Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Psychol., 04 September 2018
Sec. Cognition
This article is part of the Research Topic Judgment and Decision Making Under Uncertainty: Descriptive, Normative, and Prescriptive Perspectives View all 18 articles

The Psychology of Uncertainty and Three-Valued Truth Tables

  • 1CHArt (P-A-R-I-S), Université Paris 8 & EPHE, Paris, France
  • 2Institut Jean Nicod, École Normale Supérieure, Paris, France
  • 3Psychology Department, Durham University, Durham, United Kingdom
  • 4School of Science and Engineering, Tokyo Denki University, Tokyo, Japan

Psychological research on people's understanding of natural language connectives has traditionally used truth table tasks, in which participants evaluate the truth or falsity of a compound sentence given the truth or falsity of its components in the framework of propositional logic. One perplexing result concerned the indicative conditional if A then C which was often evaluated as true when A and C are true, false when A is true and C is false but irrelevant“ (devoid of value) when A is false (whatever the value of C). This was called the “psychological defective table of the conditional.” Here we show that far from being anomalous the “defective” table pattern reveals a coherent semantics for the basic connectives of natural language in a trivalent framework. This was done by establishing participants' truth tables for negation, conjunction, disjunction, conditional, and biconditional, when they were presented with statements that could be certainly true, certainly false, or neither. We review systems of three-valued tables from logic, linguistics, foundations of quantum mechanics, philosophical logic, and artificial intelligence, to see whether one of these systems adequately describes people's interpretations of natural language connectives. We find that de Finetti's (1936/1995) three-valued system is the best approximation to participants' truth tables.

Introduction: The Bayesian Approach to the Psychology of Reasoning

From the beginning of their investigations, and for nearly a century, psychologists studying human deductive reasoning considered bi-valued logic as the sole frame of reference. Their early inspiration was limited to Aristotelian syllogistic (Binet, 1902; James, 1908) but in the 1950s Piaget adopted propositional logic which he assumed to be the basis of adults' cognitive functioning (Inhelder and Piaget, 1958). The elementary connectives of natural language for negation, conjunction and disjunction were identified with the logical connectives ¬, ∧, and ∨, respectively, and the indicative conditional if A (antecedent), then C (consequent) was identified with the material conditional (or implication A⊃ C). However, in 1966, Wason observed that when people are required to make judgments about conditionals in terms of true and false, they often produce a table that differs from the material conditional. Participants consider that a conditional if A then C is made “true” by the A and C state of affairs and made “false” by the A and not-C state, but that the not-A cases (not-A and C and not-A and not-C) are “irrelevant” to the truth value of if A then C. Psychologists came to call this truth table “defective” to underscore participants' apparent imperfect comprehension of the material conditional which was assumed to be the meaning of if … then. This “defective” conditional is represented in Table 1 (column 1) as C|dA. Wason's (1966) observation was confirmed by early experimental studies in which part of the participants required to choose or construct the states of affairs that make the sentence true or false disregard the not-A states (Evans, 1972) or choose the option irrelevant when it is offered to them (Johnson-Laird and Tagart, 1969), or spontaneously express the irrelevance of these cases (Delval and Riviére, 1975; Politzer, 1981). Whatever this table is called, it should be contrasted with the truth table for the material conditional which is true in the not-A cases (see Table 1, column 2). In addition, a “defective” biconditional (denoted by C‖dA in Table 1, column 3) has also been observed (Delval and Riviére, 1975). It is made true by the A and C state of affairs, and made false by the A and not-C and not-A and C states, with the not-A and not-C state alone “irrelevant” (see Evans and Over, 2004, for further research on the “defective” conditional and biconditional truth tables in psychology).

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. The different truth tables for the conditional if A then C: two-valued (columns 1–3′) and three-valued (columns 4–7).

Until the end of the century, the major part of the theoretical debate on deduction in cognitive psychology revolved around the format of representation of the connectives. For one stream of research the representation was assumed to be syntactic and deduction rule-governed (Rips, 1994; Braine and O'Brien, 1998) whereas for another stream it was assumed to be semantic and deduction model-based (Johnson-Laird and Byrne, 1991). Whatever the option may be, the frame of reference was still two-valued logic and the explanation of the defective table was a major item on the agenda. However, in recent years, this old model of reference has been questioned and a new approach using a probabilistic frame of reference has emerged. This new paradigm in the psychology of reasoning emphasizes that most human inferences take place when there is some degree of uncertainty about the subject matter (Oaksford and Chater, 2007, 2009; Over, 2009, 2016; Pfeifer and Kleiter, 2010; Evans, 2012; Elqayam and Over, 2013; Pfeifer, 2013; Baratgin et al., 2015; Baratgin and Politzer, 2016; Over and Baratgin, 2017; Over and Cruz, 2018). This uncertainty is found in both everyday thought and scientific inference, when people are trying to decide what they will most enjoy on a lunch menu, or to infer what has caused an outbreak of food poisoning.

This new Bayesian approach to the psychology of reasoning has received great impetus from two sets of experimental findings. The first finding is that, as claimed by the theory, people generally judge the probability of the indicative conditional, P(if A then C), to be the conditional probability of C given A, P(C|A) (for early data see: Evans et al., 2003, 2007; Oberauer and Wilhelm, 2003, but see also Douven and Verbrugge, 2010; Vidal and Baratgin, 2017). The second finding is that participants' assessments of the conclusions of explicit deductive inferences made under uncertainty tend to be in the coherence intervals determined by the probability of the premises, that is, participants tend to conform to the laws of probability (Pfeifer and Kleiter, 2009, 2010, 2011; Pfeifer, 2014; Singmann et al., 2014; Cruz et al., 2015; Evans et al., 2015; Politzer and Baratgin, 2016).

An important target of the new Bayesian paradigm concerns the “defective” table mentioned earlier. Supporters of the new paradigm consider that far from being anomalous it reveals a semantics that differs from the material conditional (Baratgin et al., 2013, 2014)1. This point will be developed below and generalized to the basic connectives of natural language (negation, conjunction, disjunction) and also to the biconditional.

The de Finettian Approach

Is there a normative framework for unifying all these experimental results? We have argued (Baratgin, 2015; Baratgin and Politzer, 2016; Over and Baratgin, 2017; Over and Cruz, 2018) that de Finetti's Bayesian subjective theory offers just such a framework. De Finetti is one of the founding fathers of modern probability theory, and the most prominent representative of subjective Bayesianism. His overall approach to probability (de Finetti, 1974) has deep psychological relevance (see Baratgin and Politzer, 2006, 2007; Baratgin, 2015, for a discussion in the field of the psychology of probability judgment). His conception of probability as subjective degree of belief, and of the assessment of probability through the well-known betting procedure, are rooted in psychological reflection.

de Finetti (1980) proposed three levels of knowledge of an event. The objective level, Level 0, corresponds to binary logic, in which every statement that expresses the occurrence or the non-occurrence of an event is objectively true or false. This is the level of events that are known for sure. It is this level that was traditionally studied in the psychology literature of reasoning, even though it is severely limited for a psychological approach, for people often do not know for sure what is true and what is false. It is also, ironically, the level of which de Finetti (2006, p. 113) says that it is “sterile” because logic has no other use than order, enumerate, and expound what is already known. A purely logical science cannot be concerned in forecasting. Hence the need to substitute this “rigid logic” with a ”logic of the probable“ that is the logic of everyday allowing to make predictions with regard to uncertain knowledge (de Finetti, 1977/1993, p. 494).

Beyond Level 0, de Finetti (1980) considered two other levels that are subjective. On Level 1, the event (or statement) concerns a specific object defined by its own characteristics known to the individual. An event is always conditioned on the individual's personal state of knowledge. The statements can be classified as having one of three values: true, characterizing an expected event that has happened; false, characterizing an expected event that has not happened; and uncertain. The value uncertain is to be understood as follows. It represents the subjective point of view of an individual who is wondering whether or not an event will happen or, equivalently, whether the statement that expresses the occurrence of the event is true or false. The third value reflects a transitory state of ignorance (at a given time) until the statement is verified or falsified. Until this takes place, it is impossible to give it a truth value. Even though he did not vary in this conception of the third value, he used various terms to designate it; his favorite expression was “void” (e. g., de Finetti, 1967, 1974, 1995/2008) which we will adopt and will denote by “∅”.

To formalize these notions, de Finetti (1936/1995, 1967, 1974, 1995/2008, 2006) defined a three-valued system that uses the third value void and is superimposed on a two-valued logic that uses true and false. We describe below the three-valued truth tables that define this system, specifying how these values are propagated for the usual connectives.

The second epistemic level in de Finetti (1980), Level 2, is a development of the first level. At this level, the initially non-numerical degrees of belief are finally expressed as numerical probability judgments. People are seldom fully ignorant about an event. They have expectations, make subjective probability judgments, engage in wagers, etc. This level corresponds to the full range of subjective degrees of belief about events where the initial ignorance and the ensuing uncertainty give way to the expression of additive probabilities. Fine distinctions are thus possible at Level 2, which is of psychological importance, since both ordinary people and scientists do often distinguish between events that are uncertain, judging some as more probable than others conditionally on their personal state of knowledge (Baratgin, 2015).

