents, nuclear energy may currently be causing roughly 105 deaths globally per year (OME) by comparison to 107 for fossil fuels. Fossil fuels, which are generating some 20 times more power than nuclear fission, may be causing 100 times (OME) more deaths, making them five times (OME) less efficient in this human-rights-oriented sense—consistent with Hansen’s claim. But renewables can also cause future deaths: the land used by solar power plants might otherwise be used for agriculture, alleviating future famines, and hydroelectricity affects biodiversity when rivers are dammed.
The main limitation of the present approach is uncertainty. All numerical estimates are assumed uncertain by plus or minus a few tens of percent—unavoidable, when extrapolating toward unprecedented future situations. But the explicit acknowledgment of uncertainty is also a strength. IPPC reports were improved by quantifying probabilities associated with qualifiers such as “likely” (>66%) or “virtually certain” (>99%) (IPCC, 2010).
Another limitation is the explicitly anthropocentric focus. Only human lives have been considered; the intrinsic value of other species (ecocentric and biocentric ethics; Nolt, 2011b) has been ignored. Deaths and extinctions of other species have been considered only relative to their effect on human mortality. A more ecocentric approach might have significant implications for conservation practice and policy (Kopnina et al., 2018). One might “take a pragmatic approach by which primary human needs are met first and foremost whereas the needs of other living organisms and ecosystems are allowed to prevail over secondary human needs” (Bourdeau, 2004, p. 9).
The question of economic growth versus steady-state economies (Buch-Hansen, 2014) has not been considered. In a cost-benefit analysis, the economic benefits of growth in the absence of environmental degradation may have fallen below the effective long-term environmental costs (the cost of inaction; Bosetti et al., 2009). But the dependence of future death tolls on carbon burned in the present analysis may be largely independent of economic context.
The possibility of future discounting (Dasgupta, 2008) has not been systematically considered, nor has the precautionary principle (Kriebel et al., 2001). These two principles would change predictions in opposite directions and partially cancel each other.
Data Availability Statement
The raw data supporting the conclusions of this manuscript will be made available by the authors, without undue reservation, to any qualified researcher.
Author Contributions
The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.
Funding
The author acknowledges the financial support by the University of Graz.
Conflict of Interest
The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Footnotes
References
Abbott, G. (2010). Dying and killing: euphemisms in current English. Engl. Today 26, 51–52. doi: 10.1017/S0266078410000349
Adger, W. N., Barnett, J., Brown, K., Marshall, N., and O’Brien, K. (2013). Cultural dimensions of climate change impacts and adaptation. Nat. Clim. Chang. 3, 112–117. doi: 10.1038/nclimate1666
Allen, M. R., Frame, D. J., Huntingford, C., Jones, C. D., Lowe, J. A., Meinshausen, M., et al. (2009). Warming caused by cumulative carbon emissions towards the trillionth tonne. Nature 458, 1163–1166. doi: 10.1038/nature08019
Amnesty International (n.d.). Climate change. Available at: amnesty.org/en/what-we-do/climate-change (Accessed March 29, 2019).
Apfel, F. (2007). Environmental change and infectious diseases workshop. Stockholm: Meeting Report. European Centre for Disease Prevention and Control Available at: ecdc.europa.eu
Archer, D., Eby, M., Brovkin, V., Ridgwell, A., Cao, L., Mikolajewicz, U., et al. (2009). Atmospheric lifetime of fossil fuel carbon dioxide. Annu. Rev. Earth Planet. Sci. 37, 117–134. doi: 10.1146/annurev.earth.031208.100206
Arsenault, C. (2014). Only 60 years of farming left if soil degradation continues. Sci. Am. 5. Available at: scientificamerican.com (Accessed November 20, 2018).
Barnett, J., and Adger, W. N. (2007). Climate change, human security and violent conflict. Polit. Geogr. 26, 639–655. doi: 10.1016/j.polgeo.2007.03.003
Bevis, M., Harig, C., Khan, S. A., Brown, A., Simons, F. J., Willis, M., et al. (2019). Accelerating changes in ice mass within Greenland, and the ice sheet’s sensitivity to atmospheric forcing. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 116, 1934–1939. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1806562116
Black, R. E., Victora, C. G., Walker, S. P., Bhutta, Z. A., Christian, P., De Onis, M., et al. (2013). Maternal and child undernutrition and overweight in low-income and middle-income countries. Lancet 382, 427–451. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(13)60937-X
Boggs, C. L. (2016). The fingerprints of global climate change on insect populations. Curr. Opin. Insect Sci. 17, 69–73. doi: 10.1016/j.cois.2016.07.004
Booth, C. (2012). Bystanding and climate change. Environ. Values 21, 397–416. doi: 10.3197/096327112X13466893627987
Bosetti, V., Carraro, C., Sgobbi, A., and Tavoni, M. (2009). Delayed action and uncertain stabilisation targets. How much will the delay cost? Clim. Chang. 96, 299–312. doi: 10.1007/s10584-009-9630-2
Bourdeau, P. (2004). The man−nature relationship and environmental ethics. J. Environ. Radioact. 72, 9–15. doi: 10.1016/S0265-931X(03)00180-2
Bourne, A. J., Abbott, P. M., Albert, P. G., Cook, E., Pearce, N. J. G., Ponomareva, V., et al. (2016). Underestimated risks of recurrent long-range ash dispersal from northern Pacific arc volcanoes. Sci. Rep. 6:29837. doi: 10.1038/srep29837
BP (2018). BP statistical review of world energy (67th Edn). Available at: bp.com
Brysse, K., Oreskes, N., O’Reilly, J., and Oppenheimer, M. (2013). Climate change prediction: erring on the side of least drama? Glob. Environ. Chang. 23, 327–337. doi: 10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2012.10.008
Buch-Hansen, H. (2014). Capitalist diversity and de-growth trajectories to steady-state economies. Ecol. Econ. 106, 167–173. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2014.07.030
Burke, L., Reytar, K., Spalding, M., and Perry, A. (2011). Reefs at risk revisited. Washington, DC: World Resources Institute. Available at: wri.org
Caney, S. (2010). “Climate change, human rights, and moral thresholds” in Climate ethics: Essential readings. eds. D. Jamieson and H. Shue (New York: Oxford University Press), 163–177.
