Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Sustain., 01 March 2024
Sec. Quantitative Sustainability Assessment

Both de-growth and a-growth to achieve strong and weak sustainability: a theoretical model, empirical results, and some ethical insights

  • Dipartimento di Scienze per la Qualità della Vita, Università di Bologna, Bologna, Italy

This study conceptually characterizes and theoretically represents the four main sustainability paradigms (strong sustainability, weak sustainability, de-growth, and a-growth) in terms of equality and inequality. It then applies these conditions to developed and less-developed countries (OECD and non-OECD countries) and empirically shows that the change in production technology (∆θ) required by a-growth is impossible and the change in consumption preferences (∆α) required by de-growth is unfeasible. Finally, it combines a-growth and de-growth in a theoretical solution for the relationship between ∆α and ∆θ that meets the conditions required by both strong and weak sustainability (parameters are the world’s population, consumption preferences, and production technologies or concerns for nature and future generations in developed and less-developed countries) and empirically demonstrates that this solution is feasible. In particular, sustainability turns out to be an ethical issue more than a technological issue, and the ethical concern for nature turns out to be more favorable than the ethical concern for future generations. Ethical assumptions and implications of the four main sustainability paradigms are highlighted and ethical assumptions and implications of the combined theoretical model are discussed. In particular, intergenerational efficiency is achieved in terms of welfare, and intergenerational equity is achieved in terms of environmental status.

1 Introduction

Ecological economists have vigorously debated the concept and consequences of de-growth since the first publication by Kallis et al. (2010) and a-growth since the first publication by Van den Bergh (2010), as well as their value as alternative sustainability paradigms. In particular, an ideological debate by these authors (i.e., Kallis, 2011; Van den Bergh, 2011) in Ecological Economics has led to a conceptual debate by (mainly) these authors and (some) other authors in (mainly) this journal and (some) other journals (e.g., Haapanen and Tapio, 2016; Cosme et al., 2017).

However, environmental sustainability is a practical issue. Indeed, the observed failures of international pacts on climate change (e.g., the Kyoto Protocol and the Paris Agreement) suggest that it is not enough for a technological improvement to be possible or a cultural change to be intended to move the world away from unsustainable practices; new technologies and values must also be feasible (i.e., both effective and practical) to achieve realistic equilibrium sustainability conditions.

The primary purpose of this study is to test whether there can be synergies between a-growth and de-growth to support the practical debate over how to achieve weak sustainability and strong sustainability as two theoretically distinct sustainability paradigms. To do so, I will conceptually characterize the four sustainability paradigms (section 2.1) by developing a single theoretical framework that depicts all these sustainability paradigms (section 2.2). I will then apply real-world data to this theoretical framework to test whether the conditions required only by a-growth (based on improvements in production technology), only by de-growth (based on changes in consumption preferences), and the combined requirements under a-growth and de-growth are unable to meet the conditions required by weak and strong sustainability (section 3). I discuss the previous results in the literature and the novel insights of my study, as well as the methodological weaknesses and strengths of my approach in section 4, and I summarize my conclusion in section 5.

Note that the public opinion on the growth versus environment dilemma has been properly evaluated (i.e., multi-level and cross-country models) by three recent articles: Gugushvili (2021) in 33 European countries by applying logistic regressions to data from the 2017 European Values Study; Lou et al. (2022) in 58 countries by applying random forest models to the World Values Survey data collected from 2010 to 2014; and Paulson and Büchs (2022) in 34 European countries by applying logistic regressions to data from the 2017 European Values Study. Indeed, other articles are limited to a single country (e.g., Drews et al., 2019; Savin et al., 2021; Böhmelt and Zhang, 2023) or they apply single-level models (e.g., Nadeau et al., 2022). In those three articles, the idea of sacrificing a certain level of growth for the sake of the environment turns out to have predictors at the country level (i.e., Gross Domestic Product growth rate, Gross Domestic Product per capita, and carbon dioxide productivity) and the individual level. In particular, post-materialists, politically left-leaning, better-off, and higher educated people with a larger sense of responsibility, self-expansion identity, concern for the environment, and a more favorable attitude toward science and technology prioritize environmental protection over growth; materialists, politically right-wing, and disadvantaged people prioritize growth over environmental protection.

However, combining economic perspectives with ecological perspectives means adopting an interdisciplinary approach.

The secondary purpose of this study is to highlight the main linkages and interactions between ethical assumptions and implications in alternative perspectives. In particular, ethical assumptions and implications of the four main sustainability paradigms are highlighted in section 2.1, whereas ethical assumptions and implications of the combined theoretical model are discussed in section 5.

Note that many articles have characterized de-growth and a-growth in terms of values (e.g., Gunderson, 2018; Hankammer and Kleer, 2018; Strunz and Bartkowski, 2018; Sandberg et al., 2019) and policies (e.g., Khmara and Kronenberg, 2020; Fitzpatrick et al., 2022). Moreover, some articles have compared de-growth and a-growth from the experts’ and researchers’ perspectives (e.g., D'Amato et al., 2019; Lehmann et al., 2022). Finally, few articles have characterized de-growth and a-growth with a theoretical approach (e.g., Heikkinen, 2020) or an empirical approach (e.g., O'Neill, 2015). However, to the best of my knowledge, no articles have characterized and compared de-growth and a-growth with a theoretical and empirical approach.

2 Methods

2.1 Conceptual characterization of sustainability paradigms

Four main sustainability paradigms can be identified between a purely economic framework (e.g., Ramsey, 1928) and a purely ecological framework (e.g., Holling, 1973) under the definition of environmental sustainability by Salas-Zapata et al. (2017) (i.e., maximization of social and ecological continuity and/or minimization of social and ecological impacts): weak sustainability, a-growth, de-growth, and strong sustainability (Zagonari, 2022).