A substantial amount of research on uncertain reasoning has been carried out at Level 2—in fact most of the work mentioned above on the probability of conditionals or deduction under uncertainty. Hardly any research has been done to investigate Level 1 (with the exception of Baratgin et al., 2013, considered below). Level 1 should support and lead up to Level 2, and yet most contemporary theorists in the de Finetti tradition have concerned themselves with a much more refined and expressive system at Level 2 in which the third value for if A then C is specified by the conditional probability itself, P(C|A), and the logical values true and false are replaced with 1 and 0 (Gilio, 1990; Jeffrey, 1991; Coletti and Scozzafava, 2002; Pfeifer and Kleiter, 2009). As Baratgin et al. (2013) point out, Level 2 removes some anomalies in Level 1, for people are never ignorant of trivial tautologies, such as if A & C then A and A or not-A (Over and Baratgin, 2017). But people do not always, and could not always, make such fine-grained evaluations of Level 2. They can, however, simply express their ignorance, or in other words, can remain at the transitory level 1. In summary, there is a gap to fill. De Finetti's theory has gained much experimental support at Level 2, but the question of its descriptive adequacy at Level 1 is open. The present paper addresses this question in several experiments, our aim being to test the descriptive adequacy, for ordinary people's judgments, of de Finetti's Level 1 in his overall theory of subjective probability. For half a century research in the psychology of reasoning has produced robust results on the comprehension of the connectives of propositional logic. People's performance indicates that they possess negation and conjunction, and to a lesser extent, disjunction (Manktelow, 2012) but their comprehension of the material conditional and biconditional is “defective,” in the sense mentioned above. However, these studies were limited to the framework of classical bi-valued logic. The change of conceptual framework brought about by the Finettian theory necessitates that these studies be carried out with a tri-valued logic. The present study applies itself to refine and reinterpret the old results.

We now turn to the analysis of de Finetti's three-valued system in some detail. We begin with focusing on the conditional, which leads us to the concept of conditional event (or tri-event). A conditional event is defined by de Finetti (1936/1995) as a logical entity that is true when the antecedent A and the consequent C are true; false when A is true and C false; and void in the sense introduced above when A is false. The conditional event is closely analogous to a conditional bet, which is won in the first case, lost in the second case, and called off in the third case, when it is “void” and no one wins or loses (see Politzer et al., 2010, on this analogy and the relation to Ramsey, 1926/1990, 1929/1990). So, at Level 1, the betting interpretation helps illustrate the void case2.

It now appears that the empirical “defective” table for the conditional should be called the “2 × 2 de Finetti table” (and similarly for the “defective” biconditional) to avoid the negative term “defective” (Milne, 2012; Baratgin et al., 2013, 2014; Nakamura and Kawaguchi, 2016). Notice (Table 1) that in columns 1 and 3 the empirical “defective” table bears a symbol ”I“ (for irrelevant), whereas in column 1′ and 3′ the 2 × 2 de Finetti tables bear the symbol “∅” (for void). This point deserves explication. The 2 × 2 “defective” table in column 1 (Table 1) describes the psychological observation that participants judge that the states of affairs in which the antecedent is false do not allow to evaluate the conditional sentence in terms of true or false. Participants say that the sentence is neither true nor false, or that it may be true or false, or that one cannot know, and the term “irrelevant” (readily endorsed by participants) was coined by psychologists to express participants' perplexity about the truth value of the sentence. In other words, “irrelevant” and “void” refer to the same state of ignorance, the former being empirically-based and descriptive, and the latter theoretical.

The next step is to take into account the ignorance that can affect elementary events, considering that they, too, can be true, false or void (because for de Finetti all events are conditional), leading to a three-valued (3 × 3) truth table for the conditional event (denoted by C|FiA in Table 1, column 5) which de Finetti (1936/1995) called ”subordination“. Similarly, he defined three-valued truth tables for the ordinary connectives (negation, conjunction, disjunction, see below). This set of truth tables which we will call “3 × 3 de Finetti tables” constitutes de Finetti's Level 1 system, abbreviated to Fi.

Traditional psychological experiments on the “defective” table were limited by the fact that the antecedent A and consequent C of the conditional did not have the third value, but de Finetti's 3 × 3 table, while encompassing the 2 × 2 de Finetti table, allows A and C to have the third value. In brief, we can find in the 3 × 3 de Finetti tables an answer to the question of what value does if A then C have when A or C have the third value (even though this was not his main objective). Of course, because the 3 × 3 table incorporates the 2 × 2 table, it keeps answering the question of what value does if A then C have when A is false: it is void. Note that void defined by a state of ignorance (as well as irrelevant expressed by participants in psychological experiments) is not a truth value homogeneous with true and false; rather, it is a meta-evaluation (for an analysis of this point, see Dubois and Prade, 2001; Dubois, 2008). It is in this sense that the 3 × 3 logic is superimposed on the 2 × 2 logic.

The conditional is so important that Baratgin et al. (2013) initially focused on it in their experimental study of three-valued tables. They observed that almost 60% of participants who gave responses in agreement with de Finetti's 2 × 2 table expanded it to produce de Finetti's full 3 × 3 conditional event table, when evaluating indicative conditionals and conditional bets. This is the first result supporting de Finetti's Level 1 system, but it is limited. Extending it to the other connectives of the system would demonstrate its descriptive adequacy, that is, provide a semantic theory of the interpretation of natural language connectives under uncertainty. This is the objective of the present paper. But before proceeding to the experiments, we should make some theoretical and methodological points. There exist many three-valued logical systems (for reviews, see Rescher, 1969; Haack, 1974; Gottwald, 2015). Some of them appeared before de Finetti, and many more have appeared in cognitive science since then. Psychologists of reasoning have so far done little to study whether any of these tables matches the judgments of ordinary people when they are in a state of ignorance about what is true and what is false (but see Elqayam, 2006, on “liar” paradoxes)3. Some of these systems propose a conditional table encompassing the 2 × 2 de Finetti table and so constitute possible alternative theories to de Finetti's Level 1 system, Fi. We give a short overview of these systems in the next section. See Appendix A (Supplementary Material) for a more detailed description, and Appendix B (Supplementary Material) for a presentation of the authors' individual reasons for developing their systems.

Nine Systems of Three-Valued Tables

An Extension of 2 × 2 Bi-Valued Tables

In addition to de Finetti's (1936/1995) 3 × 3 table for the conditional event, there exist numerous other possibilities to build a 3 × 3 table to represent the indicative conditional of natural language, which we will call the natural conditional. Consider column 4 in Table 1 in which C|?A represents a general 3 × 3 conditional table for this natural conditional. Here A and C can be true (“T”), false (“F”), or judged to be neither. After lines 1, 3, 7, and 9 have been filled in with the values of the “defective” table, there remain five cells marked with “?.” The basic question is: what value should be in the place of each “?” to represent the natural conditional? There are 243 possible ways (35), in theory, of completing this conditional table. The same question is also posed for the other connectives. Among the existing three-valued logics we have found only nine three-valued systems that extend the 2 × 2 de Finetti table for the conditional and that also propose 3 × 3 tables that extend standard two-valued logic for the conjunction and disjunction connectives. By “extending,” we mean 3 × 3 tables that have the same true or false values as their 2 × 2 counterpart in lines 1, 3, 7, and 9 mentioned above. Looking for such extensions is motivated by the experimental evidence that the classical 2 × 2 conjunction and disjunction truth tables are produced by a majority of people (Manktelow, 2012).

These nine systems of three-valued tables originate from the work of logicians, linguists, philosophers, and artificial intelligence researchers, who had different theoretical interests and approaches. As we will see in section Interpreting the Connectives and Appendix B (Supplementary Material), this is most evident in their interpretation of the third value. Some of these systems were not originally intended to represent an intuitive sense of uncertainty, which de Finetti aimed to capture (Baratgin and Politzer, 2016), but even so, they do have some prima facie interest for psychological modeling, simply because they extend the traditional 2 × 2 tables of two-valued logic to three-valued systems. Three-valued judgments have long been found in truth table studies of the conditional in psychological research, as we have described.

In summary, there are four basic connectives (negation, conditional, conjunction, disjunction). Three types of conditional (see Table 1, columns 5, 6, and 7) and four types of conjunction and disjunction (see Appendix A, Table A.2 in Supplementary Material) constitute the differential building blocks of the nine three-valued systems: as displayed in Appendix A, Table A.3 (Supplementary Material), each system is defined by using the involutive negation and by selecting one type of connective among the other three basic connectives4. A short reminder on the origins of three-valued logic is given in Appendix B (Supplementary material), followed by the origins of the nine “extended” systems [numbered (1)–(9)].

Interpreting the Connectives

The different truth tables for the connectives in Table 1 and Tables A.1, A.2, A.5 (Supplementary Material) may appear somewhat formal, and so we give a brief informal overview of how they differ from each other. We begin with the conditional if A, then C.

Recall that six systems, (1)–(6) in Appendix B (Supplementary Material), adopt the Fi conditional and so share the notion that a conditional with a false antecedent takes on the value ∅. Indeed, we have already seen through the betting schema that, whenever the antecedent A is not known to be true (∅ or F), the Fi conditional takes on the value ∅. In addition, a conditional sentence whose antecedent is true takes on the truth value of its consequent.

