Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Lang. Sci., 12 June 2024
Sec. Psycholinguistics

Motivating a fine-grained syntax of Arabic prepositional phrases

  • 1The ACVL Project, The Linguistic Society of Morocco, Mohammed V University, Rabat, Morocco
  • 2Department of Modern Languages and Literatures, King Abdulaziz University, Jeddah, Saudi Arabia

The paper provides a novel motivation in favor of a complex and fine-grained syntax of spatial PPs in Arabic. It neatly fills a gap between the complex semantics of spatial expressions and their morphosyntax, which remains unexplained using wide spread cognitive approaches. We propose a fine-grained architecture of root nodes, categories, and features in the basic representations of Path/Place expressions, inspired by cartographic analyses of PPs, but based on a pP dual-projection model, separating the root/lexical part from the functional/categorial part, as in Distributed Morphology (=DM). In so doing, the paper challenges traditional analyses of PPs as projecting a uniform Path over Place structure (with no bifurcating domain separation). It also provides essential ingredients allowing the decomposition of Place and Path words or expressions, including COINCIDENCE, CONTAIN, CONTACT, etc., or syntactic projections such AxPs, DeixPs, DegPs, ScaleP, GoalPs, etc., which play important syntactico-semantic roles in the grammar. Our analysis successfully accounts for complexity of prepositions or spatial expressions, their morphosyntactic alternations, variation, and polysemy.

1 Basic issues

Prepositions have a rich semantic content and can operate in various domains, including space, time, degree, or force dynamics. Their semantics have been widely studied in the literature (Jackendoff, 1983; Herskovits, 1986; Kracht, 2002; Gärdenfors, 2015, among others). Crucially, some of these properties have been shown to be not only semantic (or ontological), but also of syntactic impact on grammaticality and the syntactic structure of PPs in numerous detailed studies (Jackendoff, 1983; Wunderlich, 1991; Zwarts, 1997, 2005; Koopman, 2000; Zwarts and Winter, 2000; Kracht, 2002; Gehrke, 2008; den Dikken, 2003, 2010; Svenonius, 2010). But more syntactico-semantic features remain to be explored. Our contribution aims as refining the granularity of the PP semantic and syntactic structure in spirit of the Cartography approach (typically Cinque, 2010; Svenonius, 2010, 2012; Procházka, 2011), although relying on a Distributed Morphology design (Halle and Marantz, 1993; Wood and Marantz, 2017). We describe some core fragments of the grammar of Arabic PPs along the lines sketched, in contrast to dominant cognitive approaches of Arabic PPs, in which syntax plays only a minor role in structuring prepositional meanings (Lentzner, 1977; Esseesy, 2010; Jan, 2018).

1.1 Places and paths

As in Talmy (1975, 2000), prepositions normally denote a relation between two arguments, Figure and Ground, which express the external and internal arguments, the object located and the reference land mark. Jackendoff (1983) decomposes PPs into his “ontological categories” PLACE or PATH, and a consensus has developed since then on the relevance of two main functional/syntactic categories: Place and Path, as illustrated in the examples in (1).

(1) a. The elephants remained in the boat. (Svenonius, 2006, p. 127)

b. The boat is drifted to Narvik.

In (1a), the PP in the boat is a PlaceP, while the PP in (1b) to Narvik is a PathP. Prepositions that are associated with stative locational meanings project are Place heads while prepositions associated with directional meanings projects are Path heads. This classification is not only semantic but also reflected in syntax. For example, locative PPs can co-occur with stative verbs like be, stay, remain (Gehrke, 2008, p. 87), which select them, but not with directional PPs, as the contrast in (2) shows:

(2) a. The     /remained  /on         /under/ behind the table.   
     box      in
     stayed

b. *The     /remained  /into/  from   /out  /down/ through
  box      to                                       of                   the
  stayed                                                                  table.

In German, locative prepositions govern the dative case ([+OBL]), whereas directional prepositions mostly govern the accusative case ([–OBL]), as in (3) (Bierwisch, 1996, p. 32):

(3) a. Er schwamm unter dem Steg

         He swam under the bridge.      locative

b. Er schwamm unter den Steg

         He swam under the bridge.      directional

In Dutch, locative adpositions are prepositional; whereas directional ones are post-positional (den Dikken, 2010, p. 6):

(4) a. Jan liep/rende in het bos

         Jan walked/ran in the woods      locative

b. Jan liep/rende het bos in

         Jan walked/ran the woods in      directional

Structurally, PathP can be seen as more complex than PlaceP, given the fact that PathP cartographically embeds PlaceP, as represented in (4) (Svenonius, 2012, p. 5):

(5) yes

1.2 The figure and the ground as p/P arguments

These distinct morphosyntactic properties are best thought as reflecting differences in syntactic structure. In fine-grained syntax, the question arises as to whether the figure F and the ground G are both included in a basic argument configuration type as bi-argumental, as argued for by Hale and Keyser (2002), the P root being dyadic, as in their argument structure type in (6a); [=their structure (17), p. 7], or their schematic argument structure in (6b):

(6) yes

Alternatively, G is introduced as a complement of (the big) P (or our root P), and F is indeed the external argument of (small) p, a functional head exactly parallel to v, or more commonly voice, in its ability to license an external argument, as in Wood and Marantz (2017). Ideally, various functional heads can be reduced to one single argument introducer, which is referred to as i*, in distinct syntactic contexts. Differences between different uses of i* stem from rules that are sensitive to the syntactic context in which it occurs. The functional head i* encompasses both p, v, or voice, or other flavors of f-categories. So, in terms of argument-introducing heads, we have two essential traditional distinct heads in (7):

(7) a.  Little p (figures): Bare i* merges with PP.

b. Voice (agents): Bare i* merges with vP.

Interpretive differences between the two heads are now understood as contextually determined interpretation rules, as illustrated in (8):

(8) a. [[i*]]↔λxλs. FIGURE(x,s) / ___(locative PP)

b. [[i*]]↔λxλe. AGENT(x,e) / ___(agentive vP)

As for the root of P (or bigP), it is a root-adjoined i* with selectional feature checked by complement. The authors pointed out that they follow basically Svenonius in identifying internal argument with G, and external argument with F of prepositions (pp. 258–261).

While we basically adhere to this line of reasoning concerning the general design of the theory, we will leave the room open for the argument structure in (6) as potential structure of big P in some cases, or of the RootP of the PP, given potential evidence for the existence of both basic intransitive and transitive verb roots that can be causativized, and that the structure of the basic transitive cannot be readily derived from that of the intransitive. Parallel preposition configurations can be potentially found conflated in more complex causative structures.1

1.3 Morphosyntactic complexity

Beside cartographic distribution of Paths and Places, morphological complexity is another property that has been used in English to determine syntactic structure. Prepositions such as in, on, at are simple prepositions, but in front of, under, next to are complex (see Svenonius, 2006, 2010; Cinque, 2010, among others). Moreover, some complex propositions have been argued to contain two more heads: Ax(ial)Part and Case (K), as in Svenonius (2006, 2010):

(9) yes

(Svenonius, 2010, p. 131, adapted)

The syntactic structure of Place in (9) goes in line with its semantics. According to Svenonius (2012), in back of and behind both must have the same syntax (i.e., with three heads), although in back of is prosodically three words. Thus, the category labels are often associated with both syntax and semantics. In complex prepositions, Svenonius (2012) proposes that p is higher than AxPart, which introduces the external argument (or Figure). That is to say, the prepositional locative word or structure is decomposed into p, AxPart, and K in complex constructions:

(10) yes

(Svenonius, 2012, p. 10)

A further elaboration of morphosyntactic complexity which is reflected in the structure of PlaceP is the sensitivity to Measure Phrases (MeasP). Only some Place expressions (but not others) are measurable, allowing phrases such as ten meters, twenty feet, a foot etc to occur, as illustrated in (8) and (9) (Svenonius, 2012, p. 16). Svenonius calls this feature Proj(ective), adopting Herskovits (1986) original term of the semantic feature Projective:

(11) a. There's a tree twenty feet in front of the house.

b. There's a wind vane a foot above the house

(12) a. There's a tree (*five feet) beside the house.

b. There's a tree (*a foot) on top of the house.

The (un-)grammaticality is reflected in the structure. Svenonius (2012) argues that projective expressions are endowed with a Proj(ective) feature. Structurally, Proj expressions have an additional projection ProjP that is not available in non-projective expressions. Compare the cartography (10)2 below to the non-Proj structure in (9) above (but see Section 3 below for more discussion):

(13) yes

(Svenonius, 2012, p. 16)

Beside Proj, there are other semantic features embodied in the locative expression such as Size, Stability, Outline, Contact, and Motion that remain unexplored. These features are widely discussed in Landau and Jackendoff (1993), Kracht (2008), Herskovits (1986), Gärdenfors (2015), Fassi Fehri (2021), among others, but the question is to what extent these features are reflected in the syntactic structure. We return to the issue in Section 3 for more discussion and refinements.

1.4 Hierarchical paths

Like locative prepositions or places, directional expressions or paths have semantic features that turn out to be also syntactic, suggesting further granularity or finer cartography. Building on work developed by Jackendoff (1983), Piñón (1993), Kracht (2002) and Zwarts (2008), among others, Procházka (2011) identifies three semantico-syntactic types of paths: Goal, Source and Route, structured and ordered cartographically. Moreover, using three aspectual or semantic features (±TRANSITION, ±ORIENTATION, and ±DELIMITATION), these types are further subdivided in eight subtypes, to account for distinctions found in the following constructions, (14) to (16), respectively:

(14) a. They cast a wistful glance to the shore. (Svenonius, 2010, p. 127)

b. saafar-tu      ʔilaa                d-doḥat-i

            traveled-I    to                     Doha-GEN

            “I traveled to Doha.”

(15) a. The boat drifted farther from the beach. (Svenonius, 2010, p. 127)

b. ʔamšii        min              l-bayt-i

           walk-I         from            the-house-
                                              GEN

              “I walk to the house.”

(16) a. A band is playing through the trees. (Svenonius, 2010, p. 149)

b. y-               ṭ-ṭaaʔir-      ḥawl-a     š-šajarat-

           aḥuum-u   u                                  i

           3-roam-    the-bird-    around-  the-tree-

            IND            NOM            ACC          GEN

           “The bird is roaming around the tree.”