Table 1 summarizes the main ethical assumptions and implications of the four sustainability paradigms by including a purely social perspective and a purely ecological perspective, whereas Supplementary Materials and Zagonari (2022) provide the definitions of concepts used in the two main economic models and the three main ecological models. In particular, social efficiency in Ramsey (1928) and Arrow and Debreu’s (1954) economic models, Holling (1973) ecological resilience, and Yi and Jackson (2021) and Li et al. (2020) ecological models.

Table 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Ethical assumptions and ethical implications.

Some remarks in Table 1 are worthy here. Social sustainability (in Economy) comes from the maximization of the discounted value of welfare from t = 0 to t = ∞; ecological sustainability (in Ecology) is based on the environmental status being equal to a resilient equilibrium from t = 0 to t = ∞. Weak sustainability maximizes total welfare by implementing the inter-generational constraint in terms of the average welfare. Strong sustainability minimizes environmental impacts by implementing the inter-generational constraint in terms of each individual’s environmental status. Even if individuals are identified as having a fixed set of preferences (in weak sustainability and a-growth), well-informed preferences together with complete and perfect information are likely to be crucial for environmental issues. Imperfect competition (in de-growth) might be due to the lack of complete and perfect information. The lack of a monetary evaluation in terms of an equilibrium market price due to incomplete information, imperfect information, or imperfect competition implies the relevance of top-down vs. bottom-up decisions in de-growth and the adoption of a top-down approach in strong sustainability. The correct evaluation of externalities in a-growth requires perfect information about future generations’ (well-informed) preferences. The correct evaluation of capital reductions in de-growth requires complete and perfect information on the current generation’s (well-informed) preferences.

2.1.1 Weak sustainability

Weak sustainability can be defined as a development that meets the needs of (representative individuals of) the present generation without compromising the ability of (representative individuals of) future generations to meet their own needs (Dietz and Neumayer, 2007). Its main features can be summarized as follows: the objective units are the average human needs in at least three incommensurable dimensions (i.e., economic, social, and environmental); equity as each individual’s needs in current and future generations have the same importance, but because the analysis is based on representative individuals, the comparison is only inter-generational (not intra-generational); efficiency as intra-generational Pareto efficiency based on equilibrium prices and inter-generational Pareto efficiency based on constraints for current and future needs; and the constraint unit is the comprehensive amount of capitals (i.e., perfect substitution is possible among natural, manufactured, human, and social capitals).

Note that weak sustainability relies on unlikely absolute decoupling since there are no constraints on population growth (Biely et al., 2018). Moreover, it aims to maximize welfare and is based on instrumental rationality (i.e., on average). Finally, introducing ecological constraints under the weak sustainability paradigm (e.g., tipping points, uncertainties, and resilience), because the results are disliked in terms of environmental status, is an ad hoc modification of its logical framework that hides the ethical approach behind the weak sustainability paradigm (Irwin et al., 2016).

The main ethical assumptions behind weak sustainability (i.e., intergenerational efficiency in terms of welfare) are (a) consequentialism, (b) welfarism, (c) individualism, (d) rationality, (e) efficiency, (f) equity as the same value attached to each individual’s welfare and (A) complete information, (B) perfect information, (C) no externalities, (D) perfect competition, (E) welfare of future generations at least equal to welfare of current generation, and (F) perfect substitution of different types of capitals. Note that weak sustainability amounts to the Ramsey (1928) model, where the social discount rate is 0.

The main ethical implications of weak sustainability are environmental sustainability (i.e., the environmental status is consistent with social values and dynamics) and monetary evaluation of the environmental status (i.e., an equilibrium price is attached to each natural item from which human beings obtain some welfare). Note that environmental sustainability is distinguished from ecological sustainability here, where the environmental status is consistent with ecological functioning and dynamics.

2.1.2 A-growth

A-growth can be defined as an ecological and economic strategy that focuses on indifference to or neutrality about the economic (GDP) growth as a non-robust and unreliable indicator of social welfare and progress due to the many neglected non-market transactions (e.g., informal activities and relationships) and the many unpriced environmental effects (e.g., long-term impacts of nuclear power or plastic production; Van den Bergh, 2010). Its main features can be summarized as follows: the objective unit is the average human welfare; equity as each individual’s welfare in current and future generations has the same importance, but because the analysis is based on representative individuals, the comparison is only inter-generational (not intra-generational); efficiency as intra-generational Pareto efficiency based on equilibrium prices that include environmental externalities and inter-generational Pareto efficiency based on constraints for current and future welfare; and the constraint unit is the comprehensive amount of capitals (i.e., there is a perfect substitution among natural, produced, human, and social capitals).

Note that both rich and poor people will oppose policies that threaten their real incomes via an increase in prices (Shao, 2020). Moreover, different increases in prices, which result from different levels of internalization of environmental impacts, will produce different changes in production sectors and rich and poor members of society. Finally, information campaigns to educate the adult population or environmental education to inform the young population can produce only long run behavioral and structural changes, together with technological and scale changes, based on relative and absolute decoupling, respectively (Kallis, 2011).

The main ethical assumptions behind a-growth (i.e., intergenerational efficiency pursued by technological changes) are the weak sustainability assumptions plus the absence of C (i.e., the presence of externalities). The main ethical implications of a-growth are the weak sustainability implications plus internalized prices (i.e., equilibrium prices include the non-compensated impacts of pollution production and resource use on current and future generations’ welfare).