What distinguishes the Fi conditional from the other two conditionals, in columns 6 and 7 of Table 1, appears precisely for the value ∅ of the antecedent in lines 4 and 6. Two of the nine systems, (8) and (9) in Appendix B (Supplementary Material), use the Cooper conditional. For this conditional, with a truth-value gap ∅ (denoted by G for gap by Cooper) for the antecedent, the conditional takes on the value of the consequent, which is also the case when the antecedent is T. This captures the notion that the conditional has the same value with a ∅ antecedent as it has with a T antecedent. Only when the antecedent is F is the conditional ∅ whatever the value of the consequent. The Farrell conditional, (7) in Appendix B (Supplementary Material), differs in that it adopts a slightly more cautious evaluation: When the antecedent has a truth-value gap ∅ (denoted by I for ignorance by Farrell) and the consequent is T the conditional is not T but ∅ (Table 1, column 6). Note that both concur in holding the conditional to be F when the antecedent is ∅ and the consequent F. How this differs with Fi can be exemplified as follows. Suppose it is unknown whether this chip is square, while it is false that this chip is black. Then to evaluate if this chip is square, then it is black, some theorists (like Farrell and Cooper) may have the intuition that it is “false,” whereas others (like de Finetti) may have the intuition that the value is “void”5.

We can further examine the differences between systems by comparing the four types of conjunction and disjunction on which they are based that we have identified, viz., KLH, B, S, and M [defined in Appendix A (Supplementary Material)]. Most proposed systems (like Fi) in Appendix B (Supplementary Material) have truth-value gaps and consequently differ from three-valued systems proper in which the third value is homogeneous with the values T and F to which it can be compared using a relation of order. Most authors define an order between the truth-value gap and T and F. In de Finetti's framework, the truth-value gap is viewed as intermediate between F and T. Mura (in de Finetti, 1995/2008) gives a pragmatic justification with the bet schema: the payoff of a void bet is clearly intermediate between the payoff of a bet that is lost and a bet that is won (for more technical justification, see Hailperin, 1996; Milne, 1997, 2004; Blamey, 2001; Mura, 2016). It is exactly the order of KLH connectives. Conjunction obeys the following principle: the three values are formally put in an order denoted by F ≤ ∅ ≤ T (Dubois and Prade, 1994); then, whenever two sentences are connected, the value of the conjunction is the minimum of their values, that is, the conjunction gets the “weaker” value. Consider a context of chips of different shapes and colors. With the interpretation of ∅ as a truth-value gap resulting from ignorance, take a true sentence, for instance the chip is square (T), and suppose one is ignorant whether the chip is black (∅); then the conjunction the chip is square and it is black is evaluated as ∅ because min(T, ∅) = ∅. Suppose now the chip is square to be false; then the conjunction the chip is square and it is black is evaluated as F because min(F, ∅) = F. Similar considerations obtain for disjunction, mutatis mutandis. Here the value of the connection is defined by the maximum values of the disjuncts. If it is known to be true that the chip is square (T) and one is ignorant whether the chip is black (∅), then the chip is square or it is black will be evaluated as true because max(T, ∅) = T.

The various conjunctions obey the min order but they have their own formal order for the three values, which in fact differentiates them from each other. The same obtains for the disjunctions with the max order. We will not review them in detail, but will have a look at what the choice of an order intuitively means. Take Bochvar's (1938/1981) conjunction ∧B. Its order is ∅ < F < T. This means that whenever a sentence with the third value is connected (conjunctively) with another sentence whatever its value, the third value prevails and “contaminates” the conjunction. Similarly for disjunction ∨S, the order corresponds to F < T < ∅. For instance, with a third value interpreted as of no interest, the sentence the chip is square being true or false and the chip is black being of no interest, the sentence the chip is square or it is black will be evaluated as being of no interest in each case. The situation is opposite for the Sobocinsky connectives where the orders are F < T < ∅ for conjunction and ∅ < F < T for disjunction, resulting in connections that appear to be “immune” to the third value as the other values absorb it. With the previous example, the disjunction will be evaluated as T in the first case and F in the second one.

Finally, consider involutive negation, which all the systems share. T is negated by F and F by T like in two-valued logic. Negating the third truth value by itself captures the intuition that one cannot consider a sentence that is not ∅ as T any more than consider it as F, so that it remains ∅.

Prima facie all the nine systems, irrespective of their origins and motivations, provide candidates for three-valued tables relevant to the psychological modeling of people's comprehension of connectives under uncertainty. They accommodate and extend the 2 × 2 de Finetti table for the conditional, which is supported by earlier psychological research, as we have explained. Most of the systems above are directly relevant to psychologists, especially those motivated by linguistic considerations and the inappropriateness of the material conditional to represent people's interpretation of the natural language conditional (such as BFM, etc., defined in Appendix A (Supplementary Material). Clearly, an empirical investigation is necessary to decide which of these three-valued systems best fits ordinary people's judgments about natural language connectives. We present several experiments that aim to answer this question by examining people's truth tables for negation, conjunction, disjunction, the conditional, and the biconditional. More strongly, we ask whether the tables closest to people's judgments belong to one system in the literature. For all the reasons detailed in section The de Finettian Approach, and in view of the results we have already obtained for the conditional, we consider de Finetti's Level 1 system as the most serious contender. Recall that it is characterized by the Fi conditional and the KLH conjunction and disjunction.

Experiments: The Finettian and Other Three-Valued Systems

Method

Participants

In Experiment 1 (N = 54) and Experiment 2 (N = 101), participants were French native speakers. They were students at the University Paris 8 who volunteered for the experiments. They already held a degree and were resuming their studies in a remote teaching program in the social sciences. They had no specific background in logic or probability theory. In Experiment 3, participants were 58 undergraduate Japanese native speaker students enrolled in a computer programming class at the Tokyo Denki University. All were naive to the purposes of the study. Experiments 1 and 2 were administered on a computer screen and Experiment 3 was presented in a booklet. An online informed consent was obtained from all participants. This study was carried out in accordance with the recommendations of the APA ethical principles and code of conduct and was approved by the ethics committee of Laboratoire Cognitions Humaine et Artificielle (EA 4004–CHArt), Université Paris 8, France.

Materials

In Experiment 1 and 2 the same material was used. Participants were presented with sentences that referred to a chip that could be in one of two colors, black or white, and one of two shapes, square or round. The task was to judge whether the sentences were true, false, or neither. There were different conditions of visibility. In one condition, the chip was seen through a transparent window, making it clearly true whether the chip was square, or round, and similarly making it clearly true whether the chip was black or white. In another condition of visibility, the chip was seen through a device that made it visually impossible to know whether the chip was square or round. And in a third condition of visibility, the chip was seen through a filter making it visually impossible to know whether the chip was black or white. And finally the chip could be seen through both the device and the filter, making both the shape and the color impossible to identify. This technique allowed us to fill up the nine cells of a three-valued truth table with the participants' responses (see Figure 1).

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. The presentation of the game in Experiments 1 and 2.

In the third experiment (Japanese participants), an isomorphic material with pictures of round or pointed chips that could be blue or red was used (Figure 2).

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. The presentation of the game in Experiment 3.

Design and Procedure

In the three experiments, participants were required to judge the truth value of the sentence under consideration for the nine combinations corresponding to the nine cells of the truth table (see Figure 3).

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. The nine possible combinations of photographs (Experiments 1 and 2) or pictures (Experiment 3) corresponding to the nine cells of the three-valued truth table.

For the three experiments the combinations were presented in a random order and each one was accompanied by three response options: certainly true, certainly false, neither true nor false. The participants were required to select one option (see an example in Figure 4 for the conjunction).

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. Example of a trial (one logical combination) for conjunction. The first conjunct has the third value ∅ and the second conjunct is false.

The choice of the adverb “certainly” reflects the Finettian notion that when an event is known to have occurred or not to have occurred, this is known with certainty, and so the truth or falsity of the proposition that expresses it is certain. Besides, this should avoid possible common fuzzy interpretations of “true” and “false” such as “very likely to be true/false.” This wording has already been used for the same purpose in the context of research on the framing effect (Mandel, 2014).

The choice of the wording neither true nor false for the third option was made for several reasons. First it should be as close as possible to de Finetti's conception and formulation of the third value. This third value (or void, as de Finetti often called it) is the evaluation made by an individual who is not in a position to know whether an event is true or false. Commenting on the tri-event, de Finetti explicitly states that the third value is to be regarded as neither true nor false: ”Whenever the condition B is satisfied, then A|B is either true or false (1 or 0). But unless the condition B is satisfied, one can neither say that the event A|B is true, nor that the event A|B is false. It is void or null in the sense that the premise under which it is considered either true or false no longer holds. In my opinion, these three cases should be treated as distinct“ (de Finetti, 1995/2008, p. 170).

Second, it should capture participants' natural evaluations, that is, with as little suggestion as possible. In principle, the third option could be “true or false” (or some equivalent expression such as “It could be true or it could be false.” This option is correct (and trivial) from a logician's objective point of view. But it does not readily accommodate subjective judgments, in particular those generated by three-valued systems (see the various and subtly different interpretations of the third value in section Interpreting the Connectives). By parity of argument, it might be objected that “neither true nor false” cannot accommodate the choice of “true or false” because it is incompatible with it. This is correct, but pragmatically rejecting the assertions that the sentence is true and that it is false gives rise to the assertion that it is neither. More precisely, participants who do not find an assertable option are led to interpret the third option as a means to express just this (and to disregard the logical triviality in case it had come to their mind). The judgment that neither “true” nor “false” are adequate options induces the judgment that “neither true nor false” is adequate, which turns the third option into a meta-option equivalent to “other” that cannot be put on the same level as “true,” “false,” and “true or false.”