Carter, T. R., Fronzek, S., Inkinen, A., Lahtinen, I., Lahtinen, M., Mela, H., et al. (2016). Characterising vulnerability of the elderly to climate change in the Nordic region. Reg. Environ. Chang. 16, 43–58. doi: 10.1007/s10113-014-0688-7
Carter, D., and Merrill, H. (2007). Bordering humanism: life and death on the margins of Europe. Geopolitics 12, 248–264. doi: 10.1080/14650040601168867
Central Intelligence Agency (n.d.). The world factbook: Life expectancy at birth. Available at: theworldfactbook.info (Accessed February 15, 2018).
Cheng, L., Abraham, J., Hausfather, Z., and Trenberth, K. E. (2019). How fast are the oceans warming? Science 363, 128–129. doi: 10.1126/science.aav7619
Clarke, G. K., Jarosch, A. H., Anslow, F. S., Radić, V., and Menounos, B. (2015). Projected deglaciation of western Canada in the twenty-first century. Nat. Geosci. 8, 372–377. doi: 10.1038/ngeo2407
Climate Change Impacts and Risk Analysis (2015). Climate change in the United States: Benefits of global action. Washington, DC: Environmental Protection Association (EPA). Available at: epa.gov/cira
Cohen, J. E. (2003). Human population: the next half century. Science 302, 1172–1175. doi: 10.1126/science.1088665
Cuthbert, M. O., Gleeson, T., Moosdorf, N., Befus, K. M., Schneider, A., Hartmann, J., et al. (2019). Global patterns and dynamics of climate–groundwater interactions. Nat. Clim. Chang. 9, 137–141. doi: 10.1038/s41558-018-0386-4
Dalin, C., Wada, Y., Kastner, T., and Puma, M. J. (2017). Groundwater depletion embedded in international food trade. Nature 543, 700–704. doi: 10.1038/nature21403
DARA International (2012). Climate vulnerability monitor (2nd Edn). Available at: daraint.org
Dasgupta, P. (2008). Discounting climate change. J. Risk Uncertain. 37, 141–169. doi: 10.1007/s11166-008-9049-6
Dehaene, S. (2003). The neural basis of the Weber–Fechner law: a logarithmic mental number line. Trends Cogn. Sci. 7, 145–147. doi: 10.1016/S1364-6613(03)00055-X
Democracy Now (2007). George Monbiot: “If we don’t deal with climate change we condemn hundreds of millions of people to death.” Available at: democracynow.org (Accessed February 16, 2018).
Drost, E. A. (2011). Validity and reliability in social science research. Educ. Res. Pers. 38, 105–123.
Economist (2018 May 31). Climate change is making the Arab world more miserable: Expect longer droughts, hotter heatwaves and more frequent dust storms. Available at: www.economist.com (Accessed November 16, 2018).
Egondi, T., Ettarh, R., Kyobutungi, C., Ng, N., and Rocklöv, J. (2018). Exposure to outdoor particles (PM2. 5) and associated child morbidity and mortality in socially deprived neighborhoods of Nairobi, Kenya. Atmosphere 9:351. doi: 10.3390/atmos9090351
Fadel, S. A., Boschi-Pinto, C., Yu, S., Reynales-Shigematsu, L. M., Menon, G. R., Newcombe, L., et al. (2019). Trends in cause-specific mortality among children aged 5–14 years from 2005 to 2016 in India, China, Brazil, and Mexico: an analysis of nationally representative mortality studies. Lancet 393, 1119–1127. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(19)30220-X
Fairchild, H. H. (1991). Scientific racism: the cloak of objectivity. J. Soc. Issues 47, 101–115. doi: 10.1111/j.1540-4560.1991.tb01825.x
Fankhauser, S. (1994). The social costs of greenhouse gas emissions: an expected value approach. Energy J. 15, 157–184.