2.1.3 De-growth

De-growth can be defined as an ecological and economic perspective based on a socially sustainable and equitable reduction (and eventually stabilization) of the quantities of materials and energy that a society extracts, processes, transports, distributes, consumes, and returns back to the environment as waste (Kallis et al., 2010). Its main features can be summarized as follows: the objective unit is the individual human welfare; equity as each individual achieves the same minimum welfare level so that both intra- and inter-generational equities are achieved; efficiency is unimportant since the focus is on the possible inequitable costs of the transition toward smaller quantities; and the constraint units are some alternative amounts of capitals (i.e., there is only a partial substitution among natural, produced, human, and social capitals).

Note that the reduced investment in cleaner technologies in the short run due to smaller production and profits will lead to a larger production of pollution in the long run at a reduced economic scale (Hanaček et al., 2020). Moreover, the selection of produced capital to be reduced cannot be based on market forces or on voluntary choices by consumers or producers, so many private goods must be replaced by public goods. Finally, de-growth requires institutional changes toward eco-villages, co-housing, consumer–producer cooperatives, and non-monetary exchange systems (Cosme et al., 2017).

The main ethical assumptions behind de-growth (i.e., intergenerational equity pursued by value changes) are the a-growth assumptions plus absence of (e) (i.e., efficiency), equity (f) as a minimum of each individual’s welfare, absence of (A) complete information, (B) perfect information, (D) perfect competition, and (F) perfect substitution of different types of capitals. The main ethical implications of de-growth are the absence of environmental sustainability and physical evaluation of the environmental status.

2.1.4 Strong sustainability

Strong sustainability can be defined as a development that allows (each individual in) future generations to access the same amount of natural resources and the same status of the environment as (each individual in) the current generation, where natural and physical or social capitals are complementary but not interchangeable (Jain and Jain, 2013). Its main features can be summarized as follows: the objective units are capitals in at least three main incommensurable dimensions (i.e., economic, social, and environmental); efficiency is disregarded because the environmental goals are considered more important than all other goals; equity as each individual has access to the same amount of natural and other types of capital, so both intra- and inter-generational equity are achieved; and the constraint units are many alternative amounts of capitals (i.e., no substitution is allowed between natural capital and the produced, human, or social capitals due to the intrinsic value of nature).

It is difficult to distinguish the critical capital that must be preserved from non-critical natural capital (Hickel, 2020). Moreover, technological progress is disregarded, although this could imply a smaller sustainability burden. Finally, strong sustainability must be combined with measures to reduce inequality since redistribution of rights to use resources will be required (Haskell et al., 2021).

The main ethical assumptions behind strong sustainability (i.e., intergenerational equity in terms of the environmental status) are the de-growth assumptions plus equity (e) as each individual’s access to the same environmental status and an intergenerational constraint in terms of the environmental status. The main ethical implications of strong sustainability are the de-growth implications plus a specified environmental status as the reference level to minimize ecological impacts. Note that this amounts to the maximization of ecological continuity in Holling (1973), Yi and Jackson (2021) and Li et al. (2020) models if the specified environmental status is an ecologically resilient equilibrium.

In summary, social continuity amounts to weak sustainability with efficiency (i.e., it maximizes inter-generational total welfare) if the social discount rate is 0; in contrast, ecological continuity amounts to strong sustainability with equity (i.e., it minimizes inter-generational resource inequality) if the reference environmental status meets the conditions for resilience. Note that population growth affects both the ecological equilibrium and the economic equilibrium. Indeed, as for the ecological equilibrium, total ecosystems could move from a stable to an unstable level in the short run and toward an insufficient level in the long run. As for the economic equilibrium, per capita capital in the long run could be too large in terms of its temporal discount rate and capital decay rate.

2.2 Mathematical representations of the sustainability paradigms

From the perspective of an average individual, weak sustainability can be depicted as follows:

UF=E/θFαFUC=E/θαEβUFγ

Where UF and UC are the per capita utility levels of the future and current generations, respectively; E* and E are the per capita sustainable and current use of Earth’s resources, respectively, at the current global population; θF (i.e., θF = E* / XF with XF the future production of goods and services) and θ (i.e., θ = E / X with X the current production of goods and services) are production technologies available to future and current generations, respectively; αF and α are the consumption preferences of the future and current generations, respectively; and β and γ are the concerns for nature and future generations that characterize the current generation, respectively.

Note that β refers to the current environmental status without minimum thresholds since this concern is for nature per se, not for an equilibrium environmental status. Moreover, weak and strong sustainability are the baselines for the other equations, and thus, WS and SS are not included in the variable names. Finally, γ refers to the future generation’s utility without minimum thresholds since this concern is for the future generation per se, not for an equitable future generation utility.

From the perspective of an average individual, a-growth can be depicted as follows:

UF,AG=E/θAGαFUC,AG=E/θαEβUF,AGγ    (1)

Or

UF,AG    (1cur)=E/θAGαFUC,AG=E/θAGαEβUF,AGγ

with

θAG=θE/E<θ    (2)

and

EE
Where θAG is the improved production technology advocated by a-growth. In other words, the current generation predicts the conditions that will prevail for the future generation in terms of production technologies and bears the transition costs to a more efficient technology (i.e., θAG < θ) that allows the future generation to sustainably consume at the same level as the current generation (i.e., E*/θAG = E/θ) by paying higher prices or achieving lower welfare (i.e., UC,AG < UC), where the future welfare is not smaller than the current welfare (i.e., UF,AG ≥ UC,AG) and where the current consumption is smaller than the future consumption (i.e., E*/θAG > E*/θ) if the technological transition is not implemented until the future (i.e., inequality 1fut) or the current consumption is the same as the future consumption (i.e., E*/θAG = E/θ) if the technological transition is implemented starting in the current period (i.e., inequality 1cur). That is, two extreme contexts are conceivable and mathematically formalized by numerically analyzing intermediate contexts.