Third, the format should be common to all the connectives. For the conditional in particular, it should be possible for participants to express a judgment such as “void” or “irrelevant” without any suggestion, which the “neither” option satisfies. Note that the first constraint above is exemplified with the conditional which theoretically returns the value void in case its antecedent is not known to be true, but the other connectives also have logical cases of voidness for which the option “neither” is appropriate for the same reasons. In brief, the aim of the third option is to capture the judgment that neither the first option nor the second is adequate, in the spirit of de Finetti, without influencing the participants, while being applicable to the various connectives, and the formulation adopted does just that.

In Experiment 1, each participant was asked to judge the truth value of a negated sentence (e.g., the chip is not square when the shape of the chip presented could be square or round or indeterminate, and the color black, white or indeterminate), hence nine presentations (or “trials”). Participants were randomly allocated to one of the two statements, the chip is not square and the chip is not black.

In Experiment 2, each participant received four sentences: first the simple affirmation, The chip is a square to familiarize them with the task. This was followed by a conjunction, The chip is square and black; then there were two sentences presented in a counter-balanced order: a disjunction disambiguated by “or both” written in parentheses, The chip is square or black (or both)6, and a conditional, If the chip is square, then it is black. The conditional will not be detailed here (for the results, see Baratgin et al., 2013).

In Experiment 3 (Japanese sample), each participant received four sentences, in this order: the simple affirmation, The chip is red, the conjunction, The chip is round and red, the conditional, If the chip is round, then it is red, and the biconditional, If the chip is round, then it is red, and if it is red, then it is round. The original sentences in French and Japanese can be found in Appendix C (Supplementary Material).

Results

Method of Analysis

The tables produced by participants will be analyzed in two stages. The first stage casts the results in terms of the traditional two-valued classification. That is, we restrict the analysis of the answers to the four “old” cells of the traditional table that correspond to the four cases where the antecedent and the consequent are either true or false. This allows the identification of a 4-cell truth table for each connective and each participant (and a 2-cell truth table in the case of negation). In this way, we take up the classic 2 × 2 tables before extending them into new 3 × 3 tables.

In the second stage of the analysis, we further characterize the tables by considering all nine cells (and all three cells for negation). Then the observed three-valued tables are compared with the relevant three-valued formal tables of the nine systems.

The First Stage Analysis

Table 2 displays for each connective the frequency distribution of the interpretations (the tables produced) in percent. To answer the research question, we were basically interested in the identification of the modal response, that is, we were looking for a dominant interpretation belonging to the same system across connectives. In each of the first three columns there is one modal response >70% (close or equal to 100% in the first three columns), that is, a clearly dominant response appears. However, in the last two columns (conditional and biconditional) the modal response is not so high. To identify this modal response as a reliable dominant interpretation, a 95% confidence interval for proportions (based on z values) was calculated (rounded to the closest unit) for all percentages >10%. Confidence intervals will also be given for the second stage analysis.

TABLE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. First stage analysis.

For negation (experiment 1), all participants answered in agreement with the two-valued truth table of negation.

For the conjunctive statement, 98% of the participants in Experiment 2 as well as in Experiment 3 respected the conjunction table.

For the disjunctive statement 73.3% respected the disjunction table. These rates correspond to the traditional rate of response presented in the literature. In particular, the review made by Evans et al. (1993) for disjunction shows that the true-false combinations are evaluated as false between 10 and 28% of the time, indicating a conjunctive interpretation. Similarly, virtually all of the 27 participants who did not respect the standard truth table answered false to the true-false combinations, either on one occasion (20) or on both (6). This means that these participants had difficulty processing disjunction and had a tendency to construe it as a conjunction in line with the classic results, and that their error was not due to having trouble with the uncertain cases or with the response format, that is, with the three-valued system. Finally, there was no case of exclusive interpretation, indicating that the disambiguation by “or both” was effective.

For the conditional statement, the two main tables produced by Japanese participants of Experiment 3 correspond to the usual “defective” conditional (37.9%) and conjunction tables (22.4%). These frequencies are comparable to Baratgin et al. (2013) French data. The only notable difference is that the frequency of the biconditional table which was virtually null now reaches 15.5%.

For the biconditional statement, the dominant interpretation is the 2 × 2 de Finetti table (50%), followed by the material biconditional table (25.9%) and the conjunction table (20.7%).

The Second Stage Analysis

We consider all nine cells of the observed truth tables. Each participant's table is classified by considering the formal table to which it is the closest. Our criterion of “closeness” or “distance” is as follows. A participant's table is taken to be a perfect instance of a formal table X when it is identical to X. A participant's table is a “close” instance of X when it differs from X just by one cell, and from any other formal table by more than one cell. If a participant's table differs equally (by one cell) from two (or more) formal tables, it is still “close” to, but classified as ambiguous between, these tables (these are equally likely). Finally, if a participant's table differs by two or more cells from all formal tables, then it is classified as “indeterminate”: it differs too much to make a reliable identification.

First of all, for the simple affirmation, the chip is square, all participants answered correctly, that is, certainly true when the chip was square, certainly false when it was round, and neither true nor false when its shape was blurred. This is evidence that the square, blurred, and round shapes were visually well distinguished, allowing participants to recognize the three logical possibilities, and in particular, the representation of uncertainty by the blurred image. Importantly, there was a perfect one-to-one correspondence between the blurred image and the neither answer, which validates this formulation.

For the negation, 48 participants (89%) fully conformed to the involutive negation ¬i (in which the third value maps onto itself) on all nine trials, and six participants (11%) answered in agreement with this table on eight trials (meaning that they were closer to the involutive negation than to any other type of negation). Two of these six participants clearly made a well-known slip triggered by double negation (Wason, 1959), answering F instead of T to a round chip when the sentence was The chip is not square. The other four participants negated the ∅ chip by answering F (three cases) or the T chip by answering ∅ (just for one case). The answers provided by these four participants are thus closest to an involutive negation than to left and right negations. In brief, we find evidence of only the involutive negation.

Before considering conjunction and disjunction, note that the numbers for these two connectives are smaller than they are in the first stage. This is because the three-valued tables for conjunction and disjunction (like for negation) are built as expansions of the corresponding classic two-valued tables which serve as filters, so that only participants who have produced the latter can be considered in the second stage. For instance, we have mentioned earlier that 98% of the 101 participants in Experiment 2 (i.e., 99 participants) produced a conjunction table in the first stage analysis. Consequently, the second stage analysis for conjunction and the related percentages are based on those 99 participants. The only case where N is notably diminished is disjunction in Experiment 2 (from 101 to 74, as mentioned in section The First Stage Analysis). The results for conjunction and disjunction are detailed in Tables 3, 4 in which we will examine the sum column.

TABLE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Table 3. Second stage analysis. Conjunction.

TABLE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Table 4. Second stage analysis. Disjunction.

For conjunction (Table 3), it is apparent that a large majority of the observations coincide with the KLH connective ∧K defined in Appendix A, Table A.2 (Supplementary Material) (82.8% in Experiment 2 and 96% in Experiment 3). The remaining interpretations correspond to the McCarthy ∧M conjunction (13.1 and 4%, respectively).

For disjunction (Table 4), the absolute majority of the observations (58.1%) coincide with the KLH connective ∨K defined in Appendix A, Table A.2 (Supplementary Material). The remaining interpretations coincide with the Sobocinsky disjunction ∨S (14.9%) and to tables that we call “ambiguous” because they differ equally (by one cell) from both disjunctions ∨K and ∨S.

For the conditional (Table 5), almost all the participants' interpretations coincide with a table that belongs to the Fi system. We find notably that all of the 22 participants whose first stage table was identified as de Finetti's 2 × 2 “defective” table expanded this table into de Finetti's conditional event (3 × 3) table. In other words, the conditional probability to produce the three-valued conditional event table knowing that the two-valued table is the “defective” table equals one. Also of interest is the fact that most participants (84.6%) who have a conjunctive interpretation of the conditional in the first stage expand this table into a conjunction table (the KLH table) that is in the Fi system. These results confirm the observations of Baratgin et al. (2013) with French participants. Similarly, most participants giving a biconditional interpretation produce the Fi biconditional. Interestingly, even for the material biconditional interpretation, most participants produce the associated Finettian table.

TABLE 5
www.frontiersin.org

Table 5. Second stage analysis. Conditional and biconditional.

For the biconditional sentence (Table 5), the observations are identical: almost all the participants' interpretations coincide with a table that belongs to the Fi system. In particular, the dominant biconditional interpretation is always the Finettian one, that is, 100% of 3 × 3 de Finetti biconditional table. Similarly, most participants (86.7%) with a material biconditional interpretation choose the expanded Kleene material biconditional [defined in Appendix A, Table A.5 (Supplementary Material)] and also most of those (83.3%) with a conjunctive interpretation produce the associated Finettian table [the KLH conjunction ∧K defined in Appendix A, Table A2 (Supplementary Material)]. All this suggests a remarkable consistency within a unique logical system, namely the Fi system.

