Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 28 November 2017
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology
This article is part of the Research Topic Basic Emotions: Still Necessary After All These Years? View all 16 articles

Commentary: Constructing nonhuman animal emotion

  • 1Center for Neurocognition, Epistemology and Theoretical Syntax, Istituto Universitario di Studi Superiori di Pavia (IUSS), Pavia, Italy
  • 2Vita-Salute San Raffaele University, Milan, Italy

A commentary on
Constructing nonhuman animal emotion

by Bliss-Moreau, E. (2017). Curr. Opin. Psychol. 17, 184–188. doi: 10.1016/j.copsyc.2017.07.011

In a recent opinion paper, Bliss-Moreau argues for a new framework for studying non-human animal emotions. Contrary to Classical Views of Emotion (CVE) such as Basic Emotion theories, she claims that “emotions are not modules or hardwired circuits, but rather emerge from a combination of ingredients” (Bliss-Moreau, 2017, p. 185), as predicted by Theories of Constructed Emotions (TCE). Such an endeavor is interesting and praiseworthy, as it promises to overcome the anthropomorphic vice to impose human emotion categories on the whole animal kingdom. Inasmuch as it makes room for the construction of genuinely non-human emotions, TCE allegedly enables us to “understand animal minds for their own sake” (Barrett, 2017, p. 276). However, I suspect that this enterprise rests on shaky foundations.

TCE proponents (most notably Barrett, 2006) contend the central assumption of the CVE, i.e., that emotion categories such as “fear” and “anger” each denote a biologically inherited mechanism which is shared by all humankind, and arguably by several mammals. Behavioral and neuroanatomical homologies in mammals such as those described by Panksepp (e.g., Panksepp, 2007) constitute prima facie counterevidence to their view. Barrett et al. (2007) concede that these count as similarities in behaviors (and in behavioral circuits). Nonetheless, they claim that inferring an emotion from a behavior would be a mistake, which Barrett (2017, p. 272) dubs the mental inference fallacy.

One thing to keep in mind here is that different scholars seem to have different explanatory targets when they speak of emotion and folk emotion terms (e.g., “fear”). While some think of them as functional states mainly defined by their behavioral outcomes (in behavioristic-flavored third-person perspective; e.g., Panksepp, 2007; Adolphs, 2017), others save these folk terms to indicate phenomenological states (assessable through a first-person perspective; e.g., LeDoux, 2012; Barrett, 2017). Inasmuch TCE advocates adhere to this second usage of emotion terms (which is likely also closer to their vernacular meaning), they have good reasons for casting doubts upon mental inferences from behaviors to emotions, since according to their jargon that entails inferring first-person states from third-person observation.

TCE's critique against CVE sounds quite convincing (though not conclusive; see Scarantino, 2015; Celeghin et al., 2017). Unfortunately, I find their counterproposal far less convincing. Indeed, at the present stage the model they propose might be equally if not more flawed than CVE's.

Varieties of TCE differ in what ingredients are posited for emotional recipes, and in how important they are, e.g., semantic knowledge, past experiences, social roles, and norms. However, “at the core of [every] TCE is “affect”—a global state characterized by valence and arousal that forms the basis of emotions” (Bliss-Moreau, 2017, p. 185). Whilst not sufficient, affect is a necessary ingredient for emotion.

Both Bliss-Moreau and her mentor Barrett take for granted that non-human animals experience affect. They also seem committed to the view that affect is best described by some degree of arousal and valence (Barrett and Bliss-Moreau, 2009). Having asked whether animals experience affect, Barrett answers that “we can give a pretty confident yes, based on some biological and behavioral clues” (Barrett, 2017, p. 268). However, I am afraid that the available clues suggest otherwise.

Several neuroimaging studies in human sought to map either discrete emotion categories or affective properties (valence, arousal) onto some neural basis. Meta-anlyses reveal that the selectivity of valence/arousal is as scarce as that of the discrete emotion categories (Wager et al., 2015), and perhaps even worse (Kragel and LaBar, 2015). But then, if valence and arousal are not even firmly grounded in human neurobiology, why should they be a common properties of the whole animal kingdom?