Note that the future generation is not concerned about the environment under a-growth (i.e., βF = 0) since the future generation is in an environmentally steady state. Moreover, the maximum transition cost that the current generation is willing to pay amounts to the opportunity cost to achieve sustainability (i.e., UCUC,AG), where sustainability is pursued for ethical reasons (i.e., a duty to future generations) and nature has instrumental value (i.e., it is evaluated in terms of welfare; Zagonari, 2020a). Finally, the future generation is not concerned about the future generation (i.e., γF = 0) since the future generation is in a socially steady state.

From the perspective of each single individual, de-growth can be depicted as follows:

UF,DG=E/θαDGUC,DG=E/θαDGEβUF,DGγ    (3)

with

αDG=αlnE/θ/lnE/θβlnE/E/lnE/θ    (4)

and

EE

Where αDG is the consumption preference advocated by de-growth. In other words, the current generation predicts the conditions that will prevail for the future generation in terms of consumption preferences and attaches a different value to the current consumption level (i.e., αDG ≠ α) to achieve the same welfare at a sustainable (smaller) consumption level (i.e., E/θ > E*/θ), where the current consumption equals the future consumption (i.e., E/θ = E*/θ) and the future welfare is not smaller than the current welfare (i.e., UF,DG ≥ UC,DG). That is, a single context is conceivable and mathematically formalized.

Note that using UC = UF,DG instead of UC,DG = UC to solve for αDG replicates weak sustainability. Moreover, we will focus on changes in consumption preferences by keeping changes in the concern for nature (∆β) and future generations (∆γ) as alternative scenarios. Finally, using UC,DG = UF,DG instead of UC,DG = UC to solve for αDG replicates a-growth.

From the perspective of each single individual, strong sustainability can be depicted as follows:

EE

Note that θAG from equality 2 satisfies the condition for weak sustainability, in which the technological transition is implemented in the future if ln [θ] ≥ [1–β/(αγ)] ln [E]. Moreover, weak sustainability, a-growth, and de-growth assume that UF cannot be smaller than UC to avoid forcing the future generation to bear the sustainability burden (e.g., technology improvements funded by public debt). Finally, αDG from equality 4 satisfies the condition for strong sustainability by definition since it includes E = E*.

3 Results

In this section, we rely on the following realistic assumptions to support the analytical results:

1. Production technologies and consumption preferences of the future generation are weighted averages of the production technologies and consumption preferences of current generations in developed and less-developed countries, for which the weights are the current relative populations (i.e., the proportions of the total global population in developed and less-developed countries). This accounts for historical legacies and traditions.

2. The changes in consumption preferences required by de-growth are proportional to the initial level of preferences in developed and less-developed countries [i.e., (αN,t + 1 – αN,t)/αN,t = (αS,t + 1 – αS,t)/αS,t where N and S stand for developed and less-developed countries, respectively]. This depicts an equitable social cost for changes in consumption preferences.

3. Technology improvements required by a-growth are proportional to the initial technology levels in developed and less-developed countries [i.e., (θN,t + 1 – θN,t)/θN,t = (θS,t + 1 – θS,t)/θS,t where N and S stand for developed and less-developed countries, respectively]. This depicts an equitable economic cost for improved technology.

4. The perspective of an average individual is depicted by referring to both developed and less-developed countries properly weighted in terms of their relative populations, whereas the perspective of each single individual is depicted by separately referring to representative individuals in developed and less-developed countries.

5. The environmental transition starts during the current generation (i.e., E = E*) to depict the urgency of environmental sustainability, with a sustainable consumption preference implemented in the current period, but with options for the sustainable production technology: it can be totally implemented in the current period, totally implemented in the future period, or partially implemented in both periods.

6. Sustainability is based on inter-generational equity in terms of welfare in weak sustainability, a-growth, and de-growth (e.g., Aristotle or Harsanyi equity as teleological ethics grounded on duty to future generations, where it is assumed that actions have a goal: Aristotle in eudemonic terms based on flourishing and Harsanyi in utilitarian terms based on welfare, but both focused on human beings from an average person’s perspective), but in terms of the environment in strong sustainability (e.g., Kant or Rawls equity as deontological ethics grounded on duty to future generations, where it is assumed that actions are performed for their own sake rather than based on their consequences: Kant in terms of freedom and Rawls in terms of resources, but both focused on human beings from a per-capita perspective).

Note that technology improvements or value changes in current generations in developed and less-developed countries will affect the production technologies and consumption preferences of the future generation (Van den Bergh et al., 2019). Moreover, the equitable distribution of social and economic costs solves the problem created by referring to average representative individuals. Finally, nature has instrumental value in weak sustainability, a-growth, and de-growth, but intrinsic value in strong sustainability (Zagonari, 2021).

Some teleological ethics are based on duty to future generations (e.g., Aristotle and Harsanyi); some deontological ethics are based on duty to future generations (e.g., Kant and Rawls);

In this section, we rely on the following real parameter values for the numerical results (Footprint Network, 2023; World Bank, 2023):

1. QN = ENN is the production function in developed countries (N for northern hemisphere countries, for simplicity), with θN representing the technology that transforms the environmental status into goods and services (i.e., θN = 5.74/36.727 = 0.156 ha ecological footprint [EF]/thousand US$ [GDP]). Similarly, for less-developed countries (S for southern hemisphere countries, for simplicity): QS = ESS (i.e., θS = 2.14/8.216 = 0.260 ha ecological footprint [EF]/thousand US$ [GDP]).