We can summarize these results as follows. The overwhelmingly dominant table for A and C is the KLH conjunction ∧K and the dominant table for A or C is the KLH disjunction ∨K, both of which are features of the Finettian system. Whatever the interpretation for if A then C (conditional, conjunction, biconditional, material biconditional), it is the corresponding Finettian table that is overwhelmingly the dominant choice. This obtains also for if A then C and if C then A, whatever its interpretation (conjunction, biconditional, material biconditional). In addition, the involutive negation is always observed.

Discussion

De Finetti's Level 1 System as the Best Approximation

The hypothesis that de Finetti's Level 1 system is adequate to model the psychological three-valued truth tables for natural language connectives is clearly supported by the results in the following two respects. One, its constitutive connectives: involutive negation ¬i, the KLH conjunction ∧K, the KLH disjunction ∨K, the Fi conditional C|FiA and the Fi biconditional C||FiA, have been found to be the dominant interpretations. This was the case for the two languages studied, French and Japanese, which offers a remarkable cross-linguistic support to the Finettian theory on Level 1, given the remoteness of the two linguistic families. Two, even when the conditional and biconditional sentences are not construed as a conditional or a biconditional, respectively, the truth table that is produced still belongs most generally to the Fi system. However, it can be objected to the first point that the other two logical systems that are built on the same connectives, namely McDermott, and Reichenbach could, eo ipso, be regarded as possible candidates. Is there a way to decide between the three systems? We have seen earlier that the latter two differ from de Finetti in that they have additional connectives.

Consider first Reichenbach's system, (2) in Appendix B (Supplementary Material). It has additional connectives (two more negations), and two material conditionals and two material biconditionals [see Tables A.1 and A.4 (Supplementary Material)]. We made no observation of a form of negation other than the involutive one, nor did we find any trace of the two forms of material conditional or biconditional. We can conclude that Reichenbach's three-valued logic is inadequate in that it predicts several truth tables, that is, interpretations of the negation, conditional, and biconditional, that our participants never had. This is not too surprising given that the objective of his logic is to account for a problem that belongs to the epistemology of quantum mechanics. Even though there is striking overlap between his system and the three-valued table of the Finettian conditional, the additional connectives needed for his purpose are irrelevant for psychological modeling. To take but one example of the lack of plausibility of the system from a psycholinguistic point of view, the cyclical negation of A requires a triple application of the operator to get back to A: A = ~~~ A; and the complete negation holds only as: A¯=A¯¯¯, whereas double negation does apply to diametrical (involutive) negation: A = ¬i¬iA (see Table A.1).

McDermott's system, (4) in Appendix B (Supplementary Material), also has additional connectives: one conjunction (∧S) and one disjunction (∨S). For disjunction, we did find some trace of ∨S (15%, against 58% for ∨K), but for conjunction we did not find any trace of ∧S. This does not support the system. However, before eliminating it, we must envisage that there may be special conditions or circumstances under which the second set of connectives is used, which our material may have failed to meet. McDermott (1996) contented himself to remark, based on intuition, that and, and or are ambiguous in natural language, hence his definition of two different connectives in each case. But to exemplify the ambiguity he did not use simple sentences made of two atomic components, such as A and B, or A or B. Instead, he used complex sentences, one component of which was always a conditional (such as A and if B then C, or A or if B then C). Obviously, if this is required for the supplementary connectives to apply, the double connective claim cannot be refuted by our experimental results, which are based on at most two atomic sentences. McDermott's theory is not specified enough in its current state and the question remains open for further research. But it should be noted that if the claim becomes experimentally supported, it would come as an extension of the Finettian system proper. It is remarkable that McDermott's approach has much in common with de Finetti's, in particular in the assessment of truth values using the betting method, and crucially in the definition of the natural conditional. Finally, the conditions that trigger the additional connectives interpretation could have a pragmatic explanation, keeping the Finettian system semantically unaltered. For all these reasons, the objections to the first point above seem hard to maintain; in addition they leave the second point unaffected. This is why we can confidently conclude that our results designate the Finettian system as the best approximation to the participants' three-valued truth tables obtained from judgments of truth and falsity of atomic sentences describing uncertain characteristics.

The Significance of the Results: Logic and the Study of Human Reasoning

Our results constitute a step toward giving an integrated answer to three related questions. One, is there a dominant interpretation of the basic connectives with sentences that have a truth-value gap? Two, do these interpretations constitute a consistent system? Three, is there a way to solve the half-a-century-old problem of the “defective” truth table of the conditional?

The Existence of a Dominant Interpretation

We have obtained an affirmative answer to the first question. For each connective (negation, conjunction, disjunction, conditional, and biconditional), participants' interpretations were distributed over a limited number of table varieties among numerous possible tables, and for each connective, there was a clear dominant interpretation, namely, involutive negation, the KLH conjunction ∧K, the KLH disjunction ∨K, the Fi conditional C|FiA and the Fi biconditional C||FiA, respectively. For negation there was a single interpretation (involutive). For conjunction the modal interpretation (∧K), collapsed over two experiments, was close to 90%. For disjunction the modal interpretation (∨K) was chosen 58% of the time (among participants who had a 2 × 2 disjunctive interpretation) while the next most frequent interpretation was seldom chosen (16%). For the conditional and the biconditional, one interpretation (C|FiA and C||FiA, respectively) was chosen 100% of the time (among participants who had the corresponding 2 × 2 interpretation). In brief, given people's two-valued interpretation, there is always one way to extend this interpretation to a three-valued table that musters an absolute majority, and (except for disjunction) there is near unanimity for this interpretation.

The Existence of a System

We have obtained an affirmative answer to the second question too: not only is there a predominant interpretation for each connective, but this interpretation always belongs to the same system. It could have been the case that while the dominant table for one connective belongs to one system, the dominant table for another connective belongs to another system. But this is not what we have observed: for each connective, out of all the possible tables, it is the one that belongs to the Finettian system that dominates. And there is more: even when the two-valued table has deviating interpretations, which occurs for the conditional and the biconditional, the table is almost always completed into the corresponding Finettian table. See for instance how in Experiment 3 the two-valued conjunctive interpretation of the biconditional made by 12 participants (20.7%, Table 2, first stage analysis) leads ten of them (83.3%) to the corresponding conjunctive Finettian (∧K) three-valued interpretation shown in Table 5 (second stage analysis). All this means that the present results are more than an extension to the other connectives of the results obtained for the conditional by Baratgin et al. (2013). Rather, what we have established here is the existence, in people's judgments under uncertainty, of mutually consistent interpretations of the standard connectives organized in one system, namely de Finetti's Level 1 system.

Interpreting the “Defective” Table

Finally, we have obtained confirmation of a positive answer to the third question, “Can the puzzle of the defective table be solved?” Three-valued truth tables generalize two-valued tables. They collapse into two-valued tables when the component sentences are certain. In such a case, for the conditional, the third value ∅ left in the body of the 2 × 2 table constitutes the “defective” table and the explanation of its origin. Note that there is no conflict between the two-valued and three-valued tables. The latter incorporate the former in the same way that rational numbers include integers.

The Significance of the Results: Interpreting the Third Value

We recalled some important findings in the introduction. For several decades psychologists have known that people judge that if A then C is true when A holds and C holds, false when A holds and C does not, and neither true nor false when A does not hold. For the last decade, there has been growing psychological evidence that people tend to judge that the probability of the indicative conditional, P(if A then C), is the conditional probability of C given A, P(C|A). There is also evidence supporting the claim that people tend to be coherent in explicit deduction under uncertainty. More recently, psychologists have shown that there is a close relation between indicative conditionals and conditional bets (Oberauer and Wilhelm, 2003; Politzer et al., 2010; Baratgin et al., 2013, 2014; Nakamura et al., 2018). There is an urgent need to integrate these experimental findings. The integration has been held back because psychologists did not raise the general question of which three-valued tables correspond most closely to people's judgments under uncertainty.

In the present paper, we have raised the question and proposed an answer based on de Finetti's Level 1 system, offering a model of the interpretation of natural language connectives under uncertainty. Obviously, we should keep in mind the limitations of our study due to the size of the samples and more importantly to the fact that the sentences in the experiments referred to specific materials. No overall investigation of the foundations of de Finetti's system, at Level 1, had yet been carried out. In view of the psychological relevance and plausibility of de Finetti's subjective approach to probability, and of the successful application of his concepts and ideas recalled above, it would have been deeply puzzling if the interpretation of connectives had been found to be at variance with his system. But on the contrary, our results showing that people conform to de Finetti's Level 1 system add much support to the project of developing the psychology of reasoning on a de Finettian basis, within the Bayesian account of ordinary reasoning that we are pursuing.

Our results should lead to more research. Important questions concerning the interpretation of the third value still await investigation. We have seen that the various systems of three-valued logic have different uses and objectives in defining a third value (even though most systems studied interpret it as a truth-value gap, see Appendix B (Supplementary Material). However, there appears to be an underlying common notion, that of doubt about truth and falsity due to uncertainty.