Fetherstonhaugh, D., Slovic, P., Johnson, S. M., and Friedrich, J. (1997). Insensitivity to the value of human life: a study of psychophysical numbing. J. Risk Uncertain. 14, 282–300.
Fielding, K. S., and Hornsey, M. J. (2016). A social identity analysis of climate change and environmental attitudes and behaviors: insights and opportunities. Front. Psychol. 7:121. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00121
Fontaine, K. R., Redden, D. T., Wang, C., Westfall, A. O., and Allison, D. B. (2003). Years of life lost due to obesity. J. Am. Med. Assoc. 289, 187–193. doi: 10.1001/jama.289.2.187
Friedlingstein, P., Cox, P., Betts, R., Bopp, L., von Bloh, W., Brovkin, V., et al. (2006). Climate–carbon cycle feedback analysis: results from the C4MIP model intercomparison. J. Clim. 19, 3337–3353, doi: 10.1175/JCLI3800.1
Frison, E. A., Cherfas, J., and Hodgkin, T. (2011). Agricultural biodiversity is essential for a sustainable improvement in food and nutrition security. Sustainability 3, 238–253. doi: 10.3390/su3010238
Friston, K. J., and Frith, C. D. (2015). Active inference, communication and hermeneutics. Cortex 68, 129–143. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2015.03.025
Gabbert, B. (2018). Climate assessment predicts increasing wildfire: By mid-century western wildfires could increase 200 to 600%. Available at: wildfiretoday.com
Galvani, A. P., and Slatkin, M. (2003). Evaluating plague and smallpox as historical selective pressures for the CCR5-Δ32 HIV-resistance allele. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 100, 15276–15279. doi: 10.1073/pnas.2435085100
Gattuso, J. P., Magnan, A., Billé, R., Cheung, W. W., Howes, E. L., Joos, F., et al. (2015). Contrasting futures for ocean and society from different anthropogenic CO2 emissions scenarios. Science 349:aac4722. doi: 10.1126/science.aac4722
Ge, M., Lebling, K., Levin, K., and Friedrich, J. (2019). Tracking progress of the 2020 climate turning point. Washington, DC: World Resources Institute. Available at: wri.org
Gifford, R. (2011). The dragons of inaction: psychological barriers that limit climate change mitigation and adaptation. Am. Psychol. 66, 290–302. doi: 10.1037/a0023566
Gingerich, P. D. (2019). Temporal scaling of carbon emission and accumulation rates: modern anthropogenic emissions compared to estimates of PETM-onset accumulation. Paleoceanogr. Paleoclimatol. 34, 329–335. doi: 10.1029/2018PA003379
Gleeson, T., Befus, K. M., Jasechko, S., Luijendijk, E., and Cardenas, M. B. (2016). The global volume and distribution of modern groundwater. Nat. Geosci. 9, 161–170. doi: 10.1038/ngeo2590
Gleick, P. H. (2014). Water, drought, climate change, and conflict in Syria. Weather Clim. Soc. 6, 331–340. doi: 10.1175/WCAS-D-13-00059.1
Godfray, H. C. J., Beddington, J. R., Crute, I. R., Haddad, L., Lawrence, D., Muir, J. F., et al. (2010). Food security: the challenge of feeding 9 billion people. Science 327, 812–818. doi: 10.1126/science.1185383
Goulson, D. (2014). Ecology: pesticides linked to bird declines. Nature 511, 295–296. doi: 10.1038/nature13642
Goulson, D., Nicholls, E., Botías, C., and Rotheray, E. L. (2015). Bee declines driven by combined stress from parasites, pesticides, and lack of flowers. Science 347:1255957. doi: 10.1126/science.1255957
Green, J. K., Seneviratne, S. I., Berg, A. M., Findell, K. L., Hagemann, S., Lawrence, D. M., et al. (2019). Large influence of soil moisture on long-term terrestrial carbon uptake. Nature 565, 476–479. doi: 10.1038/s41586-018-0848-x
Gregory, J. M., Jones, C. D., Cadule, P., and Friedlingstein, P. (2009). Quantifying carbon cycle feedbacks. J. Clim. 22, 5232–5250. doi: 10.1175/2009JCLI2949.1
Guardian (2009 November 3). Global warming could create 150 million ‘climate refugees’ by 2050. Available at: theguardian.com (Accessed February 24, 2018).
