- 1Laboratoire d'Etude des Mécanismes Cognitifs, Université de Lyon, Lyon, France
- 2Institut Universitaire de France, Paris, France
- 3Laboratoire de Neurosciences Cognitives, CNRS, LNC, Aix Marseille Univ, Marseille, France
- 4CNRS, Fédération 3C, Aix Marseille Univ, Marseille, France
- 5Integrative, Multisensory, Perception, Action, and Cognition Team, Centre de Recherche en Neurosciences de Lyon, INSERM-CNRS-Université de Lyon, Rhône-Alpes, France
- 6Mouvement, Handicap et Neuro-Immersion, Hospices Civils de Lyon et Centre de Recherche en Neurosciences de Lyon, Rhône-Alpes, France
- 7UNIROUEN, CRFDP (EA7475), Normandie Univ, Rouen, France
Introduction
The sense of agency refers to the experience of controlling one's own motor actions and, as a result, external events (Pacherie, 2008; Haggard and Chambon, 2012). Surprisingly, this aspect has been largely overlooked in the literature on apraxia, a disorder affecting skilled and volitional movements (De Renzi, 1989). In this context, an outstanding issue is whether loss of agency is an ignored dimension of apraxia—and particularly of apraxia of tool use (see below)—or whether loss of agency and apraxia of tool use are two independent syndromes based on distinct neurocognitive mechanisms. The goal of this Opinion article is to tackle this issue. Note that we will mainly focus here on apraxia of tool use, namely, difficulties in selecting appropriate everyday tools and/or in performing the mechanical action needed to complete a task. This is only one of the manifestations of apraxia, which may also concern the production of symbolic, meaningful, or meaningless gestures (Osiurak and Rossetti, 2017).
Loss of Agency and Apraxia of Tool Use
The rationale underlying the idea that apraxic patients could experience loss of agency is grounded in classical, neuropsychological models of apraxia. Historically, Liepmann (1908) proposed that tool use is supported by the generation of movement formulae (i.e., the ideation), which are not stored motor programs as commonly thought, but rather images of the action intended (Goldenberg, 2003). There is then a transfer of these movement formulae to the motor innervation. In this framework, patients who fail to generate movement formulae are impaired to use tools. This is the classical description of ideational apraxia: Patients do not know what to do. By contrast, a disconnection between movement formulae and motor innervation leads to ideomotor apraxia: Patients know what to do but not how to do it. A last aspect concerns the deficit of motor innervation (i.e., motor apraxia initially called limb-kinetic apraxia), an aspect we will discuss later in this paper. Although Liepmann's model has been repeatedly updated (Geschwind, 1975; Heilman et al., 1982; Rothi et al., 1991; Cubelli et al., 2000; Buxbaum, 2001, 2017; van Elk et al., 2014), most current, cognitive neuropsychological models are in line with the idea that apraxia of tool use can concern not only the ideational component (i.e., knowing what to do), but also the ability to select the appropriate motor action (i.e., knowing what to do, but not how to do it). Nevertheless, contrary to Liepmann's model, the ideational component is not viewed as the ability to generate a visual image of the action intended, but as the ability to retrieve semantic knowledge about the functional use of everyday tools (hereafter called semantic knowledge). In addition, for Liepmann, movement formulae directly guide the selection of appropriate motor innervatory patterns (i.e., the gesture is reconstructed de novo for each use; for a somewhat similar viewpoint, see Osiurak et al., 2011)and ideomotor apraxia is a disconnection syndrome. By contrast, for current models, people store motor programs specifying the kinematic characteristics of movements associated with the use of a specific tool (hereafter called manipulation knowledge). Thus, the issue of (mis-)selection is no longer a disconnection issue but a memory issue. Note that manipulation knowledge can also be considered as an internal model, helpful to control and predict the consequences of one's own motor actions and to compare them to actual outcomes (Sirigu et al., 2003; Buxbaum, 2017).