Syntactically then, Path is decomposed into three syntactic heads: Source, Goal, and Route (or symmetric Path) (Procházka, 1993, 2011; Nam, 1995). In languages with rich spatial case system such as Daghestanian languages, the three heads manifest a fixed hierarchy: Route>Source>Goal as illustrated in (17): 3

(17) yes

1.5 Research questions and significance of the study

The paper aims at answering two essential research questions:

(a) How granular are the morphosyntactic features in Arabic locational and directional expressions, to reach a reasonable degree of descriptive adequacy?

(b) How are these features syntactically represented, given the root/category divide (a basic tenet of DM), and the also potential hierarchical cartography?

Our contribution explores in particular the internal structure of PPs in Arabic. Arabic is targeted as a relatively poorly described language regarding the topic, when compared to the abundant and meticulous studies of Germanic, Romance, or Slavic. This is not denying the existence of important contributions found in tradition grammar, including namely Ibn Hišaam (1985) and Al-Muraadii (1992), or in cognitive descriptions as conducted by Lentzner (1977), Esseesy (2010) and Jan (2018), or the generative analysis developed by Saeed (2014), Fassi Fehri (2021), or previous studies by the authors, on which we are building substantially (see also Procházka, 2011). The article investigates and motivates morphosyntactic features or categories in both locational and directional expressions along their semantic interpretations from both theoretical and cross-linguistic perspectives, and how these features and categories are hierarchically ordered, along the root/category divide in a Distributed Morphology (=DM) design of grammar.

1.6 Our basic analysis

In analyzing the Arabic prepositional or axial (Axpart) noun expressions, we adopt a DM model which takes into account the dual life of spatial expressions, as lexical roots (normally represented by big P), and as functional categories [normally represented by small p; (see e.g., Rooryck, 1996; Marantz, 1997; Deacon, 2011; Wood and Marantz, 2017)]. In DM, lexemes are not formed in the lexicon, before they enter the syntactic derivation. Rather, the necessary aspects of the lexicon are positioned within sentential derivation. The concept of lexeme is replaced by two forms: Lexical Item (LI) and Vocabulary Item (VI). LIs are borne as uncategorial roots (or abstract language specific morphemes), which enter the derivation as simple or complex root nodes, and are categorized through various functional category nodes, which form the terminal nodes in syntax, or constitute interpretable phases. Terminal nodes are provided after the syntactic derivation with a specific phonological form of the word, a VI (see Chomsky, 1995, 2001; Harley and Noyer, 1999; Embick and Noyer, 2005; Marantz, 2013; and Harley, 2014, among many others). As for the fine structure of PPs, our work draws heavily from significant cartographic studies on the topic, including notably Koopman (2000), Svenonius (2010, 2012), Cinque (2010), den Dikken (2010), and Pancheva (2011), among others.

As in Wood and Marantz (2017) for English, and Fassi Fehri (2021) and Fassi Fehri and Alrawi (2023) for Arabic, the structure of PPs is split between the root node(s) and the syntactic f-node(s). In parallel to the vP shell (Larson, 1988, 2014), the pP shell is argued to be a dual projection: a Root √ (the traditional big P) and a categorizing (case assignor or small) p:

(18) yes

This structure allows us to elegantly account, among other things, for the categorial flexibility of spatial expressions. They can surface as a preposition, a noun, an adjective, or as a (locative) verb phrase, as illustrated in (19):

(19) a. al-kitaab-u      ʕalaa      ṭ-ṭaawilat-i

           the-book-       on          the-table-GEN

          NOM

           “The book is on the table.”

b. ʔazal-tu        n-naḥlat-a      min      ʕalaa      dahr-i-ka

            removed-I    the-bee-        from    on           back-GEN-

                                  ACC                                             your

            “I took out the bee from above your back.”

c. nazala              l-maaɁ-u       min      Ɂaʕlaa

            came down    the-water-   from    above.GEN

                                     NOM

            “The water went down from above.”

d. l-jabal-u      Ɂaʕlaa      min      xams-      mitr-in

                                                              imiɁat-i

            the-             higher      than     five         meters-GEN

            mountain-                              hundred-

            nom                                          GEN

            “The mountain more than five hundred

            meters height.”

            (lit. “The mountain is higher than five

            hundred meters.”)

e. ʕala-t             l-miyaah-u      l-jabal-

                                                           a

            went.high-    the-water-     the-

            F                      NOM               mountain-

                                                           ACC

            “The water went up the mountain.”            (after Fassi Fehri and Alrawi, 2023, p. 9)

Thus, the root of ʕalaa “on,” as seen in (20), can surface as p in (20a), n in (20b) or (20), a in (20c), or v in (20d):

(20) yes

(Fassi Fehri and Alrawi, 2023, p. 9)

Moreover, the lower √Ploc or √Pdir (den Dikken, 2010) is responsible for the distinct locative or directional (or Place/Path) meanings associated with spatial expressions. The c-commanding functional p is the categorizer that assigns genitive case, parallel to v in vP that assigns accusative. Movement of √-to-p is motivated: the interpretable [loc]/[dir] feature makes the spatial expression an appropriate goal probed by p (Fassi Fehri, 2021). In our analysis, the traditional single projection PlaceP is split into two projections: √Ploc and the axial or AxPart nP (see Section 3.1). Similarly, PathP is split into two projections: the root √Pdir rode and the pP categorial node, as represented in (21):

(21) yes

A number of details and motivations can be found in Fassi Fehri and Alrawi (2023), and will not be repeated here. This contribution is an attempt to refine the basic analysis argued for there or in other works on the topic, adding further motivations and clarifications. It focuses chiefly on the granular issue, its syntactic motivation, in addition to elaborating on complexity of prepositions, their polysemy (or allosemy; Marantz, 2013), their homonymy (or allomorphy), as well as dialectal variation.

2 complex polysemies and syntactic alternations

Prepositional phrases are found in complex constructions, polysemies, and dialectal variations. In our system, these phenomena are taken care of by distinct structures, depending on constructions that may or may not be related morpho-syntactically, in association with their semantics. Cognitivists, by contrast, rely on hierarchically ordered cognitive networks that are associated with words (as in Lentzner, 1977; Esseesy, 2010; Jan, 2018). We claim that the hierarchically ordered “word approach” used is inadequate, given that it does not assume a tight correlation between syntactic (or morpho-syntactic) structure and semantics, do not make meaning depending on constructions (but on words), and hence do not make clear predictions about form meaning correlations built in the syntax of languages, or about empirically motivated lexical classes or subtypes behind dialectal variation, as we will explain below.

2.1 meanings of Place with fii and bi-

In traditional grammar, each P is polysemous, although meanings are ordered, starting with basic or primary meanings (Ibn Hišaam, 1985; Al-Muraadii, 1992, among others). Fii has a number of meanings that are instantiations of the “lexical” root P. Chiefly, among those meanings is a broad locative or temporal “circumstantiality”, or more specifically a CONTAINMENT (htiwaaɁ), as illustrated in (22):

(22) a. zayd-un        fii      d-daar-i

           Zayd-NOM     in      the-house-GEN

           “Zayd is in the house.”

b. sa-Ɂuṯri    fii            biḍʕ-i        siniina

            FUT-be      rich in    few-GEN   years.GEN

           “I will be rich in few years.”

In modern grammars, most Arabic linguists converge on the idea that fii has a broad LOCATIVE meaning, and a more specific meaning of CONTAIN(MENT) that corresponds to those of the English preposition “in,” or more extensively “at” or “on” as illustrated in (23), (24), and (25), respectively (Lentzner, 1977; Esseesy, 2010; Jan, 2018; Fassi Fehri, 2021):

(23) l-jamaaʕat-u         fii      l-masjid-i

       The-group-NOM    in      the-mosque-GEN

       “The group is in the mosque.”

(24) y-atajawwalu      fii      š-šaariʕ-i

       3-walk                 in      the-avenue-GEN

       “He walks in theavenue.”

(25) l-qimmat-u                 fii      y-ulyuuz-a

       the-summit-NOM        in      July-GEN

       “The summit is in July”

The locative meaning of fii can be partial CONTAIN (rather than total), in which the Ground partially contains the Figure, as in (26).

(26) a. l-ʕuṣfuur-u        fii      š-šajarat-i

        the-bird-NOM        in      the-tree-GEN

       “The bird is in the tree.”

b. l-wardat-u           fii      l-mazhariyyat-i

       the-flower-NOM      in      the-vase-GEN

       “The flower is in the vase.”

The bird in (55a) is not contained by the tree but it is located in one branch of the tree, and only part of its body is attached to the branch. Similarly, in (55b), only part of the flower is located inside the vase (Esseesy, 2010).

Moreover, localization can be broad or abstract, where no physical or concrete containment is infered, as in (27):

(27) ṭanjat-u                fii      šamaal-i          r-ribaaṭ-i

       Tangier-NOM        in      north-GEN      Rabat-GEN

       “Tangier is to the north of Rabat.”

In (27), there is no concrete physical containment relation between Tangier and Rabat, but only a broad more abstract location, according to which the Figure F is seen as included in the INTERIOR of the Ground G.

In the time domain, fii situates F in a certain G moment in time and means specifically CENTRAL COINCIDENCE in Tense and Aspect. It corresponds to English “at” or “in”, which means that F and G either coincide (i.e., overlap in the positioning in time), as in (28a), or that G is a container inside of which F is temporally located, as in (28b).

(28) a. mawʕid-u-na                   fii      l-xaamisat-i

            appointment-NOM-        in      the-five-GEN

            our

            “Our appointment is at 5 o'clock.”

b. naḥnu      fii      l-masaaɁ-i

            we           in      the-evening-GEN

            “We are in the evening.”

What is of interest, in particular, is to see whether these two primary meanings of fii- can be confused with those of other close prepositions, typically bi-. As we will see, the essential meanings of the two prepositions can be contrasted, and made distinct, despite the fact that they can overlap, or be confused and made interchangeable.4

The preposition bi- “at, with” is the closest preposition to fii “in.” But according to traditional grammars, its primary meaning is CONTACTilsaaq, literally “gluing”, or “sticking”), compared to fii, which is primarily dedicated to CONTAINMENT or INCLUSION. The locational contact meaning is clearly found in the following constructions:

(29) ṣ-ṣuur-at-u                    laṣiiq-at-un      bi-l-ḥaaɁiṭ-i

        the-photograph-F-      glued-F-           at-the-wall-

        NOM                                NOM                 GEN'

       “The photograph is glued to the wall.”