Even though we have identified the most frequent interpretation of each connective, namely the one that belongs to the Finettian system, it must be kept in mind that this result relies on a few experiments that operationalized uncertainty as ignorance about which of two values a visually defined variable had. Visual uncertainty about the identification of two shapes or two colors was hypothesized to coincide with de Finetti's concept of a “void” judgment. We certainly acknowledge that there is a need for additional experiments using other languages and, more importantly, that vary the source of uncertainty. There are perhaps other types of visual uncertainty, e.g., arising from soritical series (see Douven et al., 2018), and we should move beyond the visual modality, e.g., to sound or haptic modalities, and then beyond the sensory modalities, e.g., to logical or semantic uncertainty (as can be found in the paradoxes of self-reference; see Elqayam, 2006). The choices are unlimited, for uncertainty is everywhere in natural language, a point de Finetti himself would have emphasized. If the results of such experiments are consistent with the present observations, then there will be stronger support for the general conclusion that the Fi system is the best semantic theory of the interpretation of natural language connectives under uncertainty.

In contrast, it is possible to operationalize a much more common concept of uncertainty. Considering that ignorance reflects a lack of information that could be dispelled as information increases, still using the same material participants could be provided with frequency distributions about the proportions of round, square, black, and white chips, that is, manipulating the base rates. With this additional knowledge, one is invited to move from radical uncertainty to a gradable notion of uncertainty in which the individuals' degrees of belief vary between 0 and 1. In this modified situation there is no more total ignorance and the individual shifts from Level 1 to Level 2. But in doing so, one would be losing the state of total ignorance whose investigation is the objective of the present work, and as noted earlier (section The de Finettian Approach) the psychological research on reasoning under uncertainty (and indeed a large amount of research on judgment and decision making under uncertainty) has essentially been carried out on Level 2.

We have considered the basic connectives, but it might be interesting for future research to study more complex sentences than the basic ones. Conditionals can be embedded like in left embedding If they were outside (O), then if it rained (R) they got wet (W) or in right embedding If the cup broke (B) if dropped (D), then it was fragile (F) (see Gibbard, 1981; Douven and Verbrugge, 2013; Douven, 2016). In the Finettian framework of Level 1, these sentences can be written as (W|FiR)|FiO and F|Fi(B|FiD), respectively and they collapse into a single form, W|Fi(RKO) and F|Fi(BKD), respectively (de Finetti, 1974, p. 328). Their truth tables can be established, allowing a further test of the theory on its Level 1 (van Wijnbergen-Huitink et al., 2015). Recently the Finettian treatment of embedded conditionals on level 2 has attracted the attention of theorists (Gilio and Sanfilippo, 2014; Douven, 2017; Sanfilippo et al., 2018) with results that reflect the difference of perspective between the two levels.

One final remark also for future research: in the current study we have compared various systems by eliciting judgments of truth value for connected sentences. Given that each system has a consequence relation, another way to test the systems against each other could be to study the elementary inferences that reasoners are willing to make.

Author Contributions

JB and GP: design of the study and data analysis. JB and TT: data collection. GP and JB: draft of the manuscript. JB, GP, and DO: conceptual elaboration. DO and TT: critical revision of the manuscript.

Funding

This work was supported by the French ANR agency under grant ANR Chorus 2011 (project BTAFDOC) and by JSPS KAKENHI Grant Number 17H04696.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Ikuko Hattori, Masasi Hattori, Yoshimasa Majima, Hiroko Nakamura, Jean-Louis Stilgenbauer, Hiroshi Yama, and Arai Yoshiko for much discussion and other help in our research and several reviewers of a previous version for helpful suggestions. We are also grateful to Junki Yokokawa for his help in running Experiment 3 and its analysis.

Supplementary material

The Supplementary Material for this article can be found online at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01479/full#supplementary-material

Footnotes

1. ^Several philosophers have proposed an identical 2 × 2 “defective” table in their analysis of “if” in ordinary language, with different interpretations of the third value. According to Quine (1950) a conditional affirmation with a false antecedent is as if it had never been made. O'Connor (1951) defines a table with a third undetermined value. Dummet (1958/1959) presents a similar table where the third value corresponds to neither true nor false. Kneale and Kneale 1962, p. 135–136) suggest a “defective” table (in the sense of defective truth function) where the value I (denoted by ”–“) characterizes a truth-value gap.

2. ^There is much more in the betting scheme: de Finetti (1937/1964) proposed it at Level 2 as a procedure to operationally evaluate P(C|A), from which it follows that the conditional event can be represented as a three-valued random quantity taking on values 1, 0, P(C|A) (Gilio, 1990). Note that de Finetti (1962, 1964/1972, 1974) proposed also the penalty criterion (based on the Brier score) as a procedure to operationally evaluate P(C|A) (see for a recent analysis Gilio and Sanfilippo, 2011).

3. ^Stenning and Van Lambalgen (2008) used Kleene's (1938) three-valued logic in the framework of logic programming, but they did not study participants' truth tables.

4. ^With the exception of the R system, the material conditional and the material biconditional are not defining features because they can be derived compositionally from the basic connectives using the formulas AC =df ¬ AC, and AC =df (AC) ∧ (CA).

5. ^One may balk at this notion because conditionals typically have uncertain antecedents and nevertheless they often convey a high degree of belief (or disbelief) rather than ignorance. One need not know whether it is true that this man will fall from the 20th floor to hold it to be false that if this man falls from the 20th floor he will survive. In this apparent counter example, which is on Level 2, the common knowledge suggests a degree of belief. In contrast, with our abstract and arbitrary material on Level 1 individuals have no expectations about the truth value of the conditional.

6. ^In doing so, we followed psychologist's traditional way of disambiguating “or” in the study of reasoning.

References

Baioletti, M., and Capotorti, A. (1994). “Two different characterizations of logical dependence on conditional events,” in Proceedings of the 3rd Workshop on Uncertainty Processing in Expert Systems (WUPES'94), ed R. Jiroušek (Trešt), 7–17.

Google Scholar

Baioletti, M., and Capotorti, A. (1996). “A comparison between classical logic and three-valued logic for conditional events,” in Proceedings of Sixth International Conference Information Processing and Management of Uncertainty in Knowledge-Based Systems (IPMU'96) (Granada), 1217–1222.

Google Scholar

Baratgin, J. (2015). Rationality, the Bayesian standpoint, and the Monty-Hall problem. Front. Psychol. 6:1168. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01168

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baratgin, J., Douven, I., Evans, J. S. B. T, Oaksford, M., Over, D., et al. (2015). The new paradigm and mental models. Trends Cog. Sci. 19, 547–548 doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2015.06.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baratgin, J., Over, D. E., and Politzer, G. (2013). Uncertainty and the de Finetti tables. Think. Reason. 16, 253–287. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2010.519564

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baratgin, J., Over, D. E., and Politzer, G. (2014). New psychological paradigm for conditionals and general de Finetti tables. Mind Lang. 29, 73–84. doi: 10.1111/mila.12042

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baratgin, J., and Politzer, G. (2006). Is the mind Bayesian? The case for agnosticism. Mind Soc 5, 1–38. doi: 10.1007/s11299-006-0007-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baratgin, J., and Politzer, G. (2007). The psychology of dynamic probability judgment: order effect, normative theory and experimental methodology. Mind Soc. 5, 53–66. doi: 10.1007/s11299-006-0025-z

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Baratgin, J., and Politzer, G. (2016). “Logic, probability and inference: a methodology for a new paradigm,” in Cognitive Unconscious and Human Rationality, eds L. Macchi, M. Bagassi, and R. Viale (Cambridge: MIT Press), 119–142.

Beaver, D. (1992). “The kinematics of presupposition,” in Proceedings of the Eighth Amsterdam Colloquium, eds P. Dekker and M. Stockhof (University of Amsterdam: ILLC), 17–36.

Google Scholar

Beaver, D. (1997). “Presupposition,” in The Handbook of Logic and Language, eds J. van Benthem and A. ter Meulen (Amsterdam: Elsevier), 939–1008.

Google Scholar

Beaver, D., and Kramer, E. (2001). A partial account of presupposition projection. J. Log. Lang. Inf. 10, 147–182. doi: 10.1023/A:1008371413822

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Belnap, N. D. (1970). Conditional assertion and restricted quantification. Nôus 1, 1–12. doi: 10.2307/2214285

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Belnap, N. D. (1973). “Restricted quantification and conditional assertion,” in Truth, Modality and Syntax, ed H. Leblanc (Amsterdam: North-Holland), 48–75.

Google Scholar

Binet, A. (1902). La Psychologie du Raisonnement: Recherches Expérimentales par l'Hypnotisme [The Psychology of Reasoning: Experimental Research by Hypnosis]. Paris: Alcan.

Blamey, S. (2001). Partial Logic, Vol. 5. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 261–353.

Google Scholar

Bochvar, D. A (1938/1981). On a three-valued logical calculus and its application to the analysis of the paradoxes of the classical extended functional calculus. Hist. Philos. Log. 2, 87–112.

Google Scholar

Bourne, C. (2004). Future contingents, non-contradiction, and the Law of excluded middle muddle. Analysis 64, 122–128. doi: 10.1093/analys/64.2.122

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Braine, M., and O'Brien, D. P. (1998). Mental Logic. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Bruno, G., and Gilio, A. (1985). Confronto fra eventi condizionati di probabilità nulla nell' inferenza statistica bayesiana [Comparing conditional events of zero probability in Bayesian statistical inference]. Riv. Mat. Sci. Econom. Soc. 8, 141–152.