In this contemporary perspective, three kinds of disorder can be described (i.e., volition, ideation, and selection), even if only two of them (volition and selection) are be labeled as loss of agency (see Pazzaglia and Galli, 2014). The first has been described as a disorder of volition: The patient has difficulties initiating tool-use actions and exhibiting perplexity (e.g., the patient looks hesitatingly at the tools and objects, picks up some of them, puts them down, and so on; De Renzi and Lucchelli, 1988). Given that semantic knowledge (i.e., the ideational component) can be spared, this is a specific disorder of agency: The patient being unable to initiate volitional motor actions (see Pazzaglia and Galli, 2014). The second is a disorder of ideation, that is, of semantic knowledge. This is not an instance of loss of agency because the patient cannot form a mental representation of what to do. The third is a disorder of selection: The patient knows what to do, but is unable to select the appropriate manipulation knowledge (e.g., when asked to pantomime the use of a hammer, the patient performs a first action [rotational wrist movements], then tries to carry out another one [oscillatory elbow movements], and so on). This is also a disorder of agency because the interference, caused by the competition between different degraded motor programs, weakens the subjective perception of controlling one's own motor actions (see Pazzaglia and Galli, 2014).
In broad terms, loss of agency might clearly be an ignored dimension of apraxia of tool use, and contemporary, cognitive models might be particularly suited to develop the study of the underlying mechanisms (Pazzaglia and Galli, 2014). Consistent with this, studies have confirmed the presence of loss of agency in apraxic patients with unilateral hemisphere lesions using self-generated action paradigms (Sirigu et al., 1999, 2004). When reported in these patients, the loss of agency concerns both hands (ipsilesional and contralesional) and occurs independently from elementary sensorimotor disorders (e.g., motor neglect). However, to our opinion, the link between apraxia of tool use and loss of agency is not as obvious as it might appear, and recent evidence has challenged contemporary models of apraxia.
Volition and Ideation: Two Sides of the Same Coin?
The so-called existence of a selective disorder of volition in apraxia of tool use implies that some patients could have difficulties in initiating tool-use actions without having impaired semantic knowledge (i.e., without a disorder of ideation). This hypothesis presupposes that semantic knowledge supports the ideational component of tool-use actions. However, considerable evidence has indicated that semantic knowledge—commonly assessed with picture-matching tasks—and familiar tool use can be impaired independently (e.g., Negri et al., 2007; Silveri and Ciccarelli, 2009; for a review, see Osiurak and Badets, 2016). In addition, tool-use disorders generally occur in left-brain damaged (LBD) patients presenting lesions within the left inferior parietal lobe (IPL), whereas semantic knowledge involves lesions within the temporal lobes. Taken together, these findings suggest that semantic knowledge cannot be considered as the cognitive basis for the ideation of tool-use actions, as proposed by contemporary, cognitive models of apraxia of tool use, thereby theoretically questioning the aforementioned hypothesis of a disorder of volition without semantic knowledge deficits.
For Liepmann (1908), the ideational component corresponded to the generation of an image of the intended action. Proponents of manipulation-knowledge hypothesis have interpreted it as the visual image of the motor action (i.e., the so-called visuo-kinesthetic engram; e.g., Heilman et al., 1982; Rothi et al., 1991). Nonetheless, another interpretation is that this refers to the visual image of the mechanical action involving tools and objects (e.g., a hammer pounding a nail), an interpretation in line with the technical-reasoning hypothesis (Osiurak et al., 2010; Osiurak and Heinke, 2018; for a somewhat similar viewpoint, see Goldenberg and Hagmann, 1998; Goldenberg and Spatt, 2009). This hypothesis posits that people reason about physical object properties to generate a mental simulation of the mechanical action, appropriate to solve a physical problem. This reasoning is based on mechanical knowledge, that is, knowledge about mechanical and physical principles (e.g., lever, cutting) that might involve the left IPL. A key assumption is that technical reasoning supports the use of both familiar and novel tool use, as confirmed by neuropsychological and neuroimaging studies (for reviews, see Osiurak and Badets, 2016; Reynaud et al., 2016). In this view, patients with impaired technical reasoning can have difficulties not only in initiating tool-use actions (a so-called disorder of volition) but also in performing the appropriate ones (a disorder of ideation). For instance, Osiurak et al. (2013) asked LBD patients with tool-use disorders to solve mechanical problems in using novel tools. Besides severe difficulties in solving the problems, those patients spent a considerable time scrutinizing and grasping tools and objects without initiating tool-use actions, when compared to healthy participants. In other words, those patients were unable to generate a mental simulation of the mechanical solution, preventing them from following any trial-and-error strategy and leading them to perform poorly and to be perplexed. These findings suggest that a so-called disorder of “volition” (i.e., perplexity) may solely be another manifestation of a disorder of ideation (i.e., impaired technical reasoning), but not an instance of loss of agency as suggested earlier. Actually, disorders of “volition” may better suit the clinical description of patients with apathy and apragmatism following damage to the frontal dorsolateral or anterior cingulate cortex, who demonstrate a dissociation between normal motor functions and loss of desire to act (e.g., Devinsky et al., 1995).