(30) Ɂanaa      mutaʕalliq-un        bi-ka

        I                attached-NOM      at-you

        “I am attached to you.”

In verb complexes, favored by traditional grammar, to vehicle CONTACT, prototypical constructions include the following instances, where a contact is established between me and the man's hand in (31a), or me and the man in (31b):

(31) a. Ɂaxađ-tu      bi-yad-i               r-rajul-i

            took-I         at-hand-GEN        the-man-GEN

            “I took the man's hand.”

b. ltaqayt-tu      bi-r-rajul-i

            met-I             at-the-man-GEN

            “I met the man.”

In all these contexts, fii cannot be used instead of bi- in the standard variety of Arabic.5

What is problematic, in traditional descriptions, however, is that they make no room for the general locational meaning that bi- can express, without inducing any inclusion, but still entailing some PROXIMITY or VICINITY meaning, or roundabout (Jan, 2018) as in the following examples:

(32) Ɂanaa      bi-baab-i             manzil-i-ka

        I               at-door-GEN       house-GEN-

                                                     your

        “I am by your house door.”

Clearly, the preposition in these examples locates F in some proximity or roundabouts of G, but does not induce any containment or inclusion. The introduction of fii is clearly not an option here. Moreover, the translation of bi- should be “at” rather than “in,” although bi- does not have meanings of “at;” in fact, most of the meanings of the English locative “at,” discussed by Brenda (2015), are rather expressed by fii. This difference clarifies the distinctive interpretation of the PP in the classical (33a), compared to (33b):

(33) a. Ɂinnaka      bi-l-waadii      l-muqaddas-i,          ṭawaa

            you            at-the-            the-sacred-GEN       Tawa

                               valley.GEN

            “You are at the sacred valley, Tawa” (Quran, 16).

b. Ɂanaa    fii      l-waadii

            I            in      the-valley.GEN

            “I am in the valley.”

It is possible that both bi- and fii express COINCIDENCE, and that they differ in that fii can be viewed as expressing central COINCIDENCE, whereas bi- expresses non-central COINCIDENCE (see Lentzner, 1977, where fii expresses COINCIDE INTERIOR, compared to bi-, which is not specified for INTERIOR). We propose that CONTACT or non-central COINCIDE(NCE) are the specific meanings of the spatial bi- “at.”

Hale (1986) claims that two essential distinct local cases in Walbiri can be defined along the COINCIDE notion, characterizing the role of F (or theme) with respect to G (or Place), or spatial–temporal relations more generally. Demirdache and Uribe-Etxebarria (2014) extend the notion to include both space and temporality, as in (62):

(34) a. [+ central coincidence]: F within G

            Location, trajectory, or linear arrangement of F

            centrally coincides with G.

b. [- central coincidence]: F not within G “terminal,”

            “initial,” etc. (bi-)

            Location, trajectory, or linear arrangement of F

            does not centrally coincide with G.

In (34a), the location of the interlocutor coincides with that of the valley, without inducing any containment or inclusion, contrary to (34b).

Fii “in,” on the other hand, locates F in a position interior and within the boundaries of G, a CONTAINMENT, or a CC relation. We assume that what differentiates bi- “at” from fii “in” is the meaning associated with the root, to fit in a suitable construction. Thus, the root of bi- “at” is distinct from that of fii “in,” as schematized in (35); ± CC abbreviating ±: CENTRAL COINCIDE

(35) yes

Clearly, bi- does not normally replace fii in Classical or Modern Standard Arabic, although there appear some cases of interchangeability in modern data. In most cases, this is due to dialectal interferences in the diglossic situation of Arabic. Clearly also, there is a quite systematic variation in the dialectal uses, depending on geographical locations, which can be distinguished depending on the two prepositions uses, instantiating vocabulary variation, as we explain in the next subsection.

2.2 Lexical variation as distinct vocabulary

Lexical variation can elegantly be associated with a distributed model in the standard variety or between other varieties. For example, in Mashriqi dialects, bi- “at” replaces fii in denoting CONTAIN (in addition to CC), as in (36a,b) below from Levantine Arabic:

(36) a. Ɂana      bi-l-bet              b. Ɂana      bi-l-bab

            I            in-the-                    I            at-the-door

                         house

            “I am in the house.”           “I am at the house.”

In Maghribi dialects, on the other hand, fii is often generalized, instead of bi (both are reduced to f- and b-), as in Moroccan Arabic (37):

(37) a. Ɂana      f-d-dar                  b. Ɂana      f-l-bab

            I            in-the-                        I            at-the-door

                         house

            “I am in the house.”              “I am at the house.”

For containment in time, by contrast, bi- in Mashriqi dialects replaces fii-:

(38)  n-tlaaqa       bi-l-masaa/bi-l-lail

        we-meet      in-the-evening

        “We meet in the evening/at night.”

                                                                            (Fassi Fehri, 2021, p. 160)

In Maghribi dialects, on the other hand, f- is used instead of b-, as in Moroccan Arabic (37):

(39)  n-tlaaqaw      f-l-ʕašiia/f-l-lail

        we-meet       in-the-evening

        “We meet in the evening/at night.”

With perception or contact verbs, Maghribi dialects more often use b-, as in the (b) examples, while Mashriqi dialects use f-, as in the (a) examples:

(40) a. ḥasse-t      fiik           b. ḥssee-t      bi-k

            felt.I            in-you        felt.I         at-you

            “I felt you”

(41) a. taṣal-t                 fi-k                 b. taṣal-t               bi-k

            contacted-I       in-you                contacted-I      at-you

            “I contacted you.”

(42) a. raḥḥab             fiy-ya                b. raḥḥab             biy-ya

            welcomed      in-me                    welcomed      at-me

            “He welcomed me.”

To express MANNER, b- is mostly used in all dialects, rather than f-:

(43) a. ka-n-tkellem                  b-š-šweyya          (Maghribi)

            PROG-I-talk                    with-slow

            “I talk slowly.”

b. be-n-t-kallam                 b-šwayaš           (Machriqi)

            PROG-we-talk                 with-slow

            “We talk slowly.”

2.3 Morpho-syntactic alternations

Morpho-syntactic alternations play a major role in revealing the “lexical” or root syntax of prepositions, as well as their functional projections in category syntax. Among these alternations are places/paths, transitives/intransitives, causatives, and the various prepositional uses.

2.3.1 Place/path and CC/TC alternations

The preposition fii alternates between being a Place head in space, as in (44a), or state as in (44b), or a Path head when it collocates with a directed motion event such as daxal “enter,” indicating a change of state, as in (45):

(44) a. r-rajul-u                 fii      l-manzil-i

            the-man-NOM       in      the-house-GEN

            “The man is in the house.”

b. r-rajul-u                fii      gaybubat-i-n

            the-man-NOM      in      coma-GEN-N

            “The man is in a coma.”

(45) daxala         r-rajul-u                fii      gaybubat-i-n

        entered      the-man-NOM      in      coma-GEN-N

        “The man entered into a coma.”

It is important to note that this Place/Path alternation results in change from a CC (Central Coincidence) interpretation to a TC (Terminal Coincidence) interpretation, as if the preposition has switched from the equivalent of in interpretation in English to that of into. That suggests in turn that the TC preposition is complex, made of two prepositions, one of which is unpronounced as in Hale and Keyser (2002, p. 222); [structure (39)]. This is reflected in (46)

(46) yes

The motion event selects a PathP, when fii collocates with a motion event, it denotes a directional Path, having basically the meaning of the directional Path Ɂilaa, rather than a pure locational Place. This is a case of polysemy of the preposition, involving presumably two distinct syntactic structures (a case of so-called interchangeability of prepositions). It means simply that one preposition (as a vocabulary item, VI) is associated with distinct structures, which are normally associated with two distinct prepositions with some specific senses.

2.3.2 Transitive/intransitive, causative, and alternations

Constructions with Ɂilaa “to” seem to exhibit a prepositional/accusative alternation in which Ɂilaa “to” is either overt or hidden:

(47) a. ṣaʕada      r-rajul-u       Ɂilaa      l-jabal-i

           climb        the-man-      to         the-mountain-

                             NOM                           GEN

           “The man climbed (to) the mountain.”

b. ṣaʕada        r-rajul-u               l-jabal-a

            climb          the-man-NOM      the-mountain-

                                                              GEN

            “The man climbed the mountain.”

Ɂilaa expresses a Goal–Path meaning in these constructions, available in both (47a) and (47b), which suggests the presence of a Path root P in both constructions. If so, then the difference appears to be only in the case assignor. The genitive case assignor, p, is available in (47a), but not in (47b). The absence of the structural case assigner p, leaves l-jabal-a “the mountain” in (47b) without case. It is then assigned a sort of oblique “accusative” by default. The two alternations can be represented as follows:

(48) yes

Consider now causative alternations. Prepositional/accusative alternations also occur in causative constructions in which the preposition has an overt/null alternation, as illustrated in (49):

(49) a. Ɂ-ahday-tu        kitaab-an      li-zayd-in

            CAUS.gave-I       book-ACC      to-Zayd-

                                                             GEN

            “I gave a book to Zayd.”

b. Ɂ-ahday-tu       zayd-an        kitaab-an      <dative>

            CAUS.gave-I      Zayd-ACC     book-ACC

            “I gave Zayd a book.”

In both (49a) and (49b), Zayd is the dative or the Recipient of the action. The dative interpretation is assigned by the Goal root √li-. To put it differently, the dative root √li- is assumed to be the source of the dative interpretation, and it is available for both (49a) and (49b). The two constructions then differ only in the source of case assignment. The prepositional p head assigns the genitive case in (49a). But in order for Zayd to receive (structural dative) case in (49b), it moves to a position where it is assigned accusative by v. The examples in (49a) and (49b) are represented in (50a) and (50b), respectively:

(50) yes

If (50a) is roughly the basic structure for both constructions in (49), then the dative has to move higher in (50b), adjoining to the pP, to get structural case there.