Google Scholar

Calabrese, P. G. (1987). An algebraic synthesis of the foundations of logic and probability. Inf. Sci. 42, 187–237. doi: 10.1016/0020-0255(87)90023-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Calabrese, P. G. (2002). Deduction with uncertain conditionals. Inf. Sci. 147, 143–191. doi: 10.1016/S0020-0255(02)00262-1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cantwell, J. (2008). The logic of conditional negation. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 49, 245–260. doi: 10.1215/00294527-2008-010

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cantwell, J. (2009). Conditionals in reasoning. Synthese 171, 47–75. doi: 10.1007/s11229-008-9379-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Chrzastowski-Wachtel, P., Tyszkiewicz, J., Hoffmann, A., and Ramer, A. (2001). Definability of connectives in conditional event algebras of Schay-Adams-Calabrese and Goodman-Nguyen-Walker. Inf. Process. Lett. 79, 155–160. doi: 10.1016/S0020-0190(00)00219-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cobreros, P., Égré, P., Ripley, D., and van Rooij, R. (2014). Foreword: three-valued logics and their applications. JANCL 24, 1–11. doi: 10.1080/11663081.2014.909631

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Coletti, G., and Scozzafava, R. (2002). Probabilistic Logic in a Coherent Setting. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Cooper, W. S. (1968). The propositional logic of ordinary discourse. Inquiry 11, 295–320. doi: 10.1080/00201746808601531

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cruz, N., Baratgin, J., Oaksford, M., and Over, D. E. (2015). Bayesian reasoning with ifs and ands and ors. Front. Psychol. 6:192. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00192

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

de Finetti, B (1936/1995). La logique de la probabilité. Actes du congrès international de philosophie scientifique. Sorbonne, 1935. IV: induction et probabilité, 31-39. Paris: Hermann. English translation (1995): the logic of probability. Philos. Stud 77, 181–190.

Google Scholar

de Finetti, B (1937/1964). La prevision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Annales de l'Institut Henri Poincaré, VII, 1-67. English translation: “Foresight: its logical laws, its subjective sources,” in Studies in Subjective Probability, eds H. E. Kyburg Jr. and H. E Smokler. (New York, NY: John Wiley), 55–118.

de Finetti, B. (1962). “Does it make sense to speak of 'good probability appraisers'?,” in The Scientist Speculates: An Anthology of Partly-Baked Ideas, ed I. J. Good (London: Heinemann), 357–364.

de Finetti, B (1964/1972). Probabilità composte e teoria delle decisioni. Rendiconti di Matematica, 23, 128–134. English translation: “Conditional probability and decision theory,” in Probability, Induction, and Statistics. The Art of Guessing (New York, NY: John Wiley), 13–18.

de Finetti, B. (1967). Sur quelques conventions qui semblent utiles [On some conventions that seem helpful]. Rev. Roumaine Math. Pures Appl. 9, 1227–1233.

de Finetti, B. (1974). Theory of Probability. Vol. 1 and 2. New York, NY: Wiley.

Google Scholar

de Finetti, B (1977/1993). “Il ruolo della probabilità nei diversi atteggiamenti del pensiero scientifico'” [The role of probability in the different attitudes of scientific thinking], in Probabilità e Induzione; Induction and Probability, eds P. Monari and D. Cocchi (Rome: Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei), 27–42.

de Finetti, B. (1980). Probabilità [Probability]. Encyclopedia, Vol. 10. Torino: Einaudi, 1146–1187.

de Finetti, B (1995/2008). Filosofia della probabilità [Philosophy of probability]. Il Saggiatore: Milan. English translation: Philosophical Lectures on Probability. Collected, edited, and annotated by Alberto Mura. (2008). Synthese Library; 340. Dordrecht: Springer.

de Finetti, B. (2006). L'invenzione della Verità [The Invention of Truth]. Cortina: Milan.

Google Scholar

Delval, J. A., and Riviére, A. (1975). “Si llueve, Elisa lleva sombrero”: Una investigacion psicologica sobre la tabla de verdad del condicional. [“If it rains, Elisa takes an umbrella”. A psychological study on the truth table of the conditional]. Rev. Psicol. Gen. Apl. 136, 825–850.

Douven, I. (2016). The Epistemology of Indicative Conditionals: Formal and Empirical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Douven, I. (2017). “On de Finetti on iterated conditionals,” in Computational Models of Rationality, eds C. Beierle, G. Brewka, and M. Thimm (London: College Publications), 265–279.

Google Scholar

Douven, I., Elqayam, S., Singmann, H., and van Wijnbergen-Huitink, J. (2018). Conditionals and inferential connections: a hypothetical inferential theory. Cogn. Psychol. 101, 50–81. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2017.09.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Douven, I., and Verbrugge, S. (2010). The adams family. Cognition 117, 302–318. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2010.08.015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Douven, I., and Verbrugge, S. (2013). The probabilities of conditionals revisited. Cogn. Sci. 37, 711–730. doi: 10.1111/cogs.12025

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dubois, D. (2008). On ignorance and contradiction considered as truth-values. Log. J. IGPL 16, 195–216. doi: 10.1093/jigpal/jzn003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dubois, D., and Prade, H. (1994). Conditional objects as nonmonotonic consequence relationships. IEEE Trans. Syst. Man. Cybern. Syst. 24, 1724–1740. doi: 10.1109/21.328930

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dubois, D., and Prade, H. (2001). Possibility theory, probability theory and multiple-valued logics: a clarification. Ann. Math. Artif. Intell. 32, 35–66. doi: 10.1023/A:1016740830286

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Dummet, M (1958/1959). Truth. Proc. Aristot. Soc New Series 59, 141–162.

Dunn, J. M. (1975). Axiomatizing Belnap's conditional assertion. J. Philos. Log. 4, 343–397.

Google Scholar

Ellis, B. (1973). The logic of subjective probability. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 24, 125–152. doi: 10.1093/bjps/24.2.125

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Elqayam, S. (2006). The collapse illusion effect: a semantic-pragmatic illusion of truth and paradox. Think. Reason. 12, 144–180. doi: 10.1080/13546780500172425

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Elqayam, S., and Over, D. E. (2013). New paradigm psychology of reasoning: an introduction to the special issue edited by Elqayam, Bonnefon, and Over. Think. Reason. 19, 249–265. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2013.841591

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Evans, J. St. B. T. (1972). Interpretation and matching bias in a reasoning task. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 24, 193–199. doi: 10.1080/00335557243000067

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Evans, J. St. B. T. (2012). Questions and challenges for the new psychology of reasoning. Think. Reason. 18, 5–31. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2011.637674

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Evans, J. St. B. T., Handley, S. J., Neilens, H., and Over, D. E. (2007). Thinking about conditionals: a study of individual differences. Mem. Cogn. 35, 1772–1784. doi: 10.3758/BF03193509

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Evans, J. St. B. T., Handley, S. J., and Over, D. E. (2003). Conditionals and conditional probability. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 29, 321–335. doi: 10.1037/0278-7393.29.2.321

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Evans, J. St. B. T., Newstead, S. E., and Byrne, R. M. J. (1993). Human Reasoning–The Psychology of Deduction. Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Evans, J. St. B. T., and Over, D. E. (2004). If. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Evans, J. St. B. T., Thompson, V., and Over, D. E. (2015). Uncertain deduction and conditional reasoning. Front. Psychol. 6:398. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00398

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text

Farrell, R. J. (1979). Implication and presupposition. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 27, 51–61. doi: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093636522

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Farrell, R. J. (1986). Material implication, confirmation, and counterfactuals. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 20, 383–394. doi: 10.1305/ndjfl/1093882546

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Frege, G (1892/1952). “On sense and reference,”. in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, eds P. T. Geach and M. Black (Oxford: Blackwell), 56–78.

Gibbard, A. (1981). “Two recent theories of conditionals,” in Ifs: Conditionals, Belief, Decision, Chance, and Time, eds W. L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce (Dordrecht: Reidel), 211–247.

Google Scholar

Gilio, A. (1990). Criterio di penalizzazione e condizioni di coerenza nella valutazione soggettiva della probabilità. [Penalty criterion and conditions of coherence in subjective evaluation of probability]. Boll. Un. Mat. Ital. 4B, 645–660.

Gilio, A., and Sanfilippo, G. (2011). “Coherent conditional probabilities and proper scoring rules,” in Proceedings of the Seventh International Symposium on Imprecise Probability, (Innsbruck: ISIPTA-11), 189–198.

Google Scholar

Gilio, A., and Sanfilippo, G. (2014). Conditional random quantities and compounds of conditionals. Stud Log. 102, 709–729. doi: 10.1007/s11225-013-9511-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Goodman, I. R., Nguyen, H. T., and Walker, E. A. (1991). Conditional Inference and Logic for Intelligent Systems- A Theory of Measure-Free Conditioning. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

Gottwald, S. (2015). “Many-valued logic,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed Edward N. Zalta (Spring) Available online at: < http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/logic-manyvalued/>

Google Scholar

Grandy, H., and Osherson, D. (2014). Logic: A Primer for Psychologists. Available online at: http://www.ruf.rice.edu/~rgrandy/primer.pdf and http://www.princeton.edu/~osherson/primer.pdf

Haack, S. (1974). Deviant Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hailperin, T. (1996). Sentential Probability Logic: Origins, Development, Current Status, and Technical Applications. Bethlehem: Lehigh University Press.