Hakes, J. K., and Viscusi, W. K. (2004). Dead reckoning: demographic determinants of the accuracy of mortality risk perceptions. Risk Anal. 24, 651–664. doi: 10.1111/j.0272-4332.2004.00465.x
Hansen, J., Kharecha, P., Sato, M., Masson-Delmotte, V., Ackerman, F., Beerling, D. J., et al. (2013b). Assessing “dangerous climate change”: required reduction of carbon emissions to protect young people, future generations and nature. PLoS One 8:e81648. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0081648
Hansen, M. C., Potapov, P. V., Moore, R., Hancher, M., Turubanova, S. A. A., Tyukavina, A., et al. (2013a). High-resolution global maps of 21st-century forest cover change. Science 342, 850–853. doi: 10.1126/science.1244693
Harvey, H., Orr, F. M., and Vondrich, C. (2013). A trillion tons. Daedalus 142, 8–25. doi: 10.1162/DAED_a_00182
Hasegawa, T., Fujimori, S., Mason-D’Croz, D., Wiebe, K. D., and Sulser, T. B. (2018). Risk of increased food insecurity under stringent global climate change mitigation policy. Nat. Clim. Chang. 8, 699–703. doi: 10.1038/s41558-018-0230-x
Henley, E. J., and Kumamoto, H. (1981). Reliability engineering and risk assessment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Hirth, R. A., Chernew, M. E., Miller, E., Fendrick, A. M., and Weissert, W. G. (2000). Willingness to pay for a quality-adjusted life year: in search of a standard. Med. Decis. Mak. 20, 332–342. doi: 10.1186/1472-6963-14-287
Holmes, J. (1984). Modifying illocutionary force. J. Pragmat. 8, 345–365. doi: 10.1016/0378-2166(84)90028-6
Huber, V., Ibarreta, D., and Frieler, K. (2017). Cold-and heat-related mortality: a cautionary note on current damage functions with net benefits from climate change. Clim. Chang. 142, 407–418. doi: 10.1007/s10584-017-1956-6
Huesemann, M. H. (2003). The limits of technological solutions to sustainable development. Clean Techn. Environ. Policy 5, 21–34. doi: 10.1007/s10098-002-0173-8
Hughes, T. P., Barnes, M. L., Bellwood, D. R., Cinner, J. E., Cumming, G. S., Jackson, J. B., et al. (2017). Coral reefs in the anthropocene. Nature 546:82. doi: 10.1038/nature22901
Hulme, M. (2014). Can science fix climate change? A case against climate engineering. Cambridge, UK: Polity.
International Energy Agency (2019). Global energy & CO2 status report: The latest trends in energy and emissions in 2018. Available at: iea.org/geco
IPCC (2010). Guidance notes for lead authors of the IPCC fourth assessment report on addressing uncertainties. Available at: http://www.ipcc.ch/pdf/supporting-material/uncertainty-guidance-note.pdf
Jaspal, R., Nerlich, B., and Cinnirella, M. (2014). Human responses to climate change: social representation, identity and socio-psychological action. Environ. Commun. 8, 110–130. doi: 10.1080/17524032.2013.846270
Jorgenson, A. K. (2014). Economic development and the carbon intensity of human well-being. Nat. Clim. Chang. 4, 186–189. doi: 10.1038/nclimate2110
Kagawa, F., and Selby, D. (Eds.) (2010). Education and climate change: Living and learning in interesting times. Oxford: Routledge.
Kaijser, A., and Kronsell, A. (2014). Climate change through the lens of intersectionality. Environ. Polit. 23, 417–433. doi: 10.1080/09644016.2013.835203
Kalkstein, L. S., and Greene, J. S. (1997). An evaluation of climate/mortality relationships in large US cities and the possible impacts of a climate change. Environ. Health Perspect. 105, 84–93. doi: 10.1289/ehp.9710584
Kant, I. (1785/2011). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals: A German-English edition. transl. M. Gregor and J. Timmermann. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.
Keller, D. P., Feng, E. Y., and Oschlies, A. (2014). Potential climate engineering effectiveness and side effects during a high carbon dioxide-emission scenario. Nat. Commun. 5:3304. doi: 10.1038/ncomms4304
Kellert, S. R. (1997). The value of life: Biological diversity and human society. Washington, DC: Island Press.
Knutson, T. R., Sirutis, J. J., Zhao, M., Tuleya, R. E., Bender, M., Vecchi, G. A., et al. (2015). Global projections of intense tropical cyclone activity for the late twenty-first century from dynamical downscaling of CMIP5/RCP4. Five scenarios. J. Clim. 28, 7203–7224. doi: 10.1175/JCLI-D-15-0129.1
Knutti, R., Rugenstein, M. A., and Hegerl, G. C. (2017). Beyond equilibrium climate sensitivity. Nat. Geosci. 10, 727–736. doi: 10.1038/ngeo3017
Kopnina, H., Washington, H., Gray, J., and Taylor, B. (2018). The ‘future of conservation’ debate: defending ecocentrism and the nature needs half movement. Biol. Conserv. 217, 140–148. doi: 10.1016/j.biocon.2017.10.016
Kravchenko, S. (2007). Right to carbon or right to life: human rights approaches to climate change. Vt. J. Environ. Law 9, 513–547. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.1304844
Kriebel, D., Tickner, J., Epstein, P., Lemons, J., Levins, R., Loechler, E. L., et al. (2001). The precautionary principle in environmental science. Environ. Health Perspect. 109, 871–876. doi: 10.1289/ehp.01109871
Le Quéré, C., Andrew, R. M., Friedlingstein, P., Sitch, S., Pongratz, J., Manning, A. C., et al. (2018). Global carbon budget 2017. Earth Syst. Sci. Data 10, 405–448. doi: 10.5194/essd-10-405-2018
Legendre, M., Lartigue, A., Bertaux, L., Jeudy, S., Bartoli, J., Lescot, M., et al. (2015). In-depth study of Mollivirus sibericum, a new 30,000-y-old giant virus infecting Acanthamoeba. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 112, E5327–E5335. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1510795112
Lehman, D. R., and Taylor, S. E. (1987). Date with an earthquake: coping with a probable, unpredictable disaster. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 13, 546–555.