A further example of an overt/null alternation is illustrated in (51) and represented in (52):

(51) a. kasaw-tu      l-walad-a      bi-ṯ-ṯawb-i      <tool/

                                                                                 instrument>

           wore-I          the-child-      with-the-

                                 ACC                 cloth-GEN

           “I have worn the child with the cloth.”

b. Ɂ-aksay-tu        l-walad-a         ṯ-ṯawb-a

            CAUS-wear-      the-child-        the-cloth-

            I                          ACC                  ACC

           “I made the child wear the cloth.”             (Fassi Fehri, 2021, p. 183)

(52) yes

In both (52a) and (52b), ṯ-ṯawb “the cloth” is the tool or instrument used for the action of wearing. In (80a), the causative verb kasaa “made him wear” makes use of the overt preposition bi-, in expressing the Instrument role. The preposition bi- is dominated by the functional p, and it assigns the complement ṯ-ṯawb a genitive case. In (52b), the preposition is silent, and ṯ-ṯawb “the cloth” receives an accusative case via v.

2.3.3 Fii/bi- alternations and inverted roles

Prepositions can have closely related meanings that can relate the same arguments (Figure and Ground) but with different configurational relations. Consider further alternations of fii “in” and bi- “by” in (81):

(53) a. Ɂaṯṯara          l-ḥaadi?-u            fii      r-rajul-i

           affected       the-accident-      in      the-man-GEN

                                NOM

           “The accident affected the man.”

b. ta-Ɂaṯṯara        r-rajul-u              bi-l-ḥaadiṯ-i

            REFLEX-           the-man-NOM    by-the-

            affected                                       accident-GEN

            “The man got affected by the accident.”

In (53a), l-ḥaadiṯ-u “the accident” is the Figure or the Cause and r-rajul-i “the man” is the complement Ground or the entity affected, as represented in (53a). On the other hand, r-rajul-u “the man” in (53b), which is the Ground, is in the Specifier position, and the Figure l-ḥaadiṯ-i “the accident” is the complement, as represented in (53b). It is true that the selection of the preposition depends on the form of verb, but the relation between the Figure and the Ground is determined by the preposition (or, more specifically, the prepositional root).

(54) yes

These alternations suggest the presence of the lexical meaning associated with the P root, regardless of its function as a case assignor.

2.4 Further conflating prepositions in distinct classes or roles

In the verbal domain, when PPs are part of the semantico-syntactic structure of vPs, syntactic alternations are more clearly associated with semantic correlates: CONTAIN, CONTACT, COINCIDE (±central), etc.

2.4.1 CONTACT transitive/PP alternation

Consider the CONTACT transitive/PP alternation associated with bi-:

(55) a. Ɂaxađ-tu bi-yad-i-hi                    b.    Ɂaxađ-tu yad-a-hu

            took-I at-hand-GEN-his                     took-I hand-ACC-

                                                                         his

            “I took (at) his hand.”                          “I took his hand.”

In (55a), bi- “at” collocates with the verb Ɂaxađ “took”, creating a meaning of CONTACT. This meaning is preserved in the null counterpart (55b), when bi- is covert. The difference between (55a) and (55b) is basically in terms of case assignment. The object yad “hand” receives a genitive case in (83a), but an accusative case in (55b). That is to say, the meaning connected with the root is available in both (55a) and (55b), but the genitive case assigning head is available in (55a) but not in (55b). This motivates a separation between the root head (√) that expresses the CONTACT meaning and the functional head p that assigns genitive to the complement. The structures of (55a) and (55b) can be tentatively represented in (56a) and (56b), respectively, where p is either overt or covert:

(56) yes

Another syntactic alternation is related to the CONTAIN alternation associated with fii and bi-. While both fii and bi- seem to relate the same arguments, the roles assigned to the arguments change depending on which preposition is used. Fii locates a containee Figure with respect to a container Ground. But bi- entails that the container is the Figure and the containee the Ground, the position of which coincides with that of the Figure, reversing somehow the roles. The alternating contrast is illustrated by the pair of constructions in (57):

(57) a. štaʕala      š-šayb-u           fii      r-raɁs-i

            filled         the white          in      the-head-GEN

                          hair-NOM

            “The white hair filled the head.”

b. štaʕala       r-raɁs-u                 bi-š-šayb-i

            filled          the-head-NOM      with-the-white

                                                               hair-GEN

            “The head filled with white hair.”

                               (Fassi Fehri, 1986, adapted from Fassi Fehri, 2021, p. 184)

In (57a), the DP complement of fii “in” (r-raɁs-i “the head”) is a G container, whereas the complement of bi- “with” (š-šayb-i “the white hair”) is an F containee. At the same time, the subject (or external argument) is an F containee with fii, and a G container with bi-, or so it seems. These contrasts can be represented as in (86a,b), respectively:

(58) yes

A similar container/containee placement alternation is also manifest in the following pair of sentences:

(59) a. malaɁ-tu      l-jarrat-a           bi-z-zayt-i

           filled-I           the-jar-ACC      with-the-oil-GEN

           “I filled the jar with oil.”

b. malaɁ-tu     z-zayt-a     fii      l-jarrat-i

            filled-I         the-oil-      in      the-jar-GEN

                                NOM

            “I filled the jar with oil.” (lit. “I filled the oil in the jar”).

In both (59a) and (59b), l-jarrat “the jar” is a container, and z-zayt “the oil” is the containee. The difference is that bi- “with” relates the container to the containee, and fii “in” does the opposite. Both prepositions collocate with the same verb as represented in (59a) and (59b). The complement of fii, the container, receives a “locative” G theta role in (59b), whereas the complement of bi-, the containee, appears to play a sort of Means/Instrument role (for similar patterns, see Jahfa, 2011; see also below for more discussion):

(60) yes

It is reasonable to think that the meaning associated with the prepositional root is what determines the thematic roles of its arguments. √bi- carries here the meaning of MEANS that makes its complement z-zayt “the oil” a tool which the CONTAINER, l-jarrat-a “the jar,” is filled with, whereas √fii has a LOC containment meaning that makes its complement l-jarrat-i “the jar” a true container for the Figure CONTAINEE, z-zayt-a “the oil.”

The relation between the Figure and the Ground can also be analyzed in terms of (±central) COINCIDE, as explained above. It is important to note that locative fii establishes a [+CC] relation, locative bi- establishes a [–CC] relation, whereas directional fii establishes a TC relation.

2.4.2 Locative/possessive alternations

Consider the following contrasting uses of fii and bi- in the following constructions:

(61) a. fii      d-daar-i                  rajul-un

           In      the-house-GEN      man-NOM

           “There is man in the house.”

b. ??bi-d-daar-i                   rajul-un

            with-the-house-GEN      man-NOM

(62) a. b-ii              wajaʕun       (fii l-batni)

           with-me     pain-NOM    (in the-stomach-GEN)

           “I have a pain (in the stomach).”

b. ?? f-ii         wajaʕ-un       (fii l-batni)

            in-me        pain-nom     (in the-stomach-GEN)

The construction (61a) is normally qualified as “existential,” but we concur with Creissels (2022, p. 607) to describe it as “inverse locational predication,” which is basically a locative. The structure in (62a) can be described as “Possessor (be) with possessee,” or what he calls comitative possessee construction.6 Creissells argues that such a configuration is prototypical in Arabic dialects, and he observes that a true comitative-possessee construction “Possessor (be) with Possessee,” is attested in Sudan (Kordofan, Šukriyya; Manfredi, 2010), Libya (Saad, 2019), and Mauritania (Taine-Cheikh, 2008):7

(63) Kordofanian Baggara Arabic (Manfredi, 2010, p. 169)

        musa   da                   be                bitt=a      

        Moses PROX.SG.M     with            daughter=3SG

        “Moses has a daughter.”

(64) Libyan Arabic, Benghazi variety (Saad, 2019, p. 4)

        ḫūu-ya           ayyub          ḥatta     huwwa b-murattab-a

brother-1SG Ayoub           even     3SG.M with-salary-

                                                                3SG.M

        wu                  b-sayyart-a wu        b-šәggt-a

        and                with-car-      and      with-flat-3SG.M

                               3SG.M

        “My brother Ayoub too has a salary, a car, and a flat.”

(65) Hassaniya Arabic (Taine-Cheikh, 2008, p. 429)

        ānä  b-owlād-i

        1SG with-child.PL-1SG

        “I have children.” (p. 608)

If so, then the parallel contrast between the two (eventually inverse) constructions in (61a) and (62a) represent a contrast between the genuine basic spatial locative in (61a) and the presumably “derived” possessive in (62a), a distinction which collocates with the be/have variation in Germanic and Romance (as in Freeze, 1992 and Kayne, 1993). In Arabic, however, no such auxiliary contrast exists. One option would then be to distinguish the roots of the two constructions by marking them tentatively as Ploc and Pposs, a marking similar to that used by Harley (2002) for English Ploc and Phave for double object and possessive verbal constructions, respectively. The difference is that Pposs can extend to Arabic and English, whereas Phave cannot be motivated for Arabic.

Note that bi- is used here with a possessee which is a physical state, as in (62a), or a psych state, as in (66) below. By contrast, li-, and eventually ʕinda are the most used in predicate possession where the possessee is physical, as in (67) and (68), respectively:

(66) b-ii               shawq-un

       with-me      longing-NOM

       “I have longing.”

(67) l-ii           walad-ani

       have-me children-DUAL.NOM

       “I have two children.”

(68) ʕind-ii      qalam-un Ɂaxdar

        have-me pen-NOM green-NOM

        “I have a green pen.”

3 Cartographic and feature refinements

3.1 Loc and dir features of pPs

Locational expressions that denote places, regardless of whether they are syntactically nouns or prepositions, relate a Figure to its Ground. In Arabic, we take a stative verbless sentence to be the appropriate context for places. This is illustrated in (97) below, where fii “in,” or ʕalaa “on,” or jaanib-a “next to,” or ʕind-a “near” are locative elements that head places:

(69) a. Ɂanaa                 fii                 l-bayt-i

            I                         in                 the-house-GEN

           “I am in the house.” (Fassi Fehri, 2021, p. 24)

       b. l-kitaab-u             ʕalaa              ṭ-ṭaawilat-i

           the-book-NOM    on                 the-table-GEN

           “The book is on the table.”      

        c. l-qalam-u           jaanib-a         l-kitaab-i

            the-pen-NOM     nextr-ACC      the-book-GEN

            “The pen is next to the book.”      

        d. Ɂanaa                 ʕind-a         l-bayt-i

            I                          near-ACC     the-house-GEN

            “I am near the house.”