Hailperin, T. (2011). Logic with a Probability Semantics. Lanham: the Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Inc. and Lehigh University Press.

Inhelder, B., and Piaget, J. (1958). The Growth of Logical Thinking from Childhood to Adolescence. New York, NY: Basic Books.

James, W. (1908). Text-Book of Psychology, Briefer Course. London: Macmillan.

Jeffrey, R. C. (1991). Matter of fact conditionals. Proc. Aristot. Soc. Suppl. Vol. 65, 161–183. doi: 10.1093/aristoteliansupp/65.1.161

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Johnson-Laird, P. N., and Byrne, R. M. J. (1991). Deduction. Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Johnson-Laird, P. N., and Tagart, J. (1969). How implication is understood. Am. J. Psychol. 82, 367–373. doi: 10.2307/1420752

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kleene, S. C. (1938). On notation for ordinal numbers. J. Symbolic Log. 3, 150–155. doi: 10.2307/2267778

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kneale, W., and Kneale, M. (1962). The Development of Logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Łukasiewicz, J (1920/1967). “On 3-valued logic,” in Polish Logic, ed S. McCall (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 40–65.

Mandel, D. R. (2014). Do framing effects reveal irrational choice? J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 143, 1185–1198.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

Manktelow, K. I. (2012). Thinking and Reasoning: Psychological Perspectives on Reason, Judgment and Decision Making. Hove: Psychology Press.

McDermott, M. (1996). On the truth conditions of certain ”if'-sentences“. Philos. Rev. 105, 1–37.

Google Scholar

Milne, P. (1997). Bruno de Finetti and the logic of conditional events. Br. J. Philos. Sci 48, 195–232. doi: 10.1093/bjps/48.2.195

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Milne, P. (2004). Algebras of intervals and a logic of conditional assertions. J. Philos. Log. 33, 497–548. doi: 10.1023/B:LOGI.0000046072.61596.32

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Milne, P. (2012). Indicative conditionals, conditional probabilities, and the “defective truth-table”: a request for more experiments. Think. Reason. 18, 196–224. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2012.670754

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mura, A. (2009). “Probability and the logic of de Finetti's trievents,” in Bruno de Finetti Radical Probabilist, ed M. C. Galavotti (London: College Publications), 201–242.

Google Scholar

Mura, A. (2016). Logica dei condizionali e logica della probabilità [Conditionals logic and probability logic]. Riv. Filos. 57, 71–98. doi: 10.1413/82724

CrossRef Full Text

Muskens, R., van Benthem, J., and Visser, A. (1996). Dynamics. Group preprint series, Department of Philosophy, Utrecht University.

Nakamura, H., and Kawaguchi, J. (2016). People like logical truth: testing the intuitive detection of logical value in basic propositions. PLoS ONE 11:e0169166. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0169166

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nakamura, H., Shao, J., Baratgin, J., Over, D. E., Takahashi, T., and Yama, H. (2018). Understanding conditionals in the East: a Replication study of Politzer et al. (2010) with Easterners. Front. Psychol. 9:505. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00505

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Oaksford, M., and Chater, N. (2007). Bayesian rationality: The Probabilistic Approach to Human Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

PubMed Abstract

Oaksford, M., and Chater, N. (2009). Précis of Bayesian rationality: the probabilistic approach to human reasoning. Behav. Brain Sci. 32, 69–84. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X09000284

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Oberauer, K., and Wilhelm, O. (2003). The meaning(s) of conditionals: conditional probabilities, mental models and personal utilities. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 29, 680–693. doi: 10.1037/0278-7393.29.4.680

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

O'Connor, D. J. (1951). The analysis of conditional sentences. Mind 60, 351–362.

Google Scholar

Over, D. E. (2009). New paradigm psychology of reasoning. Think. Reason. 15, 431–438. doi: 10.1080/13546780903266188

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Over, D. E. (2016). “The paradigm shift in the psychology of reasoning,” in Cognitive Unconscious and Human Rationality, eds L. Macchi, M. Bagassi, and R. Viale (Cambridge: MIT Press), 79–97.

Over, D. E., and Baratgin, J. (2017). “The ”defective“ truth table: its past, present, and future,” in The Thinking Mind: A Festschrift for Ken Manktelow, eds N. Galbraith, E. Lucas, and D. E. Over (London: Psychology Press), 15–28.

Google Scholar

Over, D. E., and Cruz, N. (2018). Probabilistic accounts of conditional reasoning. in International handbook of thinking and reasoning, eds L. J. Ball and V. A. Thompson (Hove: Psychology Press), 434–450.

Pfeifer, N. (2013). The new psychology of reasoning: a mental probability logical perspective. Think. Reason. 19, 329–345. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2013.838189

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pfeifer, N. (2014). Reasoning about uncertain conditionals. Stud. Log. 102, 849–866. doi: 10.1007/s11225-013-9505-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pfeifer, N., and Kleiter, G. D. (2009). Framing human inference by coherence based probability logic. J. Appl. Log. 7, 206–217. doi: 10.1016/j.jal.2007.11.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pfeifer, N., and Kleiter, G. D. (2010). “The conditional in mental probability logic,” in Cognition and Conditionals, eds M. Oaksford and N. Chater (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 153–173.

Google Scholar

Pfeifer, N., and Kleiter, G. D. (2011). “Uncertain deductive reasoning,” in The science of reason, eds K. Manktelow, D. Over, and S. Elqayam (Hove,: Psychology Press), 145–166.

Google Scholar

Politzer, G. (1981). Differences in interpretation of implication. Am. J. Psychol. 94, 461–477. doi: 10.2307/1422257

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Politzer, G., and Baratgin, J. (2016). Deductive schemas with uncertain premises using qualitative probability expressions. Think. Reason. 22, 78–98. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2015.1052561

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Politzer, G., Over, D. E., and Baratgin, J. (2010). Betting on conditionals. Think. Reason. 16, 172–197. doi: 10.1080/13546783.2010.504581

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Quine, W. V. O. (1950). Methods of Logic. New York, NY: Holt.

Ramsey, F. P (1926/1990). “Truth and probability,” in Philosophical Papers, ed D. H. Mellor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 52–94.

Google Scholar

Ramsey, F. P (1929/1990). “General propositions and causality (originally published 1929),” in Philosophical Papers, ed D. H. Mellor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 145–163.

Reichenbach, H. (1944). Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Reichenbach, H (1952/1953). Les fondements logiques de la mécanique des quanta [The logical foundations of quantum mechanics]. Annales de l'Institut Henri Poincaré, 13, 109–158. doi: 10.1007/978-94-009-9855-1_7.

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rescher, N. (1962). Quasi-truth-functional systems of propositional logic. J. Symb. Log. 27, 1–10. doi: 10.2307/2963674

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rescher, N. (1969). Many-Valued Logic. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.

Rips, L. J. (1994). The Psychology of Proof. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Rothschild, D. (2014). Capturing the relationship between conditionals and conditional probability with a trivalent semantics. J. Appl. Non Class. Log. 24, 144–152. doi: 10.1080/11663081.2014.911535

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sanfilippo, G., Pfeifer, N., Over, D. E., and Gilio, A. (2018). Probabilistic inferences from conjoined to iterated conditionals. Int. J. Approx. Reason. 93, 103–118. doi: 10.1016/j.ijar.2017.10.027

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schay, G. (1968). An algebra of conditional events. J. Math. Anal. Appl. 24, 334–344. doi: 10.1016/0022-247X(68)90035-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seuren, P. A. M. (1988). Presupposition and negation. J. Semant. 6, 175–226. doi: 10.1093/jos/6.1.175

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Singmann, H., Klauer, K. C., and Over, D. E. (2014). New normative standards of conditional reasoning and the dual-source model. Front. Psychol. 5:316. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00316

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Stenning, K., and Van Lambalgen, M. (2008). Human Reasoning and Cognitive Science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

van Wijnbergen-Huitink, J., Elqayam, S., and Over, D. E. (2015). The probability of iterated conditionals. Cogn. Sci. 39, 788–803. doi: 10.1111/cogs.12169

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Vidal, M., and Baratgin, J. (2017). A psychological study of unconnected conditionals. J. Cogn. Psychol. 29, 769–781. doi: 10.1080/20445911.2017.1305388

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wason, P. C. (1959). The processing of positive and negative information. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 11, 92–107. doi: 10.1080/17470215908416296

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wason, P. C. (1966). “Reasoning,” in New Horizons in Psychology, ed B. Foss (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books), 135–151.

Google Scholar

Keywords: natural language connectives, three-valued truth tables, uncertainty, de Finetti's tri-event, subjective probability

Citation: Baratgin J, Politzer G, Over DE and Takahashi T (2018) The Psychology of Uncertainty and Three-Valued Truth Tables. Front. Psychol. 9:1479. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01479

Received: 07 May 2018; Accepted: 26 July 2018;
Published: 04 September 2018.

Edited by:

David R. Mandel, Defence Research and Development Canada, Canada

Reviewed by:

Igor Douven, Université Paris-Sorbonne, France
Keith Kirk Niall, Retired, Toronto, ON, Canada

Copyright © 2018 Baratgin, Politzer, Over and Takahashi. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Jean Baratgin, amVhbi5iYXJhdGdpbkB1bml2LXBhcmlzOC5mcg==

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.