Lelieveld, J., Evans, J. S., Fnais, M., Giannadaki, D., and Pozzer, A. (2015). The contribution of outdoor air pollution sources to premature mortality on a global scale. Nature 525, 367–371. doi: 10.1038/nature15371
Lifton, R. J. (1982). Beyond psychic numbing: a call to awareness. Am. J. Orthopsychiatry 52, 619–629. doi: 10.1111/j.1939-0025.1982.tb01451.x
Louie, E. P., and Pearce, J. M. (2016). Retraining investment for US transition from coal to solar photovoltaic employment. Energy Econ. 57, 295–302. doi: 10.1016/j.eneco.2016.05.016
Lowe, J. A., and Bernie, D. (2018). The impact of earth system feedbacks on carbon budgets and climate response. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. A Math. Phys. Eng. Sci. 376:20170263. doi: 10.1098/rsta.2017.0263
MacDougall, A. H., Avis, C. A., and Weaver, A. J. (2012). Significant contribution to climate warming from the permafrost carbon feedback. Nat. Geosci. 5, 719–721. doi: 10.1038/ngeo1573
Maier, C. S. (1988). The unmasterable past: History, holocaust, and German national identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Matthews, H. D., Gillett, N. P., Stott, P. A., and Zickfeld, K. (2009). The proportionality of global warming to cumulative carbon emissions. Nature 459, 829–832. doi: 10.1038/nature08047
McMichael, A. J., Friel, S., Nyong, A., and Corvalan, C. (2008). Global environmental change and health: impacts, inequalities, and the health sector. Br. Med. J. 336, 191–194. doi: 10.1136/bmj.39392.473727.AD
McMichael, A. J., Woodruff, R. E., and Hales, S. (2006). Climate change and human health: present and future risks. Lancet 367, 859–869. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(06)68079-3
Mills, M. J., Toon, O. B., Turco, R. P., Kinnison, D. E., and Garcia, R. R. (2008). Massive global ozone loss predicted following regional nuclear conflict. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 105, 5307–5312. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0710058105
Mora, C., Dousset, B., Caldwell, I. R., Powell, F. E., Geronimo, R. C., Bielecki, C. R., et al. (2017). Global risk of deadly heat. Nat. Clim. Chang. 7, 501–507. doi: 10.1038/nclimate3322
Moriarty, P., and Honnery, D. (2016). Can renewable energy power the future? Energy Policy 93, 3–7. doi: 10.1016/j.enpol.2016.02.051
Murray, C. J. (1994). Quantifying the burden of disease: the technical basis for disability-adjusted life years. Bull. World Health Organ. 72, 429–445.
Myhre, G., Myhre, C. L., Forster, P. M., and Shine, K. P. (2017). Halfway to doubling of CO2 radiative forcing. Nat. Geosci. 10, 710–711. doi: 10.1038/ngeo3036
Nakicenovic, N., Alcamo, J., Grubler, A., Riahi, K., Roehrl, R. A., Rogner, H. H., et al. (2000). Special report on emissions scenarios (SRES), a special report of working group III of the intergovernmental panel on climate change. Cambridge, GB: Cambridge University Press.
Nguyen, G. T., Pu, J., and Watanabe, T. (2019). “Floods and foods as potential carriers of disease between urban and rural areas” in Health in ecological perspectives in the anthropocene eds. T. Watanabe and C. Watanabe (Singapore: Springer), 133–144.
Nicholls, N. (2009). Estimating changes in mortality due to climate change. Clim. Chang. 97:313. doi: 10.1007/s10584-009-9694-z
Nilsson, M., Griggs, D., and Visbeck, M. (2016). Policy: map the interactions between sustainable development goals. Nat. News 534, 320–322. doi: 10.1038/534320a
Nisbet, E. G., Manning, M. R., Dlugokencky, E. J., Fisher, R. E., Lowry, D., Michel, S. E., et al. (2018). Very strong atmospheric methane growth in the four years 2014-2017: implications for the Paris agreement. Glob. Biogeochem. Cycles. 33, 318–342. AGU100: Advance online publication, Advancing Earth and Space Science. doi: 10.1029/2018GB006009
Nolt, J. (2011a). How harmful are the average American’s greenhouse gas emissions? Ethics Policy Environ. 14, 3–10. doi: 10.1080/21550085.2011.561584
Nolt, J. (2015). Casualties as a moral measure of climate change. Clim. Chang. 130, 347–358. doi: 10.1007/s10584-014-1131-2
Nordhaus, W. D. (1994). Managing the global commons: The economics of climate change. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
O’Neill, S., and Nicholson-Cole, S. (2009). “Fear won’t do it” promoting positive engagement with climate change through visual and iconic representations. Sci. Commun. 30, 355–379. doi: 10.1177/1075547008329201
Oreskes, N. (2004). The scientific consensus on climate change. Science 306, 1686–1168. doi: 10.1126/science.1103618
Our World in Data (n.d.). The visual history of hunger and food provision. Available at: ourworldindata.org (Accessed November 13, 2018).