2. UN = (QNαN) (EN-βN)(UFγN) is the utility function for developed countries, with αN the utility from consumption of goods and services, βN the concern for the environmental status, and γN the concern for future generations, where parameters of Cobb–Douglas utility functions represent the proportion of the individual’s income spent on a given life aspect (i.e., its relative importance). Let αN = 0.6, βN = 0.1, and γN = 0.1, by referring to the individual average expenditure on consumption as a percentage of GDP (i.e., the household final consumption expenditures (% of GDP) in the World Bank dataset is used as the per-capita importance attached to consumption by assuming that this percentage is shared by all household members), the individual average expenditure on environmental protection as a percentage of GDP (i.e., the national expenditures on environmental protection (% of GDP) in the World Bank dataset is used as the per-capita concern for the environmental status by assuming that this percentage is supported by all country citizens), and the individual average expenditure on research and development as percentages of GDP (i.e., the domestic expenditures on research and development (% of GDP) in the World Bank dataset is used as the per-capita concern for future generations by assuming that this percentage is shared by all country citizens) in OECD countries, respectively (i.e., the average values based on the World Bank dataset from 2000 to 2020). Similarly, for less-developed countries: US = (QSαS) (ES-βS)(UFγS). Let αS = 0.75, βS = 0.05, and γS = 0.05.

3. QF = E*F and UF = QFαF are the production and utility functions for future generations, with θF = pN θN + pS θS, E* = 1.7 ha, and αF = pN αN + pS αS, with pN = 0.18 and pS = 0.82 representing the proportions of the world population in developed and less-developed countries, respectively.

Note that I have assumed perfect inter-generational equity for all sustainability paradigms and no intra-generational equity for weak sustainability and a-growth (i.e., these sustainability paradigms adopt the perspective of an average individual). Next, the subscript N (northern hemisphere) is used to label parameters for OECD countries, and the subscript S (southern hemisphere) is used for non-OECD countries, with full recognition that this approach ignores some exceptions.

In summary, strong sustainability refers to sustainability in terms of an individual’s use of Earth’s resources (i.e., EN ≤ EF, ES ≤ EF); de-growth refers to sustainability in terms of both individual welfare and use of Earth’s resources (i.e., EN ≤ EF, ES ≤ EF, UN ≤ UF, US ≤ UF); a-growth refers to sustainability in terms of both average welfare and use of Earth’s resources (i.e., pN EN + pS ES = EC ≤ EF, pN UN + pS US = UC ≤ UF); and weak sustainability refers to sustainability in terms of average welfare (i.e., UC ≤ UF). In other words, weak and strong sustainability differ to the greatest extent among the four paradigms.

Using these assumptions and data, sustainability is not achieved under a-growth, since UF = 4.444 < UC = 6.251 and E* = 1.7 < EC = 2.788. A technology improvement in both developed and less-developed countries should be achieved to meet E*AG = EC/θ and UF,AG ≥ UC,AG (i.e., E = E* is included in this condition).

In particular, from E*AG = EC/θ (equality 2), the use of resources must decrease (i.e., technological improvement TI = 1 + ∆θ < 1) if

TI=EF/EC<1    (5)
Since EF = E* = 1.7 and EC = 2.788. Thus, environmental efficiency must increase. Numerically, ∆θ = −0.39 = 1.7/2.788–1 = 0.61–1. Next, from UF,AG = UC,AG (inequalities 1cur and 1fut), the level of consumption must decrease (i.e., TI = 1 + ∆θ > 1) if:
lnTI=1β/αγlnEFlnθ>0    (6)

or

lnTI    (6fut)=lnEFlnθαlnθαβlnEF/α1γ>0

Thus, if technological improvement occurs in the current period, the current generation must decrease its consumption level to avoid achieving greater welfare than the future generation. In contrast, if technological improvement occurs in the future period, the current generation can increase its consumption level without achieving a larger welfare than the future generation. Numerically, ∆θ = +2.51 from Equation 6cur and ∆θ = −0.16 from Equation 6fut.

Note that consumption is more likely to decrease (i.e., ∆θ > 0) if the concern for nature is small (i.e., small β) and the production technology is environmentally efficient (i.e., small θ), the consumption preference is large (i.e., large α), the concern for the future generation is large (i.e., large γ), and the world’s population is small (large EF). Moreover, UF,AG = 6.483, UC,AG (current implementation) = 7.593, UC,AG (future implementation) = 5.204 (i.e., UF,AG > UC,AG only if the technological transition occurs in the future period). Finally, under weak sustainability, sustainability is not achieved since UF = 4.444 < UC = 6.251. Achieving weak sustainability will require a reduction of the current welfare by 29% since UF = 0.71 UC. This is larger than the 24% reduction required under a-growth, in which technological improvement is implemented.