Selection of Motor or Mechanical Actions?
Selective difficulties in selecting appropriate manipulation knowledge (i.e., a disorder of selection) could be viewed as an instance of loss of agency: The patient knowing what to do (no disorder of ideation), but not how to do it (see Pazzaglia and Galli, 2014). This interpretation of patients' difficulties works relatively well if we consider that semantic knowledge supports ideation. However, we have seen earlier that this assumption is questionable. Besides, the technical-reasoning hypothesis offers an alternative idea in suggesting that patients with apraxia of tool use perform incorrect motor actions simply because they are unable to generate an appropriate representation of the correct mechanical action. In a way, the so-called disorder of selection might be not an instance of loss of agency, strictly speaking, but a manifestation of impaired technical reasoning (see below for two other manifestations). Contrary to the technical-reasoning hypothesis, the manipulation-knowledge hypothesis has not been mainly developed from real tool-use tasks, but rather from the pantomime production task (Buxbaum, 2017; Osiurak and Badets, 2017), which consists of asking patients to pretend to use a given tool. In this task, the examiner can only assess patients' motor actions, perhaps increasing the belief that the difficulty is necessarily due to a deficit for selecting the appropriate manipulation knowledge—and, as a result, a potential instance of loss of agency. However, evidence has shown that the demonstration by pantomime is a non-routine, creative task that can involve a plurality of cognitive processes (working memory, semantic memory, communicative skills, technical reasoning; Roy and Hall, 1992; Bartolo et al., 2003; Goldenberg et al., 2003; Baumard et al., 2014; Goldenberg, 2017; Lesourd et al., 2017; Finkel et al., 2018). This multi-determined nature of pantomime is also confirmed by the diversity of brain areas that can be involved in this task (left IPL, left temporal lobe; e.g., Goldenberg and Randerath, 2015; for review, see Niessen et al., 2014), whereas real tool use concerns mainly the left IPL (e.g., Goldenberg and Spatt, 2009). Besides, if demonstration by pantomime is a key task used to observe a deficit of selection and, as a result, a loss of agency, there should be a relatively narrow link between performance in pantomime tasks and sense of agency. A key study in the field did not observe such a link, showing that difficulties in a self-generated action paradigm (supposed to assess the sense of agency) can occur in patients with a perfect score of 100% in a pantomime production task (Sirigu et al., 2004). Taken together, these findings question not only the idea that the so-called disorder of selection is an instance of loss of agency but also, more generally, whether this deficit refers to a clinical reality.