Penner, J. E., Lister, D., Griggs, D. J., McFarland, M., and Dokken, D. J. (1999). Aviation and the global atmosphere: A special report of the intergovernmental panel on climate change. Cambridge, GB: Cambridge University Press.
Pérez-Moreno, S., Blanco-Arana, M. C., and Bárcena-Martín, E. (2016). Economic cycles and child mortality: a cross-national study of the least developed countries. Econ. Hum. Biol. 22, 14–23. doi: 10.1016/j.ehb.2016.02.005
Persson, I., and Savulescu, J. (2013). Getting moral enhancement right: the desirability of moral bioenhancement. Bioethics 27, 124–131. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2011.01907.x
Petersen-Perlman, J. D., Veilleux, J. C., and Wolf, A. T. (2017). International water conflict and cooperation: challenges and opportunities. Water Int. 42, 105–120. doi: 10.1080/02508060.2017.1276041
Phillips, E., Fraser, S., Murnane, R., Paul, N., Cox, K., Daniell, J., et al. (2018). Aftershocks: Remodeling the past for a resilient future. Washington D.C.: Global Facility for Disaster Reduction and Recovery and World Bank. Available at: gfdrr.org
Pirani, A., Moufouma-Okia, W., Péan, C., Pidcock, R., Connors, S., Matthews, J. B. R., et al. (2018). Global warming of 1.5°C. an IPCC special report on the impacts of global warming of 1.5°C above pre-industrial levels and related global greenhouse gas emission pathways, in the context of strengthening the global response to the threat of climate change, sustainable development, and efforts to eradicate poverty. eds. V. Masson-Delmotte, P. Zhai, H. O. Pörtner, D. Roberts, J. Skea, and P. R. Shukla (Geneva, Switzerland: World Meteorological Organization).
Pogge, T. (2001). Priorities of global justice. Metaphilosophy 32, 6–24. doi: 10.1111/1467-9973.00172
Poore, R. Z., Williams, R. S. Jr., and Tracey, C. (2000). Sea level and climate: U.S. Geological Survey Fact Sheet 002–00. Available at: https://pubs.usgs.gov/fs/fs2-00
Prather, M. J., Holmes, C. D., and Hsu, J. (2012). Reactive greenhouse gas scenarios: systematic exploration of uncertainties and the role of atmospheric chemistry. Geophys. Res. Lett. 39:L09803. doi: 10.1029/2012GL051440
Radić, V., Bliss, A., Beedlow, A. C., Hock, R., Miles, E., and Cogley, J. G. (2014). Regional and global projections of twenty-first century glacier mass changes in response to climate scenarios from global climate models. Clim. Dyn. 42, 37–58. doi: 10.1007/s00382-013-1719-7
Rahmstorf, S. (2010). A new view on sea level rise. Nat. Rep. Clim. Chan. 4, 44–45. doi: 10.1038/climate.2010.29
Rahmstorf, S., Cazenave, A., Church, J. A., Hansen, J. E., Keeling, R. F., Parker, D. E., et al. (2007). Recent climate observations compared to projections. Science 316, 709–709. doi: 10.1126/science.1136843
Rahmstorf, S., Foster, G., and Cazenave, A. (2012). Comparing climate projections to observations up to 2011. Environ. Res. Lett. 7:044035. doi: 10.1088/1748-9326/7/4/044035
Reidmiller, D. R. (Ed.) (2018). Impacts, risks, and adaptation in the United States: Fourth national climate assessment. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Global Change Research Program. Available at: nca2018.globalchange.gov
Rentería, E., Jha, P., Forman, D., and Soerjomataram, I. (2016). The impact of cigarette smoking on life expectancy between 1980 and 2010: a global perspective. Tob. Control. 25, 551–557. doi: 10.1136/tobaccocontrol-2015-052265
Resnick, B. (2019). We have a new global tally of the insect apocalypse. It’s alarming. When insects go extinct, other species follow. Vox. Available at: vox.com/energy-and-environment
Resplandy, L., Keeling, R. F., Eddebbar, Y., Brooks, M. K., Wang, R., Bopp, L., et al. (2018). Quantification of ocean heat uptake from changes in atmospheric O2 and CO2 composition. Nature 563, 105–108. doi: 10.1038/s41586-018-0651-8
Revich, B. A., and Podolnaya, M. A. (2011). Thawing of permafrost may disturb historic cattle burial grounds in East Siberia. Glob. Health Action 4:8482. doi: 10.3402/gha.v4i0.8482
Ripple, W. J., Wolf, C., Newsome, T. M., Galetti, M., Alamgir, M., Crist, E., et al. (2017). World scientists’ warning to humanity: a second notice. Bioscience 67, 1026–1028. doi: 10.1093/biosci/bix125
Roser, M., and Ritchie, H. (2018). Hunger and undernourishment. Available at: https://ourworldindata.org/hunger-and-undernourishment (Accessed November 13, 2018).