Under a cross-linguistic view, fii “in,” ʕalaa “on,” jaanib-a “next to,” or ʕind-a “near, at” project as a Place head. However, this analysis needs refinement. This is because they are semantically but not syntactically identical to the traditional (single projection) PlaceP. On the one hand, they should be endowed with the feature [+loc] (presumably at the root) that makes them distinct from directional expressions, marked as [+dir]. The latter cannot occur in simple locational contexts, neither in Arabic (70) nor in English (71):

(70) a. *Ɂanaa               Ɂilaa             l-bayt-i

            I                        to                 the-house-GEN

b. *l-kitaab-u            min             ṭ-ṭaawilat-i

            the-book-NOM    from           the-table-GEN

(71) a. *I remained to the house.

b. *The book is located from

             the table.

On the other hand, not all of them count as p heads of Places, syntactically speaking. Indeed, if fii “in” and ʕalaa “on” can be taken as prepositions p's, assigning genitive case, ʕind-a “near” and jaanib-a “next to” are in fact axial nouns (denoting axes), which receive case, depending on context (often an accusative).

Within the DM model adopted in this paper, the categorizing nodes (or f-morphemes) are separated from root nodes (or l-morphemes). The structure of (69a) can be represented partially in (72a), and that of (69c) in (72b):

(72) yes

In (72), the root √fii, endowed with the interpretable feature [+loc] is probed by p, which is the locus of the uninterpretable feature [loc]. √-to-p Move is, accordingly, motivated by the probe-goal matching. After moving the root √ to the categorizer p, √fii surfaces as a p that assigns a genitive case to its complement. In contrast, √jaanib-a “next to”, although sharing the same [+loc] feature, surfaces as an axial noun, with its specific semantics, and being a noun makes it subject to case assignment, which is a morphological accusative in (69c), and a genitive assigned by the preposition as in (73a), represented in the structure (73b):

(73) yes

To account for the invariant accusative case assigned to jaanib-a “next” in (69c), Fassi Fehri (2021) assume an extra structural KP higher than the axial nP as in (74). The K head hosts the accusative case of the axial noun:

(74) yes

In the absence of the preposition, the axial noun is motivated to move to p according to the requirement imposed by the Edge of XP developed by Collins (2007), which goes back to the Doubly Filled Comp Filter (Chomsky and Lasnik, 1977):

(75) a. Edge(X) must be phonetically overt.

b. The condition in (a) applies in a
minimal way, so that either the head or
the specifier, but not both, are
spelled out overtly.

(Nchare and
Terzi,
2014
, p. 694)

Based on (75), the axial locative noun jaanib-a “next to” in the absence of a preposition cannot remain in situ to ensure that condition (a) be minimally applied. It undergoes head movement to p, although not directly. Due to the Head Movement Constraint, it moves to the lower head K, then next to p.

Beside [+loc], there are other semantic features that can be associated with the locational root. Figure and Ground are associated to spatial configurations based on the relative Size and Stability (or Mobility) properties of F with respect to G (Landau and Jackendoff, 1993). As pointed out by Miller and Johnson-Laird (1976) and Talmy (1983), “if the objects are unequal in size and mobility, the larger and more stable is invariably encoded as the reference object [Ground]” (Landau and Jackendoff, 1993, p. 224). This is illustrated by the awkward status of the English (a) examples, or that of the Arabic (b) examples in (76) and (77):

(76) a. ?The table is under the book.

b. *l-maqʕad-u      ʕalaa           sutrat-i           n-najaat -i

            the-seat-NOM    on               jacket-GEN      the-life-
                                                                               GEN

          Intended to mean:                  “The life jacket is under
                                                        the seat.”

(77) a. ?The garage is near the bike.

b. *l-masjid-u                  jaanib-a                 s-sayyarat-i

             the-mosque-NOM     next-ACC               the-car-GEN

             Intended to mean:   “The car is next to the mosque.”

The oddness or ill-formedness of (76) and (77) has its source in the fact that F cannot be bigger in Size than G. Rather, the correct configurations are those exemplified in the following constructions:

(78) a. The book is on the table.

b. The bike is near the garage.

(79) a. sutrat-u           n-njaat-i      taḥt-a            l-maqʕad-i

            jacket-GEN      the-life-       under-ACC   the-seat-
                                  GEN                                  GEN

            “The life jacket is under the seat.”

b. s-sayyarat-     jaanib-a     l-masjid-i

            u

            the-car-        next-ACC     the-mosque-GEN

            NOM

            “The car is next to the mosque.”

However, we see at this point no reason that treat these features are syntactic (or morphosyntactic), in addition to being semantic, or conceptual, due to cognitive constraints that are grammaticalized.

3.2 AxPartPs

Axial or Axpart expressions, in addition to [loc], [Stab], and [Size], carry a vector space semantics (Zwarts, 1997; Zwarts and Winter, 2000). They denote sets of points occupied by G to some other regions or axes of the G such as its top, bottom, front, sides, etc. This axial property is identified syntactically as AxPart (Svenonius, 2006, 2010). In Arabic, axial expressions are categorized as nouns in most cases. They are identified not only semantically, but also syntactically. It is notable that what corresponds to English axial prepositions (over, under, behind, in front of, etc.) are in fact nouns in Arabic (fawq-a “over,” taḥt-a “under,” xalf-a “behind,” Ɂamaam-a “in front of”) that receive various cases, depending on their distribution. To illustrate, consider the following examples:

(80) a. Ɂanaa                daaxil-a      l-bayt-i

            I                        inside-ACC   the-house-GEN

            “I am inside the house.”

b. Ɂanaa                xalf-a         l-baab-i

            I                        behind-      the-book-GEN

                                      ACC

            “I am behind the door.”

c. l-kitaab-u          fawq-a        ṭ-ṭaawilat-i

            the-book-NOM  above-ACC    the-table-GEN

            “The book is on the table.”

(81) a. Ɂanaa            fii         daaxil-i         l-bayt-i

            I                   in          inside-GEN     the-house-GEN

            “I am inside the house.”

b. Ɂanaa           fii          xalf-i             l-baab-i

            I                   in           behind-GEN   the-book-GEN

            “I am behind the door.”      

c. l-kitaab-u     min        fawq-i           ṭ-ṭaawilat-i

            the-book-   from      above-GEN     the-table-GEN

            NOM

            “The book is on the table.”

In (81), the axial expressions daaxil-a “inside”, xalf-a “behind”, and fawq-a “above” are the mere devices for the locational interpretation in the absence of a locative verb. Therefore, daaxil-a “inside”, xalf-a “behind”, and fawq-a “above” are endowed with a semantic/syntactic interpretable feature [loc]. Additionally, they are endowed with the features [Stab] and [Size], given the impossibility to select a Ground that is in motion or smaller than the Figure:

(82) a. *l-bayt-u                xalf-a         s-sayyarat-i

            the-house-NOM   behind-      the-car-GEN

                                          ACC

            Intended to         “The car is in front of the house.”

            mean:

b. *ṭ-ṭaawilat-u         fawq-a        l-kitaab-i

            the-table-NOM    above-ACC   the-book-GEN

            Intended to        “The book is on the table.”

            mean:

The dual projections nP and √P in our account correspond to the single projection AxPart in Svenonius (2006, 2010) account, represented in (6) above, repeated here in (84b). For the sake of comparison, consider the English and Arabic pairs in (83) and their representations.

(83) a. Ɂaqif-u         fii      Ɂamaam-i      l-bayt-i

           stood-I         in       front-GEN       the-house-GEN

           “I stood in front of the house.”

b. I stood in front of the house.

(84) yes

It is worth noting that the projection of KP does not seem to be supported in Arabic. While K, which in English lexicalizes “of,” holds a Possession relation between the Axial Parts and the Ground DP. The Arabic has no of-type Possession relation. The Arabic Possessor merges as a complement in a Construct State configuration, and not as high in the structure as the English synthetic Possessor (see Fassi Fehri, 1993 for detail about construct state possessives).

3.3 DegP

Locative expressions denote a distance on how far F is located with respect to G (see Herskovits, 1986; Koopman, 2000; den Dikken, 2006; Svenonius, 2010, 2012; Gärdenfors, 2015, among others). Some denote a far distance, endowed with the feature [Proj] such as fawq-a “over,” taḥt-a “under,” xalf-a “behind,” and Ɂamaam-a “in front of.” Others denote a near distance, endowed with the semantic features [Prox(imity)], such as jaanib “beside” and ʕind “at/by,” [Interpol(ation)] such as bayn “between,” or a zero distance, endowed with [Contact] or [Coincide], such as ʕalaa “on” and bi “in/at,” respectively. As is the case in English, Arabic makes a syntactic distinction between Proj and non-Proj expressions based on the tolerance to MeasP:

(85) a. We remained sixty feet in front of the palace.

b. *They opened the door one meter next to the stage.

(86) a. y-aqaʕu    l-masjid-   ʕalaa    buʕd-i      mitr-ayin    xalf-a

                             u

           3-locate    the-            on       distance-  meter-        behind-

                              mosque-               GEN           DUAL.           ACC

                              NOM                                       GEN

           l-bayt-i

           the-

           house-

           GEN

           “The mosque is two meters behind the house.”

b. *y-aqaʕu  l-masjid-  ʕalaa  buʕd-i      mitr-ayin    jaanib-a

                            u

            3-locate   the-           on      distance-  meter-        next to-

                              mosque-              GEN          DUAL.           ACC

                              NOM                                     GEN

            l-bayt-i

            the-house-GEN

            Intended  “The mosque is two meters next to the house.”

            to mean:

Further evidence that Proj is a syntactic feature in Arabic comes from the contrast between semantically related pair expressions such as fawq “above” and ʕalaa “on.” The Proj feature makes it possible for fawq “above” to collocate with far-distance denoting verbs such as ya-ṭiiru “fly” as in (87a), while in the same context ʕalaa “on,” which is [-Proj], cannot occur (87b).