Behavioral evidence is likewise controversial. According to Bliss-Moreau (2017, 185), “affect is likely present in most non-plant organisms, although in those lacking nervous systems or with simple nervous systems […] it may appear in rudimentary form. For example, bacteria move toward positive things (e.g., food) and away from negative ones (e.g., acid), indicating that they can use signals about affective value to guide behavior.” Due to the brevity of her article, she does not elaborate further. Instead, she refers to (LeDoux, 2012) for a discussion of this point. However, LeDoux's paper hardly supports such a claim. Tackling the conceptual confusion surrounding the first-person versus third–person meanings of “emotion” and emotion terms, LeDoux propose to save them for the first-person states, and dubs the homological structures that Panksepp had in mind (and that are responsible for homolog behaviors) “survival circuits.” He claims that we can and should seek for homology in survival circuits (starting with bacteria), and that we should refrain from assigning phenomenal states to non-human organisms: “survival circuits have their ultimate origins in primordial mechanisms that were present in early life forms. This is suggested by the fact that extant single-cell organisms, such as bacteria, have the capacity to retract from harmful chemicals and to accept chemicals that have nutritional value” (LeDoux, 2012, p. 655). Thus, based on behavioral similarities, what he hypothesizes we might share with bacteria and other living beings (especially mammals) is some kind of survival circuits, not a first-person affective state characterized by valence and arousal.

What is at stake here is not just an infelicitous reference. Indeed, valence and arousal are meant to describe felt experience in human, and their validation in human heavily relies on first-person data, e.g., verbal judgments and self-reports (Russell, 1980). But I can see no way to gather first-person data from non-human animals: all we have left are thus third-person data. But then, projecting our human first-person affective structure to non-human animals based on third-person data seems no less a mental inference fallacy then projecting the first-person states correlated with our discrete categories. And given that arousal/valence are admittedly only “descriptive features of core affect that bear no resemblance to or inform about how affect is caused” (Barrett and Bliss-Moreau, 2009, p. 188), discrete categories seem at least suited for grasping causal processes underlying behavioral homologies (Panksepp, 2007; LeDoux, 2012). In the light of this, the bargain proposed by TCE on non-human animal emotion hardly seems a good deal.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

The authors thanks Joe Dewhurst for his helpful comments and proofreading.

References

Adolphs, R. (2017). How should neuroscience study emotions? by distinguishing emotion states, concepts, and experiences. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 12, 24–31. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsw153

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F. (2006). Are emotions natural kinds? Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 1, 28–58. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00003.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F. (2017). How Emotions Are Made: The Secret Life of the Brain. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

Barrett, L. F., and Bliss-Moreau, E. (2009). Affect as a psychological primitive. Adv. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 41, 167–218. doi: 10.1016/S0065-2601(08)00404-8

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barrett, L. F., Lindquist, K. A., Bliss-Moreau, E., Duncan, S., Gendron, M., Mize, J., et al. (2007). Of mice and men: Natural kinds of emotions in the mammalian brain? A response to Panksepp and Izard. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 2, 297–312. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2007.00046.x

CrossRef Full Text

Bliss-Moreau, E. (2017). Constructing nonhuman animal emotion. Curr. Opin. Psychol. 17, 184–188. doi: 10.1016/j.copsyc.2017.07.011

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Celeghin, A., Diano, M., Bagnis, A., Viola, M., and Tamietto, M. (2017). Basic emotions in human neuroscience: neuroimaging and beyond. Front. Psychol. 8:1432. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01432

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kragel, P. A., and LaBar, K. S. (2015). Multivariate neural biomarkers of emotional states are categorically distinct. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 10, 1437–1448. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsv032

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

LeDoux, J. (2012). Rethinking the emotional brain. Neuron 73, 653–676. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2012.02.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Panksepp, J. (2007). Neurologizing the psychology of affects: How appraisal-based constructivism and basic emotion theory can coexist. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 2, 281–296. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2007.00045.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Russell, J. A. (1980). Evidence of Convergent Validity on the Dimensions of Affect. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 36, 1152–1168. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.36.10.1152

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Scarantino, A. (2015). “Basic emotions, psychological construction and the problem of variability,” in The Psychological Construction of Emotion, eds J. Russell and L. F. Barrett (New York, NY: Guilford Press), 334–376.

Wager, T. D., Kang, J., Johnson, T. D., Nichols, T. E., Satpute, A. B., and Barrett, L. F. (2015). A Bayesian model of category-specific emotional brain responses. PLoS Comput. Biol. 11:e1004066. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1004066

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: emotions, basic emotions, constructed emotions, animal emotions, affect, core affect

Citation: Viola M (2017) Commentary: Constructing nonhuman animal emotion. Front. Psychol. 8:2070. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.02070

Received: 30 October 2017; Accepted: 14 November 2017;
Published: 28 November 2017.

Edited by:

Fausto Caruana, Università degli Studi di Parma, Italy

Reviewed by:

Rebekka Hufendiek, University of Basel, Switzerland

Copyright © 2017 Viola. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Marco Viola, bWFyY28udmlvbGFAaXVzc3BhdmlhLml0

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.