Saba, V. S., Griffies, S. M., Anderson, W. G., Winton, M., Alexander, M. A., Delworth, T. L., et al. (2016). Enhanced warming of the Northwest Atlantic Ocean under climate change. J. Geophys. Res. Oceans 121, 118–132. doi: 10.1002/2015JC011346
Sachs, J. (2008). The end of poverty: economic possibilities for our time. Eur. J. Dent. Educ. 12, 17–21. doi: 10.1111/j.1600-0579.2007.00476.x
Saffer, H., and Chaloupka, F. (2000). The effect of tobacco advertising bans on tobacco consumption. J. Health Econ. 19, 1117–1137. doi: 10.1016/S0167-6296(00)00054-0
Sánchez-Bayo, F., and Wyckhuys, K. A. (2019). Worldwide decline of the entomofauna: a review of its drivers. Biol. Conserv. 232, 8–27. doi: 10.1016/j.biocon.2019.01.020
Sandman, P. (2009). Climate change risk communication: The problem of psychological denial. Available at: psandman.com (Accessed February 24, 2018).
Sangüesa-Barreda, G., Linares, J. C., and Camarero, J. J. (2015). Reduced growth sensitivity to climate in bark-beetle infested Aleppo pines: connecting climatic and biotic drivers of forest dieback. For. Ecol. Manag. 357, 126–137. doi: 10.1016/j.foreco.2015.08.017
Sayer, A. (2011). Why things matter to people: Social science, values and ethical life. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.
Scherer, G. (2012). Climate science predictions prove too conservative. Sci. Am. 6 Available at: scientificamerican.com, dailyclimate.org
Searchinger, T. D., Wirsenius, S., Beringer, T., and Dumas, P. (2018). Assessing the efficiency of changes in land use for mitigating climate change. Nature 564, 249–253. doi: 10.1038/s41586-018-0757-z
Sekerci, Y., and Petrovskii, S. (2015). Mathematical modelling of plankton–oxygen dynamics under the climate change. Bull. Math. Biol. 77, 2325–2353. doi: 10.1007/s11538-015-0126-0
Senf, C., Pflugmacher, D., Zhiqiang, Y., Sebald, J., Knorn, J., Neumann, M., et al. (2018). Canopy mortality has doubled in Europe’s temperate forests over the last three decades. Nat. Commun. 9:4978. doi: 10.1038/s41467-018-07539-6
Serway, R. A., and Jewett, J. W. (2018). Physics for scientists and engineers with modern physics. 10th Edn. Boston, MA: Cengage Learning.
Sherwood, S. C., and Huber, M. (2010). An adaptability limit to climate change due to heat stress. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 107, 9552–9555. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0913352107
Shogren, E. (2019). Scientist who resisted censorship of climate report lost her job. Reveal. Available at: revealnews.org
Smith, M. R., and Myers, S. S. (2018). Impact of anthropogenic CO2 emissions on global human nutrition. Nat. Clim. Chang. 8, 834–841. doi: 10.1038/s41558-018-0253-3
Solomon, S., Plattner, G. K., Knutti, R., and Friedlingstein, P. (2009). Irreversible climate change due to carbon dioxide emissions. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 106, 1704–1709. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0812721106
Spence, A., Poortinga, W., Butler, C., and Pidgeon, N. F. (2011). Perceptions of climate change and willingness to save energy related to flood experience. Nat. Clim. Chang. 1, 46–49. doi: 10.1038/nclimate1059
Steinberger, J. K., and Roberts, J. T. (2010). From constraint to sufficiency: the decoupling of energy and carbon from human needs, 1975–2005. Ecol. Econ. 70, 425–433. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2010.09.014
Stern, P. C. (2011). Contributions of psychology to limiting climate change. Am. Psychol. 66, 303–314. doi: 10.1037/a0023235
Stoll-Kleemann, S., O’Riordan, T., and Jaeger, C. C. (2001). The psychology of denial concerning climate mitigation measures: evidence from Swiss focus groups. Glob. Environ. Chang. 11, 107–117. doi: 10.1016/S0959-3780(00)00061-3
Strona, G., and Bradshaw, C. J. A. (2018). Co-extinctions annihilate planetary life during extreme environmental change. Sci. Rep. 8:16724. doi: 10.1038/s41598-018-35068-1
Sunstein, C. R. (2007). On the divergent American reactions to terrorism and climate change. Columbia Law Rev. 107, 503–557.
Suranovic, S. (2013). Fossil fuel addiction and the implications for climate change policy. Glob. Environ. Chang. 23, 598–608. doi: 10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2013.02.006
Sweeney, K. P. (2012). “We will never speak of it: evidence of Hitler’s direct responsibility for the premeditation and implementation of the Nazi final solution” in Constructing the Past, vol. 13, 7.