(87) a. ta-ṭiiru          ṭ-ṭaaɁirat-u    fawq-a      bayt-i-na

           3F-fly            the-plane-    over-ACC     house-GEN-

                                NOM                                our

           “The plane is flying over our house.”

b. *ta-ṭiiru        ṭ-ṭaaɁirat-u  ʕalaa        bayt-i-na

            3F-fly           the-plane-   on            house-GEN-

                                NOM                               our

            Intended to  “The plane is flying over our house.”

            mean,

Additionally, the Contact feature associated with the non-Proj expressions provides the meaning of Support in spatial and non-spatial domains (Gärdenfors, 2015), which enables ʕalaa “on,” but not fawq “above,” to collocate with certain verbs such as ya-ʕtamid “rely,” yartakiz “depend/base:”

(88) a. y-aʕtamidu   l-Ɂab-u        ʕalaa      bn-i-hi

           3-rely            the-father-   on         son-GEN-

                                 NOM                             his

           “The father relies on his son.”

b. y-artakizu      r-rajul-u      ʕalaa      ʕaṣaa-hu

           3-depend      the-man-      on           stick.GEN-

                                  NOM                            his

           “The man depends on his stick.”      

c. y-artakizu     r-raʕ-u         ʕalaa      Ɂasaas-in       ṣaḥiiḥ-in

           3-base          the-               on          ground-        correct-

                                 opinion-                      GEN               GEN

                               NOM

           “The opinion is based on a solid ground.”

(89) a. *y-               l-Ɂab-u        fawq-a   bn-i-hi

            aʕtamidu

            3-rely         the-father-    over-     son-GEN-

                               NOM               ACC        his

            Intended to “The father relies on his son.”

            mean:

b. *y-artakizu     r-rajul-u     fawq-a   ʕaṣaa-hu

            3-depend      the-man-    over-      stick.GEN-

                                   NOM            ACC        his

            Intended to “The man depends on his stick.”

            mean:

c. *y-artakizu     r-raɁy-u     fawq-a   Ɂasaas-in    ṣaḥiiḥ-in

            3-base          the-            over-      ground-      correct-

                                 opinion-    ACC         GEN             GEN

                                 NOM

            Intended to “The opinion is based on a solid ground.”

            mean:

Given that [Proj] and other features of the same kind are of syntactic feature in Arabic, we assume, following Svenonius (2010, 2012), that they are hosted under a separate projection, namely DegP. The latter is higher than PlaceP, but lower than pP. It is also higher than KP, leading to the following cartographic structure:

(90) yes

3.4 DeixP

A further interpretation expressed by the spatial expression is related to distality (distance from the speaker). The distal interpretation indicates different degrees of proximity to a deictic center (Svenonius, 2006). In Arabic, this distal information is introduced by the deictic locative adverb hunaa/hunaak, parallels English here/there:

(91) a. a few centimeters under                (Svenonius, 2010, p. 140)

            here

b. y-          l-           ʕalaa  buʕd-i      mitr-    hunaa   xalf-a

           aqaʕu    masjid-                             ayin

                         u

            3-         the-        on      distance-  meter-  here      behind-

            locate   mosque-          GEN           DUAL.GEN            ACC

                         NOM

            l-bayt-i

            the-house-GEN

            “The mosque is two meters behind the house.”

Following Svenonius (2010), we assume that there is an additional a DeixP below DegP that hosts the deictic adverb hunaa “here.”

3.5 Directional paths

Directional expressions are cross-linguistically, distinguished from locational ones both semantically and syntactically (Jackendoff, 1983; Wunderlich, 1991; Zwarts, 1997, 2005; Koopman, 2000; Zwarts and Winter, 2000; Kracht, 2002; Gehrke, 2008; den Dikken, 2010; Svenonius, 2010). Semantically, they denote a direction of an intended motion, endowed with the feature [dir]. Syntactically, they cannot occur in static contexts as illustrated in English (2b) above, repeated here in (92a). We take the impossibility of directional to occur in the verbless sentence context like (92b) as a negative diagnostic for directional PPs in Arabic:

(92) a. *The box stayed/remained to/into/from/out

            of/down/through the table.

                                                    (Gehrke, 2008, p. 87)

b. *Ɂanaa  Ɂilaa    /min/      xilaal-   ṣawb-a          l-bayt-i

                                                    a/

            I             to        /from/    throu-    /toward-     the-

                                                    gh-                             house-

                                                    ACC        ACC                GEN

            Lit:        “I am   from      /thou-    toward the house.”

                          to/                     gh/

3.5.1 Complexity of dir PPs

It is generally agreed that directional preposition phrases, or Paths, are structurally complex because they embed Places. We argue that directional expressions are even more complex in Arabic than the widely accepted PathPs. One reason is that each projection of Path or Place root may surface as a preposition p or as a noun n as illustrated in (93):

(93) yes

Another reason is related to Path expressions that surface as axial nouns (or AxPart) such as ʕabr-a “across,” ḥawl-a “around,” xilaal-a “through,” etc. More projections are required not only because they are syntactically nouns having an interpretable feature [+dir] that checks the uninterpretable feature [dir] of a higher probe p, but also because they are assigned a (oblique) case by a K head in the absence of a c-commanding preposition. For example, the directional expression ʕabr-a “across” in sentence (94a) can be represented in (94b):

(94) yes

Additionally, if we follow Svenonius (2010), ʕabr-a “across” would be an extended (PathPlace) preposition, like across in English, meaning that it is a location head conflated with the directional head. Compare the English example in (95a) (Svenonius, 2010, p. 149), with the structure in (95b), to the representation of the Arabic ʕabr-a “across” in (96), as adapted to Arabic:

(95) yes

(96) yes

3.5.2 Transition and scale

Goal expressions Ɂilaa/li- “to” vs. ṣawb-a/naḥw-a/tujaah-a “toward” illustrated in (97) typically hold the same contrast between goal-oriented to and toward in English (98) (Evans and Tyler, 2004, p. 263):

(97) a. taḥarraka-t    l-kurat-u         Ɂilaa      l-marmaa

            moved-F      the-ball-          to           the-

                                  NOM                              goal.GEN

            “The ball moved to the goal.”

b. taḥarraka-t     l-kurat-u        ṣawb-a      l-marmaa

    moved-F        the-ball-         towards-   the-

                            NOM               ACC            goal.GEN

    “The ball moved towards the goal.”

(98) a. He ran to the shop.

b. He ran toward the shop.

The semantic contrast between to and toward has been described as being relating to whether the trajectory does or doesn't reach the goal, respectively. In Kracht (2002) and Pancheva (2011) terminology, to has a transitional Goal (or Cofinal), whereas toward has non transitional Goal (or Approximative) Goal, each one bearing the feature [±TRANSITION]. Accordingly, the ball did reach the goal in (97a) but didn't in (97b). Similarly, with to, the trajectory (i.e. he) arrives at the shop in (98a), but with toward, sentence (98b), it does not entail that the trajectory (i.e., he) arrives at the shop. In Fassi Fehri's (2021) account, the contrast is attributed by the absence/presence of a semantic Mot(ion) feature in Ɂilaa/li- “to” vs. ṣawb-a/naḥw-a/tujaah-a “toward,” respectively. That makes the latter interpreted as being in motion. But the contrast between Ɂilaa/li- “to” and ṣawb-a/naḥw-a/tujaah-a “toward” could be equally attributed to the [±TRANSITION] feature opposition, in parallel to Pancheva's account.

Pancheva (2011) takes the transition opposition to be syntactically differentiated. She argues that the non-transition path expression toward in English is derived from the transition path to by having a higher scale head projecting ScaleP, and dominating GoalP, as represented in (99). The Scale head delimits the transition value, turning the goal expression into a non-transitional one:

(99) yes

But despite the fact that in (99) Scale may seem to correctly explain the relation between the two morphemes to- and -ward in English, it doesn't seem to hold in Arabic. And although we agree with Procházka (2011) that toward is a complex head, we question that it is Scale. Since the the Mot(ion) feature described by Fassi Fehri (2021) is also semantico-syntactic, the contrast is between the directional Ɂilaa/li- “to” that can occur in static contexts and the motional ṣawb-a/naḥw-a/tujaah-a “toward,” which cannot tolerate stativity:

(100) a. t-ṭariiq-u     Ɂilaa             makkat-a      muzdaḥim-

                                                                             un

             the-road-      to               Makkah-       crowded-

             NOM                                  GEN               NOM

             “The road to Makkah is crowded.”

b. *ṭariiq-u        ṣawb-a        makkat-a       muzdaḥim-

                                                                             un

             road-NOM      toward-      Makkah-       crowded-

                                   ACC             GEN                NOM

             Intended to mean       :    “The road to

                                                     Makkah is crowded.”

Moreover, Ɂilaa “to” can select a directional-denoting expression such as yamiin “right” and yasaar “left,” resulting in a directional static interpretation, while ṣawb-a/naḥw-a/tujaah-a “toward” cannot:

(101) a. r-rajul-u       waaqif-u-n  Ɂilaa              l-yamiin-i

             the-man-    standing-     to                  the-right-

             NOM              NOM-N                               GEN

             “The man is standing to the right.”

b. *r-rajul-u      waaqif-u-n   naḥw-a          l-yamiin-i

             the-man-      standing-      toward-         the-right-

             NOM             NOM-N           ACC                GEN

             Intended to mean:             “The man is standing

                                                       to the right.”

We therefore suggest that the additional morpheme is Proc(ess), adopting Ramchand's (2008) terminology, rather than Scale. The construction in (101b) above is represented in (102). The presence of Proc explains why ṣawb-a/naḥw-a/tujaah-a “toward” cannot tolerate static contexts.