Under de-growth, sustainability is not achieved, since UN = 8.265 > UF = 4.444, US = 5.808 > UF = 4.444, EN = 5.74 > EF = 1.7, and ES = 2.14 > EF = 1.7. A change in consumption preferences in both developed and less-developed countries should be espoused to achieve UN* = UN and US* = US. That is, EN = EN* = EF and ES = ES* = EF are included under these conditions. In particular, from equality 4, consumption preferences must decrease in developed countries (i.e., value change of α in developed countries VCAN = 1 + ∆αN < 1) and in less-developed countries (i.e., value change of α in less-developed countries VCAS = 1 + ∆αS < 1) if:

VCAN<1lnEN<αN2βNlnEFαN1αNlnθN    (7N)/αNβN
VCAS<1lnES<αS2βSlnEFαS1αSlnθS    (7S)/αSβS

Numerically, ∆αN = −0.66 and ∆αS = −0.87. Next, from inequality 3, consumption preferences must decrease in developed countries (i.e., value change of α in developed countries VCAN = 1 + ∆αN < 1) and in less-developed countries (i.e., value change of α in less-developed countries VCAS = 1 + ∆αS < 1) if:

VCAN=βNVCBNlnEF    (8N)/αNlnEF/θN+αWγNVCGN1lnEF/θW<1
VCAS=βSVCBSlnEF    (8S)/αSlnEF/θS+αWγSVCGS1lnEF/θW<1

Where VCBS and VCBS are the value changes of β in developed and less-developed countries, respectively, VCGS and VCGS are the value changes of γ in developed and less-developed countries, respectively, and W represents the world (global) value based on the weighted populations, with:

αW=pNαN+pSαS
θW=pNθN+pSθS

Numerically, ∆αN = −0.56 and ∆αS = −0.66.

Note that from UN = UF and US = UF, we can also obtain unfeasible solutions: ∆αN = −0.64 and ∆αS = −0.78. Moreover, UF,DG = 1.204, UC,DG (developed countries) = 1.600, UC,DG (less-developed countries) = 1.165 (i.e., UF,DG > UC,DG only in less-developed countries). Finally, under strong sustainability, sustainability is not achieved since EN = 5.74 > E* = 1.7 and ES = 2.14 > E* = 1.7. Achieving strong sustainability will require a reduction of current consumption of Earth’s resources by 71% in developed countries and by 21% in less-developed countries.

The main analytical and empirical results are summarized in Table 2. Note that, under a-growth, it is assumed that the maximum transition costs that the current generation is willing to pay (i.e., 22,880 billion US$ = 24% of world GDP) is enough to move from θ to θAG. For example, the Italian government funded an ecological transition with 10 billion € per year for the next 6 years, which amounts to around 0.6% of the yearly Italian GDP (i.e., 1/40 of 24%).

Table 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Summary of the analytical and numerical results and their achievability.

Under the combination of a-growth and de-growth, if the technological transition occurs in the current period (i.e., conditions in 6cur, 8N, and 8S are combined), the following relationship between changes in the consumption preferences (VCAcur) and technology improvement (TI) must be met (9cur):

VCAcur=VCBβN+βSβSγNVCG+βNγSVCGlnEFαNln°/θNαNγSVCGln°/θNαSln°/θS+αSγNVCGln°/θS

With ° = EF/TI and where VCB is the value change of β in both developed and less-developed countries and VCG is the value changes of γ in both developed and less-developed countries.

Under the combination of a-growth and de-growth, if the technological transition occurs in the future period (i.e., conditions in 6fut, 8N, and 8S are combined), the following relationship between the change in consumption preferences and technology improvement must be met (9fut):

VCAfut=VCBβN1γSVCG+βSγNVCG1lnEF&lnEF+αNγSVCG1lnθN+αS1γNVCGlnθS
lnTIfut=@+pNVCG#+pSVCG§lnEF+αNβSlnθNαSβNlnθSαNpN+αSpSβSβSγNVCG+βNγSVCG1

Where

&=αN1γSVCG+αSγNVCG1
@=αS(βN+pSβSβNy=αN(βS+pNβNβS
#=βSγNβNγS
§=βNγSβSγN

Note that because condition 9cur combines the conditions in inequalities 1 and 3, it allows cultural changes in the conditions for a-growth and technological changes in the conditions for de-growth.

Figure 1 depicts as curves the combinations of conditions for a-growth (inequality 1cur) and for de-growth (inequality 3) to produce 9cur. Figure 1 also depicts as points the solutions for a-growth (inequality 1fut) and for de-growth (inequality 3) to produce 9fut (i.e., ∆α = 0.602–1 at a given β and γ, but ∆α = 0.903–1 if β is increased by 50%, ∆α = 0.318–1 if γ is increased by 50%, while ∆θ = 0.901–1). Note that the conditions in equality 2 for a-growth and 4 for de-growth are depicted by values smaller than 1 for 1 + ∆θ and 1 + ∆α, respectively (i.e., a technology improvement if ∆θ < 0 for a-growth and a consumption preference change if ∆α < 0 for de-growth).

Figure 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. The relationship between the improvements in production technology (∆θ < 0) and the changes in consumption preferences (∆α < 0) is required to achieve both strong and weak sustainability. Legend: Blue curve and point for β and γ at current levels. Red curve and point for γ at current levels, but increased β. Gray curve and point for β at current levels, but increased γ. Notes: Blue curve for β and γ at current levels in developed and less-developed countries with ∆θ and ∆α occurring in the current period. Red curve for γ at current levels, but β increased by 50% in developed and less-developed countries with ∆θ and ∆α occurring in the current period. Gray curve for β at current levels, but γ increased by 50% in developed and less-developed countries with ∆θ and ∆α occurring in the current period. Blue point for β and γ at current levels in developed and less-developed countries, with ∆α occurring in the current period but ∆θ occurring in the future period. Red point for γ at current levels, but β increased by 50% in developed and less-developed countries, with ∆α occurring in the current period but ∆θ occurring in the future period. Gray point for β at current levels, but γ increased by 50% in developed and less-developed countries, with ∆α occurring in the current period but ∆θ occurring in the future period.