Thomas, C. D., Cameron, A., Green, R. E., Bakkenes, M., Beaumont, L. J., Collingham, Y. C., et al. (2004). Extinction risk from climate change. Nature 427, 145–148. doi: 10.1038/nature02121
Tokarska, K. B., Gillett, N. P., Weaver, A. J., Arora, V. K., and Eby, M. (2016). The climate response to five trillion tonnes of carbon. Nat. Clim. Chang. 6, 851–855. doi: 10.1038/nclimate3036
Tversky, A., and Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: a heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cogn. Psychol. 5, 207–232. doi: 10.1016/0010-0285(73)90033-9
UN Environment (2019). Global environment outlook – GEO-6: Summary for policymakers. Cambridge, GB: Cambridge University Press.
United Nations (2002). ‘Anyone dying from hunger was dying from murder’, special rapporteur tells third committee, as discussion on human rights continues. Available at: un.org (Accessed February 16, 2018).
United Nations (2017a). Sustainable development goals: World population projected to reach 9.8 billion in 2050, and 11.2 billion in 2100. Available at: un.org/sustainabledevelopment/blog/2017/06 (Accessed November 19, 2018).
United Nations (2017b). World population prospects 2017. Available at: population.un.org/wpp (Accessed November 19, 2018).
United Nations (2017c). Global land outlook. 1st Edn. Bonn: Secretariat of the United Nations Convention to Combat Desertification. Available at: www.unccd.int (Accessed November 20, 2018).
Van der Linden, S. (2015). The social-psychological determinants of climate change risk perceptions: towards a comprehensive model. J. Environ. Psychol. 41, 112–124. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2014.11.012
Van Vuuren, D. P., Edmonds, J., Kainuma, M., Riahi, K., Thomson, A., Hibbard, K., et al. (2011). The representative concentration pathways: an overview. Clim. Chang. 109:5. doi: 10.1007/s10584-011-0148-z
Viscusi, W. K. (1990). Do smokers underestimate risks? J. Polit. Econ. 98, 1253–1269. doi: 10.1086/261733
Voigt, C., Marushchak, M. E., Lamprecht, R. E., Jackowicz-Korczyński, M., Lindgren, A., Mastepanov, M., et al. (2017). Increased nitrous oxide emissions from Arctic peatlands after permafrost thaw. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 114, 6238–6243. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1702902114
Walker, J. C. G. (1985). Carbon dioxide on the early earth. Orig. Life 16, 117–127. doi: 10.1007/BF01809466
Watts, N., Amann, M., Arnell, N., Ayeb-Karlsson, S., Belesova, K., Berry, H., et al. (2018). The 2018 report of the lancet countdown on health and climate change: shaping the health of nations for centuries to come (executive summary). Lancet 392, 2479–2514. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(18)32594-7
Weber, E. U. (2006). Experience-based and description-based perceptions of long-term risk: why global warming does not scare us (yet). Clim. Chang. 77, 103–120. doi: 10.1007/s10584-006-9060-3
Wilkerson, J., Dobosy, R., Sayres, D. S., Healy, C., Dumas, E., Baker, B., et al. (2019). Permafrost nitrous oxide emissions observed on a landscape scale using the airborne eddy-covariance method. Atmos. Chem. Phys. 19, 4257–4268. doi: 10.5194/acp-19-4257-2019
World Health Organisation (2009). Global health risks: Mortality and burden of disease attributable to selected major risks. Geneva, Switzerland: WHO Press.
World Health Organisation (2011). Gender, climate change and health. Available at: who.int (Accessed February 20, 2019).
World Health Organisation (2017). Climate change and health. Available at: http://www.who.int/mediacentre/factsheets/fs266/en/ (Accessed February 17, 2018).
World Health Organisation (2018). Air pollution. Available at: www.who.int/airpollution/en/ (Accessed November 19, 2018).
Wu, X., Lu, Y., Zhou, S., Chen, L., and Xu, B. (2016). Impact of climate change on human infectious diseases: empirical evidence and human adaptation. Environ. Int. 86, 14–23. doi: 10.1016/j.envint.2015.09.007
Yablokov, A. V., Nesterenko, V. B., Nesterenko, A. V., and Sherman-Nevinger, J. D. (Eds.) (2010). Chernobyl: Consequences of the catastrophe for people and the environment. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons.
Yudkowsky, E. (2008). “Cognitive biases potentially affecting judgment of global risks” in Global catastrophic risks. eds. N. Bostrom and M. M. Ćirković (New York: Oxford University Press), 91–119.
Keywords: anthropogenic climate change, carbon dioxide, mortality, ethics, order-of-magnitude
Citation: Parncutt R (2019) The Human Cost of Anthropogenic Global Warming: Semi-Quantitative Prediction and the 1,000-Tonne Rule. Front. Psychol. 10:2323. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02323
Edited by:
Eric Brymer, Australian College of Applied Psychology, AustraliaReviewed by:
José Gutiérrez-Pérez, University of Granada, SpainRobert Martin Rees, Scotland’s Rural College, United Kingdom
Copyright © 2019 Parncutt. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Richard Parncutt, parncutt@uni-graz.at