(102) yes

4 Conclusion

In this paper, we have provided a finer account of the syntactic and semantic complexity of basic Arabic spatial prepositional and axial noun phrases, as manifested in Places and Paths. As in DM architecture, we have separated root (or “lexical”) nodes from category (or functional) nodes, distinguishing √P (or “big”P) from (“small”) p, as in Larson's (1988, 2014) shell structure. We have provided essential ingredients allowing the decomposition of Place and Path words or expressions into √Ploc, √Pdir, or Pmot roots, in addition to Contain, Contact, or Coincide features, etc. Syntactic projections of AxPartP, DegP, DeixP, RouteP, GoalP, SourceP, and ProcP etc. have been supported and hierarchically ordered, following the lead of Svenonius's and Cinque's cartographies. Moreover, a detailed description of the basic prepositions and axial nouns in Arabic has been provided in the light of examining their syntactic and/or semantic features and their categories or projections, enabling appropriate analyses of their correlated alternations, polysemy, interacting features, as well as their variation across diverse colloquial dialects. Needless to say, more work has to be done, from a cross-linguistic comparative perspective, to see what patterns or construction types are more widespread, and how much allosemy or allomorphy is predictable through the model.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding authors.

Author contributions

AF: Writing – review & editing, Writing – original draft, Project administration, Methodology, Investigation, Formal analysis, Data curation, Conceptualization. MA: Writing – review & editing, Writing – original draft, Project administration, Methodology, Investigation, Formal analysis, Data curation, Conceptualization.

Funding

The author(s) declare financial support was received for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. MA was partially supported by the King Abdulaziz University for presenting an earlier version of the paper at the 5th International Workshop on Syntactic Cartography (IWSC2023).

Acknowledgments

We would like to express our deepest gratitude to two reviewers for their insightful feedbacks and constructive remarks, which substantially improved the content of the article. An earlier version of the contribution was presented at the 5th International Workshop on Syntactic Cartography (IWSC2023) at Beijing, co-organized by the Department of Linguistics at Beijing Language and Culture University (BLCU), the International Association of Syntactic Cartographic Studies (IAOSCS) (Macao), and the Journal of Beijing International Studies University, 29-30 October 2023. We would like to thank the audience there for their fruitful comments, and we extend our thanks to Prof. Nadia Aamiri and Prof. Nuha Alshurafa for fruitful discussions.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

Footnotes

1. ^For example, the two psych verb constructions in the following pair of examples are headed by verbal roots which are arguably monadic and dyadic roots, respectively, as shown in Fassi Fehri (2023, to appear):

(i) gaḍiba                l-walad-u

     anger-PAST       the child-NOM

     “The child angered; became angry.”

(ii) y-akrah-u            l-walad-u               t-tanaafus-a

      3-hate-INDIC      the-child-NOM      the-competition-ACC

       “The child hates the competition.”

Causativization of (ii) is possible, indicating that it is a basic transitive, whereas the causative of a derived transitive is ill-formed:

(iii) ʔ-akraha                    r-rajul-u                l-walad-u            t-tanaafus-a

       CAUSE-hate-PAST      the-man-NOM      the-child-ACC      the-

                                                                                                    competition-

                                                                                                    ACC

       “The man caused the child to hate the competition.”

We assume that such option is also open for prepositions, without providing more detail here, due to space.

2. ^A cartography in the same spirit, but with more elaboration, is developed by Cinque (2010) as follows:

(i) [PPdir [PPstat [DPplace [DegP [ModelDirP [AbsViewP [RelViewP [RelViewP [DeicticP [AxPartP

     [PP P [NPplace the table [PLACE]]]]]]]]]]]]]

     (Cinque, 2010, p.8)

There is, however, one important difference between Svenonius” and Cinque”s cartographies in that the latter introduces a PLACE noun, which is essentially silent in English, and that a number of the functional projections of Svenonius are fused under PLACE (Kayne, 2004, 2007).

3. ^See fn. 5 below for detailed feature-based decomposition of Path PPs into eight subtypes in Pancheva (2011).

4. ^Among its less prototypical senses is CAUSATION taʕliil, as in (i)-(iii):

(i) qutila              kulayb-u             fii      naaqat-in

     killed.PASS      Kulayb-NOM      in      cow-GEN

     “Kulayb was   (Jan, 2018, p.

      killed for         133)

      (steeling/losing)

      a cow.”

A further meaning is ACCOMPANIMENT musaahaba:

(ii) xaraja                   l-Ɂamiir-u         fii      mawkib-in         ḥaafil-in

      went out             the-prince-      in      procession-      festive-GEN

                                   NOM                           GEN

      “The prince        (Jan, 2018, p.

      went out in a      133)

      festive

      procession.”

Yet another meaning is SUPERPOSITION stiʕlaaɁ:

(iii) ṣalaba-hum         fii      juḏuuʕ-I           n-naxl-i

       crucified-them   in      trunks-GEN      the-palm

                                                                       trees-GEN

       “He crucified them on the trunks of palm trees.” (Jan, 2018, p. 134)

5. ^Other typical meanings of bi- include notably INSTRUMENT/MEANS, as in (i), or MANNER, as in (ii):

 (i)  ṭaʕana-hu                     bi-sikkiin-in

      stabbed.3-him            with-knife-GEN

      “He stabbed him with a knife.”

(ii)  ṭaʕana-hu                bi-surʕat-in

      stabbed.3-him        with-quickness-GEN

      “He stabbed him quickly.”

6. ^Note that the (b) examples are ungrammatical, although the two question marksindicate that they are only hardly acceptable, given interferences with colloquial dialects, in which the two prepositions are at variation. See Section 2.2.

7. ^Creissels notes that Heine's (1997) “companion schema” and Stassen's (2009) “with-possessive” and his “comitative-possessee” construction refer to possessive clauses glossable as “Possessor (is) with Possessee”, and that possessive maʕa clauses belong to the same oblique-possessor type as the possessive ʕinda- or li- clauses of Classical Arabic. In the original example, be is glossed “by”, but this preposition also has instrumental and comitative uses, and as the author rightly observes in the section where he describes the uses of be (p. 183), its use to flag the possessee in a possessive construction certainly derives from its comitative meaning. Consequently, in this example, the gloss “with” is more adequate.

References

Al-Muraadii, H. Q. (1992). Al-junaa al-daanii fii ?uruufi-l-ma?aanii. Beirut: Dar al Aafaaq. Available online at: https://archive.org/details/1249pdf_201912/page/n13/mode/2up (accessed August 15, 2020).

Google Scholar

Bierwisch, M. (1996). “How much space gets into language?,” in Language and Space, eds. P. Bloom, M. Peterson, L. Needle, M.F. Garrettet (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 31–76. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/4107.003.0004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Brenda, M. (2015). The Semantics of “at”. Ann. Neophilol. 9, 26–55. doi: 10.18276/an.2015.9-02

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Chomsky, N. (1995). The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Chomsky, N. (2001). “Derivation by phase,” in Ken Hale: A Life in Language, ed. M. Kenstowicz (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 1–52. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/4056.003.0004

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Chomsky, N., and Lasnik, H. (1977). Filters and control. Ling. Inquiry 8, 425–504.

Google Scholar

Cinque, G. (2010). “Mapping spatial PPs: an introduction,” in Mapping Spatial PPs. The Cartography of Syntactic Structures 6, eds. G. Cinque, L. Rizzi (New York: Oxford University Press), 3–25. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195393675.003.0001

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Collins, C. (2007). Home sweet home. NYU Working Papers in Linguistics, 1–34.

Google Scholar

Creissels, D. (2022). Existential predication and predicative possession in Arabic dialects. STUF 75, 583–612. doi: 10.1515/stuf-2022-1064

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Deacon, R. J. (2011). P-forms in distributed morphology: accounting for a type of semilexical form. MA thesis, University of Florida, Gainesville.

Google Scholar

Demirdache, H., and Uribe-Etxebarria, M. (2014). Aspect and temporal anaphora. Nat. Lang. Linguist. Theor. 32, 855–895. doi: 10.1007/s11049-014-9231-2

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

den Dikken, M. (2003). On the syntax of locative and directional adpositional phrases. Ms. City University of New York, New York.

Google Scholar

den Dikken, M. (2006). On the functional structure of locative and directional PPs. Ms. City University of New York, New York.

Google Scholar

den Dikken, M. (2010). “On the functional structure of locative and directional PPs,” in Mapping Spatial PPs: Cartography of Syntactic Structures, eds. G. Cinque, L. Rizzi (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 74–126. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195393675.003.0003

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Embick, D., and Noyer, R. (2005). “Distributed morphology and the syntax/morphology interface,” in The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Interfaces, eds. G. Ramchand, C. Reiss (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 289–324.

Google Scholar

Esseesy, M. (2010). Grammaticalization of Arabic Prepositions and Subordinators: A Corpusbased Study. Leiden: Brill. doi: 10.1163/9789004187634

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Evans, V., and Tyler, A. (2004). “Rethinking English “prepositions of movement”: the case of to and through,” in Adpositions of Movement, eds. H. Cuyckens, W. de Mulder, T. Mortelmans (Amsterdam: John Benjamins), 247–270. doi: 10.1075/bjl.18.13eva

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fassi Fehri, A. (1986). The Arabic Lexicon [l-mu?jam l-?arabii]. Casablanca: Tubqal Publishers.

Google Scholar

Fassi Fehri, A. (1993). Issues in the Structure of Arabic Clauses and Words. Dordrecht: Kluwer. doi: 10.1007/978-94-017-1986-5

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fassi Fehri, A. (2021). The Arabic Constructional and Variational Lexicon. Amman: Dar Kunuuz.

Google Scholar

Fassi Fehri, A. (2023). “Psych construction types in Arabic as root-based,” in Paper presented at SLE 56 (Athens: University of Athens).

Google Scholar

Fassi Fehri, A., and Alrawi, M. (2023). Arabic PPs in a rooted lexicon. Languages 8, 1–23. doi: 10.3390/languages8020095

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Freeze, R. (1992). Existentials and other locatives. Language 68, 553–595. doi: 10.2307/415794

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gärdenfors, P. (2015). The geometry of preposition meanings. Baltic Int. Yearb. Cogn. Logic Commun. 10, 1–18. doi: 10.4148/1944-3676.1098

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gehrke, B. (2008). Ps in motion: On the semantics and syntax of P elements and motion events. LOT Dissertation Series, Netherlands Graduate School of Linguistics, Utrecht.