Apraxia—but not of Tool Use—Can be Accompanied by Loss of Agency
To sum up, apraxia of tool use might not be accompanied by loss of agency, and the so-called manifestations of loss of agency in this syndrome might be nothing else other than the different facets of a disorder of ideation, resulting from impaired technical reasoning. This does not exclude the possibility that apraxia of tool use and loss of agency occur concomitantly because of overlap between the underlying neural substrates (fronto-parietal networks). Nevertheless, the fact that distinct, specific brain areas might be involved in each syndrome confirms the independence of the two syndromes (e.g., left IPL and particularly the supramarginal gyrus for apraxia of tool use vs. right IPL and particularly the angular gyrus for loss of agency; e.g., Farrer et al., 2008). Group studies with brain-damaged patients assessed concomitantly on the two dimensions (i.e., apraxia of tool use and sense of agency) may be particularly useful to test the independence vs. dependence of the two syndromes more directly, not only at a behavioral level but also at a neural level. Perhaps the only apraxic patients experiencing loss of agency might be those suffering from motor apraxia or alien hand sign after lesions within the superior frontal and/or parietal cortex, such as in patients with corticobasal syndrome (Zadikoff and Lang, 2005). These patients frequently and explicitly report that their hand(s) do not do what they want, corroborating a loss of control of their own motor actions (for evidence of loss of agency in this syndrome, see Wolpe et al., 2014). This is perhaps the only divergence we found with Liepmann's conception of apraxia of tool use, because, according to this conception, loss of agency—the patient knows what to do but not how to do it—is supposed to accompany ideomotor apraxia and not motor apraxia.
That being said, another potential cause of loss of agency may lie in body schema disorders. Indeed, patients who have difficulties experiencing their actions as their own may also have upstream difficulties experiencing (part of) their body as their own, which might be a sufficient and perhaps more parsimonious hypothesis in some cases. This raises issues as to the relationships between body schema and cognition. For example, patients suffering from either partial or global deafferentation following spinal cord injury may demonstrate impairments in laterality judgment tasks, not because of parietal lesions and loss of agency but presumably because of primary loss of body awareness (Ionta et al., 2016). Although the diagnosis of apraxia implies to rule out sensitive and proprioceptive deficits, these latter levels—as well as more complex sensory integration mechanisms—are not systematically tested in studies on the sense of agency. Previous works demonstrated a dissociation between sensory and proprioceptive inputs on the one hand, and perception of self-generated movements on the other hand (e.g., Sirigu et al., 1999), yet body schema is a complex, multi-level process (Sirigu et al., 1991; De Vignemont, 2009). Future research may disentangle the relative contribution of action awareness and body awareness to the performance of apraxic patients in tasks assessing the sense of agency.
Author Contributions
All authors listed have made a substantial, direct and intellectual contribution to the work, and approved it for publication.
Funding
This work was performed within the framework of the LABEX CORTEX (ANR-11-LABX-0042) of Université de Lyon, within the program Investissements d'Avenir (ANR-11- IDEX-0007) operated by the French National Research Agency (ANR).
Conflict of Interest Statement
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
References
Bartolo, A., Cubelli, R., Della Sala, S., and Drei, S. (2003). Pantomimes are special gestures which rely on working memory. Brain Cogn. 53, 483–494. doi: 10.1016/S0278-2626(03)00209-4
Baumard, J., Osiurak, F., Lesourd, M., and Le Gall, D. (2014). Tool use disorders after left brain damage. Front. Psychol. 5:473. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00473
Buxbaum, L. J. (2001). Ideomotor Apraxia: a call to action. Neurocase 7, 445–448. doi: 10.1093/neucas/7.6.445
Buxbaum, L. J. (2017). Learning, remembering, and predicting how to use tools: distributed neurocognitive mechanism. Comment on Osiurak and Badets (2016). Psychol. Rev. 124, 346–360. doi: 10.1037/rev0000051
Cubelli, R., Marchetti, C., Boscolo, G., and Della Sala, S. (2000). Cognition in action: testing a model of limb apraxia. Brain Cogn. 44, 144–165. doi: 10.1006/brcg.2000.1226
De Renzi, E. (1989). “Apraxia,” in Handbook of Neuropsychology, eds F. Boller and J. Grafman (Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers), 245–263.