Note that, by mathematical continuity, if the technological transition is implemented between the current and the future periods, the required ∆α and ∆θ will lie between the curve for a given color and the corresponding colored point in each scenario. In particular, the condition for weak sustainability is met since UC = 6.251 < 6.483 = UF,AG if ∆α = 0 and ∆θ = −0.39, whereas the conditions for strong sustainability are met by definition. Moreover, a larger concern for the environment (i.e., with β increased by 50% in both developed and less-developed countries) favors the fulfillment of the conditions in equalities 4 and 2 (i.e., a smaller ∆α is allowed for a given ∆θ), whereas a larger concern for the future generation (i.e., with γ increased by 50% in both developed and less-developed countries) complicates the fulfillment of the conditions in equalities 4 and 2 (i.e., a larger ∆α is required for a given ∆θ). Finally, a current technological improvement lets us achieve sustainability at a smaller change in consumption preferences than a future technological improvement for any magnitude of technological improvement (i.e., the curve for a given color is above the corresponding colored point in each scenario). In particular, a trade-off between technological improvement and a change in consumption preferences is relevant only for a current technological improvement (i.e., the required ∆α for a future technological improvement can be read on alternative curves for ∆θ = 0).

4 Discussion

In the introduction, environmental sustainability is argued to be a practical issue (i.e., the new technologies suggested by a-growth and the new values suggested by de-growth must be feasible). In addition, environmental sustainability is claimed to be an interdisciplinary issue (i.e., the achievement of a sustainable equilibrium requires a compromise between economic and ecological criteria).

With regard to the primary purpose of this study (i.e., possible synergies between a-growth and de-growth to achieve weak and strong sustainability), the main results of this study support the following statements:

• A-growth requires relative decoupling (i.e., an increase in Q at a given E or a decrease in E at a given Q) rather than absolute decoupling (i.e., both an increase in Q and a decrease in E; e.g., Kemp-Benedict, 2018; Wu et al., 2018; Frodyma et al., 2020; Haberl et al., 2020).

• Alternative conditions for de-growth (i.e., UC = UF,DG and UC,DG = UF,DG) are less demanding than the condition required for “happy” de-growth (i.e., UC = UC,DG; e.g., Büchs and Koch, 2019; Akizu-Gardoki et al., 2020).

By combining the conditions for a-growth and de-growth, the present study achieved the following insights:

• Sustainability is an ethical issue more than a technological issue (i.e., it can be achieved by a value change, but it cannot be achieved by a technological improvement).

Some environmental ethics favor a solution toward sustainability (i.e., concern for nature), whereas other environmental ethics decrease the likelihood of sustainability (i.e., concern for future generations).

In other words, implementing both technology improvements and value changes makes a-growth rely on relative rather than absolute decoupling and makes de-growth require realistic rather than unrealistic changes in consumption preferences.

Note that sustainability as an ethical issue to a greater extent than a technological issue implies that sustainability is an institutional problem. Emphasis should be put on institutions that shape the rules of interactions (conventions, norms, and legal rules) and institutions that aggregate the values of societies (communication, treatment, and representation of complexity). Next, the ethical concern for nature as more favorable than the ethical concern for future generations implies that religious and secular institutions fostering any environmental sensitivity should be supported. Think of inter-religious dialog on environmental precepts, for example, a focus on trusteeship and parsimony in Islam, maintaining equilibrium for every single organism in Hinduism, and avoiding pain for sentient animals in Buddhism (Zagonari, 2020b; Zagonari, 2023). Similarly, think of education for environmental responsibility at different education levels (i.e., from elementary pupils to university students) and at different environmental scopes (i.e., from local to global problems), for example, education about the environment, education through the environment, and education for the environment (Kopnina, 2020; Rousell, 2020).

In addition, with regard to the secondary purpose of this study (i.e., possible linkages and interactions between ethical assumptions and implications), the main features of the theoretical model combining a-growth and de-growth can be summarized as follows: the objective unit is the average welfare (i.e., like in weak sustainability and a-growth); intra-generational efficiency is disregarded (i.e., like in de-growth and strong sustainability); intra-generational equity is disregarded (i.e., like in weak sustainability and a-growth); and the constraint unit is the per-capita environmental status (i.e., like in de-growth and strong sustainability).

The present study has the following methodological weaknesses:

• It depicts an individual perspective by referring to representative individuals in developed and less-developed countries. However, the analysis can be performed at a deeper level of detail if the required data are available.

• The burdens that must be borne by developed and less-developed countries to achieve sustainability are based on equal percentage losses. However, the analysis can be performed with different criteria if equity is preserved.

The present study has the following methodological strengths:

• The four main sustainability paradigms are included in a single theoretical framework.

• Sustainability conditions were validated using real-world data.

Note that the lack of unconditional analytical solutions due to the many parameters that are involved is irrelevant since numerical solutions based on real data are essential to solve such a practical problem. Next, sensitivity analysis is not required since the analytical models are based on production and utility functions, which are continuous in both variables and parameters, while the numerical results are depicted in a graphical framework which is based on continuous changes in parameters.

5 Conclusion

The purpose of this study was to test whether synergies were possible between a-growth and de-growth to achieve weak sustainability and strong sustainability as two theoretically distinct sustainability paradigms. The results show that a-growth is impossible whether the technological improvement occurs in the current period or the future period (due to the inconsistent technological changes that are required), whereas de-growth is unfeasible (due to the huge change in consumption preferences that are required). However, a combination of a-growth and de-growth was feasible, and it brought the weak and strong sustainability solutions closer together. In other words, the practical similarities between a-growth and de-growth (e.g., reduced working hours) should be stressed rather than ideological differences (e.g., efficiency in a-growth and equity in de-growth).