Google Scholar

Hale, H., and Keyser, S. J. (2002). Prolegomenon to a Theory of Argument Structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/5634.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hale, K. (1986). “Notes on world view and semantic categories: some Warlpiri examples,” in Features and Projections, Studies in Generative Grammar 25, eds. P. Muysken, H. van Riemsdijk (Dordrecht: Foris), 233–254. doi: 10.1515/9783110871661-009

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Halle, M., and Marantz, A. (1993). “Distributed morphology and the pieces of inflection,” in The View from Building 20, eds. K. Hale, S. J. Keyser (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 111–176.

Google Scholar

Harley, H. (2002). Possession and the double object construction. Ling. Variat. Yearb. 2, 29–68. doi: 10.1075/livy.2.04har

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Harley, H. (2014). On the identity of roots. Theor. Ling. 40, 225–276. doi: 10.1515/tl-2014-0010

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Harley, H., and Noyer, R. (1999). Distributed morphology. Glot Int. 4, 3–9.

Google Scholar

Heine, B. (1997). Possession: Cognitive Sources, Forces and Grammaticalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511581908

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Herskovits, A. (1986). Language and Spatial Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Study of the Prepositions in English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Google Scholar

Ibn Hišaam, J. (1985). Mugnii l-labiib, 6th Edn. [14th C.]. Cairo: Al-Madani Publishers. Available online at: https://archive.org/details/moharram1965_gmail_20180428/page/n339/mode/2up (accessed March 20, 2020).

Google Scholar

Jackendoff, R. (1983). Semantics and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Jahfa, A. (2011). “Verbs of recipient and content,” in Arabic Issues in Arabic Linguistics, eds. A. Khayri, A. Jahfa, and A. Rachad. (Casablanca: Faculty of Arts and Human Sciences), 11–28.

Google Scholar

Jan, H. (2018). A cognitive linguistic approach to explaining the polysemy of ‘alaa and fii in Modern Standard Arabic. PhD thesis, Georgetown University, Washington, D.C.

Google Scholar

Kayne, R. S. (1993). Toward a modular theory of auxiliary selection. Stud. Ling. 47, 3–31. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9582.1993.tb00837.x

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kayne, R. S. (2004). “Prepositions as probes,” in Structures and Beyond, ed. A. Belletti (New York: Oxford University Press), 192–212. (reprinted in Kayne (2005)). doi: 10.1093/oso/9780195171976.003.0006

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kayne, R. S. (2007). “On the Salient Absence of You are to be home by midnight in Italian Dialects (and Various Other Languages),” in paper presented at the 2nd Cambridge Italian Dialect Syntax Meeting (Cambridge, England).

Google Scholar

Koopman, H. (2000). “Prepositions, postpositions, circumpositions, and particles,” in The Syntax of specifiers and Heads, ed. H. Koopman (London: Routledge), 204–260. doi: 10.4324/9780203171608

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kracht, M. (2002). On the semantics of locatives. Ling. Philos. 25, 157–232. doi: 10.1023/A:1014646826099

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kracht, M. (2008). “The fine structure of local expressions,” in The Structure of Local P, eds. A. Asbury, J. Dotlačil, B. Gehrke, R. Nouwen (Amsterdam: John Benjamins), 35–62.

Google Scholar

Landau, B., and Jackendoff, R. (1993). “What” and “where” in spatial language and spatial cognition. Behav. Brain Sci. 16, 217–265. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X00029733

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Larson, R. K. (1988). Scope and comparatives. Ling. Philos. 11, 1–26. doi: 10.1007/BF00635755

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Larson, R. K. (2014). On Shell Structure. New York and London: Routledge. doi: 10.4324/9780203429204

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lentzner, K. (1977). Semantic and syntactic aspects of Arabic prepositions. Doctoral dissertation, Georgetown University, Washington, D.C.

Google Scholar

Manfredi, S. (2010). A grammatical description of Kordofanian Baggara Arabic. PhD thesis, Università degli Studi di Napoli L”Orientale, Naples.

Google Scholar

Marantz, A. (1997). No escape from syntax: don't try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics, 201–225.

Google Scholar

Marantz, A. (2013). “Locality domains for contextual allomorphy across the interfaces,” in Distributed Morphology Today: Morphemes for Morris Halle, eds. O. Matushansky, A. Marantz (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 95–116. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/9701.003.0008

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Miller, G. A., and Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1976). Language and Perception. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. doi: 10.4159/harvard.9780674421288

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nam, S. (1995). The Semantics of Locative Prepositional Phrases in English. Los Angeles: University of California.

Google Scholar

Nchare, A., and Terzi, A. (2014). Licensing silent structure: the spatial prepositions of Shupamem. Nat. Lang. Ling. Theory 32, 673–710. doi: 10.1007/s11049-014-9230-3

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Pancheva, M. (2011). Decomposing path: the nanosyntax of directional expressions. PhD thesis, University of Tromsø, Norway.

Google Scholar

Piñón, C. J. (1993). “Paths and their names,” in Chicago Linguistics Society 29 Beals, eds. K., Cooke, G., Kathman, D., Kita, S., McCullough, K., D. Testen (Chicago: Chicago Linguistics Society), 287–303.

Google Scholar

Procházka, S. (1993). “Some remarks on the semantic function of the reduplicated quadrilateral verbs (structure fa3fa3a),” in Proceedings of the Colloquium on Arabic Lexicology and Lexicography 1, eds. D. Kinga, T. Ivanyi (Budapest: Eotvos Lorand University and Csoma de Koros Society), 97–103.

Google Scholar

Procházka, S. (2011). “Prepositions,” in EALL, ed. K. Versteegh (Leiden: Brill), 699–703.

Google Scholar

Ramchand, G. (2008). Verb Meaning and the Lexicon. New York: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511486319

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Rooryck, J. (1996). “Prepositions and minimalist case marking,” in Studies in Comparative Germanic Syntax II, eds. H. Thrainsson, S. D. Epstein, and S. Peter (Amsterdam: Kluwer), 226–256. doi: 10.1007/978-94-010-9806-9_9

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Saad, A. (2019). “Les pseudo-verbes dans le dialecte de Benghazi: valeurs possessives et non possessives,” in Studies on Arabic dialectology and sociolinguistics: Proceedings of the 12th international conference of AIDA, eds. C. Miller, A. Barontini, M. Germanos, J. Guerrero, C. Pereira (Aix-en-Provence: Institut de recherches et d'études sur les mondes arabes et musulmans), 232–244. doi: 10.4000/books.iremam.4755

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Saeed, S. (2014). The syntax and semantics of Arabic spatial Ps. Newcastle and Northumbria Working Papers in Linguistics, 44–66.

Google Scholar

Stassen, L. (2009). Predicative Possession. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/oso/9780199211654.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Svenonius, P. (2006). The emergence of axial parts. Tromsø Working Papers in Linguistics, 50–71.

Google Scholar

Svenonius, P. (2010). “Spatial P in English,” in Mapping Spatial PPs, The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, eds. G. Cinque, L. Rizzi (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 127–160. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195393675.003.0004

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Svenonius, P. (2012). Structural decomposition of spatial adpositions. Ms. Universitetet I Tromsø, Norway.

Google Scholar

Taine-Cheikh, C. (2008). “De l”expression de la cause et de la causalité dans l”arabe de Mauritanie,” in Between the Atlantic and Indian oceans: Studies on contemporary Arabic dialects. Proceedings of the 7th AIDA, eds. S. Procházka, V. Ritt-Benmimoun (Vienna: LIT-Verlag), 423–436.

Google Scholar

Talmy, L. (1975). “Semantics and syntax of motion,” in Syntax and Semantics, ed. J. Kimball (New York: Academic Press), 181–238. doi: 10.1163/9789004368828_008

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Talmy, L. (1983). “How language structures space,” in Spatial Orientation: Theory, Research and Application, eds. H. L. Pick, L. P. Acredolo (New York: Plenum Press), 225–282. doi: 10.1007/978-1-4615-9325-6_11

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Talmy, L. (2000). Towards a Cognitive Semantics: Typology and Process in Concept Structuring. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/6848.001.0001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wood, J., and Marantz, A. (2017). “The interpretation of external arguments,” in The Verbal Domain, eds. R. D'Alessandro, I. Franco, Á. J. Gallego (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 255–78. doi: 10.1093/oso/9780198767886.003.0011

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Wunderlich, D. (1991). How do prepositional phrases fit into compositional syntax and semantics? Linguistics 29, 591–621. doi: 10.1515/ling.1991.29.4.591

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zwarts, J. (1997). Vectors as relative positions: a compositional semantics of modified PPs. J. Semant. 14, 57–86. doi: 10.1093/jos/14.1.57

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zwarts, J. (2005). Prepositional aspect and the algebra of paths. Ling. Philos. 28, 739–779. doi: 10.1007/s10988-005-2466-y

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zwarts, J. (2008). “Priorities in the production of prepositions,” in Syntax and Semantics of Spatial P, eds. A. Asbury, J. Dotlačil, B. Gehrke, R. Nouwen (Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company), 85–102.

Google Scholar

Zwarts, J., and Winter, Y. (2000). Vector space semantics: a model theoretic analysis of locative prepositions. J. Logic, Lang. Inf. 9, 169–211. doi: 10.1023/A:1008384416604

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: prepositions, Axial Parts, Place, Path, P, Distributed Morphology, Arabic

Citation: Fassi Fehri A and Alrawi M (2024) Motivating a fine-grained syntax of Arabic prepositional phrases. Front. Lang. Sci. 3:1360562. doi: 10.3389/flang.2024.1360562

Received: 04 January 2024; Accepted: 17 May 2024;
Published: 12 June 2024.

Edited by:

Maris Camilleri, University of Essex, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Peter Hallman, Austrian Research Institute for Artificial Intelligence, Austria
Hassan Banaruee, University of Education Weingarten, Germany

Copyright © 2024 Fassi Fehri and Alrawi. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Abdelkader Fassi Fehri, YWJkZWxrYWRlcmZhc3NpZmVocmkmI3gwMDA0MDtnbWFpbC5jb20=; Maather Alrawi, TWFhdGhlci5hbHJhd2kmI3gwMDA0MDtnbWFpbC5jb20=

These authors have contributed equally to this work and share first authorship

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.