De Renzi, E., and Lucchelli, F. (1988). Ideational apraxia. Brain 111, 1173–1185. doi: 10.1093/brain/111.5.1173
De Vignemont, F. (2009). Body schema and body image: pros and cons. Neuropsychologia 48, 669–680. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2009.09.022
Devinsky, O., Morrell, M. J., and Vogt, B. A. (1995). Contributions of anterior cingulate cortex to behaviour. Brain 118, 279–306. doi: 10.1093/brain/118.1.279
Farrer, C., Frey, S. H., Van Horn, J. D., Tunik, E., Turk, D., Inati, S., et al. (2008). The angular gyrus computes action awareness representations. Cereb. Cortex 18, 254–261. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhm050
Finkel, L., Hogrefe, K., Frey, S. H., Goldenberg, G., and Randerath, J. (2018). It takes two to pantomime: communication meets motor cognition. NeuroImage Clin. 19, 1008–1017. doi: 10.1016/j.nicl.2018.06.019
Geschwind, N. (1975). The apraxias: neural mechanisms of disorders of learned movement. Am. Sci. 63, 188–195.
Goldenberg, G. (2003). Apraxia and beyond: life and work of Hugo Liepmann. Cortex 39, 509–524. doi: 10.1016/S0010-9452(08)70261-2
Goldenberg, G. (2017). Facets of pantomime. J. Int. Neuropsychol. Soc. 23, 121–127. doi: 10.1017/S1355617716000989
Goldenberg, G., and Hagmann, S. (1998). Tool use and mechanical problem solving in apraxia. Neuropsychologia 36, 581–589. doi: 10.1016/S0028-3932(97)00165-6
Goldenberg, G., Hartmann, K., and Schlott, I. (2003). Defective pantomime of object use in left brain damage: apraxia or asymbolia? Neuropsychologia 41, 1565–1573. doi: 10.1016/S0028-3932(03)00120-9
Goldenberg, G., and Randerath, J. (2015). Shared neural substrates of apraxia and aphasia. Neuropsychologia 75, 40–49. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2015.05.017
Goldenberg, G., and Spatt, J. (2009). The neural basis of tool use. Brain 132, 1645–1655. doi: 10.1093/brain/awp080
Haggard, P., and Chambon, V. (2012). Sense of agency. Curr. Biol. 22, R390–R392. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2012.02.040
Heilman, K. M., Rothi, L. J., and Valenstein, E. (1982). Two forms of ideomotor apraxia. Neurology 32, 342–346. doi: 10.1212/WNL.32.4.342
Ionta, S., Villiger, M., Jutzeler, C. R., Freund, P., Curt, A., and Gassert, R. (2016). Spinal cord injury affects the interplay between visual and sensorimotor representations of the body. Sci. Rep. 6:20144. doi: 10.1038/srep20144
Lesourd, M., Baumard, J., Jarry, C., Etcharry-Bouyx, F., Belliard, S., Moreaud, O., et al. (2017). Rethinking the cognitive mechanisms underlying pantomime of tool use: evidence from Alzheimer's disease and semantic dementia. J. Int. Neuropsychol. Soc. 23, 128–138. doi: 10.1017/S1355617716000618
Negri, G. A., Lunardelli, A., Reverberi, C., Gigli, G. L., and Rumiati, R. I. (2007). Degraded semantic knowledge and accurate object use. Cortex 43, 376–388. doi: 10.1016/S0010-9452(08)70463-5
Niessen, E., Fink, G. R., and Weiss, P. H. (2014). Apraxia, pantomime and the parietal cortex. NeuroImage Clin. 5, 42–52. doi: 10.1016/j.nicl.2014.05.017
Osiurak, F., and Badets, A. (2016). Tool use and affordance: manipulation-based versus reasoning-based approaches. Psychol. Rev. 123, 534–568. doi: 10.1037/rev0000027
Osiurak, F., and Badets, A. (2017). Use of tools and misuse of embodied cognition: reply to Buxbaum (2017). Psychol. Rev. 124, 361–368. doi: 10.1037/rev0000065
Osiurak, F., and Heinke, D. (2018). Looking for Intoolligence: a unified framework for the cognitive study of human tool use and technology. Am. Psychol. 73, 169–185. doi: 10.1037/amp0000162
Osiurak, F., Jarry, C., and Le Gall, D. (2010). Grasping the affordances, understanding the reasoning: toward a dialectical theory of human tool use. Psychol. Rev. 117, 517–540. doi: 10.1037/a0019004
Osiurak, F., Jarry, C., and Le Gall, D. (2011). Re-examining the gesture engram hypothesis: new perspectives on apraxia of tool use. Neuropsychologia 49, 299–312. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.12.041
Osiurak, F., Jarry, C., Lesourd, M., Baumard, J., and Le Gall, D. (2013). Mechanical problem-solving in left brain-damaged patients and apraxia of tool use. Neuropsychologia 51, 1964–1972. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2013.06.017
Osiurak, F., and Rossetti, Y. (2017). Definition: limb apraxia. Cortex 93:228. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2017.03.010
Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: a conceptual framework. Cognition 107, 179–217. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2007.09.003
Pazzaglia, M., and Galli, G. (2014). Loss of agency in apraxia. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8:751. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00751
Reynaud, E., Lesourd, M., Navarro, J., and Osiurak, F. (2016). On the neurocognitive origins of human tool use. A critical review of neuroimaging data. Neurosci. BioBehav. Rev. 64, 421–437. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2016.03.009
Rothi, L. J. G., Ochipa, C., and Heilman, K. M. (1991). A cognitive neuropsychological model of limb praxis. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 8, 443–458. doi: 10.1080/02643299108253382
Roy, E. A., and Hall, C. (1992). “Limb apraxia: a process approach,” in Vision and Motor Control, eds P. Luc and E. Digby (Amsterdam:Elsevier), 261–282. doi: 10.1016/S0166-4115(08)62018-X
Silveri, M. C., and Ciccarelli, N. (2009). Semantic memory in object use. Neuropsychologia 47, 2634–2641. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2009.05.013
Sirigu, A., Daprati, E., Buxbaum, L. J., Giraux, P., and Pradat-Diehl, P. (2003). “How the human brain represents manual gestures: effect of brain damage,” in Taking Action: Cognitive Neuroscience Perspectives on Intentional Acts, ed S. H. Johnson- Frey (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 167–183.
Sirigu, A., Daprati, E., Ciancia, S., Giraux, P., Nighoghossian, N., Posada, A., et al. (2004). Altered awareness of voluntary action after damage to the parietal cortex. Nat. Neurosci. 7, 80–84. doi: 10.1038/nn1160
Sirigu, A., Daprati, E., Pradat-Diehl, P., Franck, N., and Jeannerod, M. (1999). Perception of self-generated movement following left parietal lesion. Brain 122, 1867–1874. doi: 10.1093/brain/122.10.1867
Sirigu, A., Grafman, J., Bressler, K., and Sunderland, T. (1991). Multiple representations contribute to body knowledge processing: evidence from a case of autotopoagnosia. Brain 114, 629–642. doi: 10.1093/brain/114.1.629
van Elk, M., van Schie, H., and Bekkering, H. (2014). Action semantics: a unifying conceptual framework for the selective use of multimodal and modality-specific object knowledge. Phys. Life Rev. 11, 220–250. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2013.11.005
Wolpe, N., Moore, J. W., Rae, C. L., Rittman, T., Altena, E., Haggard, P., et al. (2014). The medial frontal-prefrontal network for altered awareness and control of action in corticobasal syndrome. Brain 137, 208–220. doi: 10.1093/brain/awt302
Keywords: apraxia, motor action, sense of agency, technical reasoning, tool use
Citation: Osiurak F, Lesourd M, Rossetti Y and Baumard J (2019) Is There Really a Loss of Agency in Patients With Apraxia of Tool Use? Front. Psychol. 10:87. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00087
Received: 26 November 2018; Accepted: 11 January 2019;
Published: 05 February 2019.
Edited by:
Dermot Lynott, Lancaster University, United KingdomReviewed by:
Georg Goldenberg, Städtisches Klinikum München, GermanyCopyright © 2019 Osiurak, Lesourd, Rossetti and Baumard. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: François Osiurak, francois.osiurak@univ-lyon2.fr