In summary, a-growth and de-growth have two different goals (efficiency and equity, respectively) and two different units (welfare based on the instrumental value of nature and the environmental status based on the intrinsic value of nature, respectively), although they both refer to the duty to future generations. A-growth adds externalities with respect to weak sustainability, whereas de-growth defines equity in terms of the minimum individual’s welfare. In de-growth, value changes (∆α) enable the achievement of an ecological stable equilibrium (E(0)) at a smaller loss in terms of welfare by attaching a larger value to a good environmental status. This value change amounts to the internalization of the environmental status in a-growth, although it implies the loss of individual’s identity assumed by a-growth (i.e., each individual as a set of fixed preferences). In a-growth, technological changes (∆θ) attach a smaller value to consumption in terms of the environmental status by enabling the achievement of a given level of welfare from consumption at a better environmental status. This technological change favors the satisfaction of the relative decoupling assumption in de-growth, although it requires the presence of complete and perfect information assumed by a-growth (i.e., the types of capitals to be focused on are properly identified). In combining a-growth and de-growth, the present study achieves intergenerational efficiency in terms of welfare (i.e., WFG (E(0)) ≥ WCG (E(0))) and the intergenerational equity in terms of the environmental status (i.e., E = E(0)). Note that WFG ≥ WCG does not imply the social stability as defined in the economic models, whereas E = E(0) does not imply the ecological resilience as defined in the ecological models.

Data availability statement

Publicly available datasets were analyzed in this study. This data can be found at: http://data.worldbank.org and http://www.footprintnetwork.org.

Author contributions

FZ: Writing – original draft, Writing – review & editing.

Funding

The author declares that no financial support was received for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

Akizu-Gardoki, O., Kunze, C., Coxeter, A., Bueno, G., Wiedmann, T., and Lopez-Guede, J. M. (2020). Discovery of a possible well-being turning point within energy footprint accounts which may support the de-growth theory. Energy Sustain. Dev. 59, 22–32. doi: 10.1016/j.esd.2020.09.001

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Arrow, K., and Debreu, G. (1954). Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Econometrica. 22, 265–290.

Google Scholar

Biely, K., Maes, D., and van Passel, S. (2018). The idea of weak sustainability is illegitimate. Environ. Dev. Sustain. 20, 223–232. doi: 10.1007/s10668-016-9878-4

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Böhmelt, T., and Zhang, M. (2023). Supporting environmental protection in good and bad economic circumstances. Environ. Politics. 32, 1–19. doi: 10.1080/09644016.2023.2200653

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Büchs, M., and Koch, M. (2019). Challenges for the de-growth transition: the debate about wellbeing. Futures 105, 155–165. doi: 10.1016/j.futures.2018.09.002

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Cosme, I., Santos, R., and O’Neill, D. W. (2017). Assessing the degrowth discourse: a review and analysis of academic degrowth policy proposals. J. Clean. Prod. 149, 321–334. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2017.02.016

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

D'Amato, D., Droste, N., Winkler, K. J., and Toppinen, A. (2019). Thinking green, circular or bio: eliciting researchers' perspectives on a sustainable economy with Q method. J. Clean. Prod. 230, 460–476. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2019.05.099

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Dietz, S., and Neumayer, E. (2007). Weak and strong sustainability in the SEEA: concepts and measurement. Ecol. Econ. 61, 617–626. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2006.09.007

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Drews, S., Savin, I., and van den Bergh, J. C. J. M. (2019). Opinion clusters in academic and public debates on growth-vs-environment. Ecol. Econ. 157, 141–155. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2018.11.012

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Fitzpatrick, N., Parrique, T., and Cosme, I. (2022). Exploring degrowth policy proposals: a systematic mapping with thematic synthesis. J. Clean. Prod. 365:132764. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2022.132764

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Footprint Network. (2023). Available at: https://www.footprintnetwork.org (Accessed June 30, 2023).

Google Scholar

Frodyma, K., Papież, M., and Śmiech, S. (2020). Decoupling economic growth from fossil fuel use—Evidence from 141 countries in the 25-year perspective. Energies 13:6671. doi: 10.3390/en13246671

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gugushvili, D. (2021). Public attitudes toward economic growth versus environmental sustainability dilemma: evidence from Europe. Int. J. Comp. Sociol. 62, 224–240. doi: 10.1177/00207152211034224

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Gunderson, R. (2018). Degrowth and other quiescent futures: pioneering proponents of an idler society. J. Clean. Prod. 198, 1574–1582. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2018.07.039

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Haapanen, L., and Tapio, P. (2016). Economic growth as phenomenon, institution and ideology: a qualitative content analysis of the 21st century growth critique. J. Clean. Prod. 112, 3492–3503. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2015.10.024

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Haberl, H., Wiedenhofer, D., Virág, D., Kalt, G., Plank, B., Brockway, P., et al. (2020). A systematic review of the evidence on decoupling of GDP, resource use and GHG emissions, part II: Synthesizing the insights. Environ. Res. Lett. 15:065003. doi: 10.1088/1748-9326/ab842a

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hanaček, K., Roy, B., Avila, S., and Kallis, G. (2020). Ecological economics and de-growth: proposing a future research agenda from the margins. Ecol. Econ. 169:106495. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.106495

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hankammer, S., and Kleer, R. (2018). Degrowth and collaborative value creation: reflections on concepts and technologies. J. Clean. Prod. 197, 1711–1718. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2017.03.046

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Haskell, L., Bonnedahl, K. J., and Stål, H. I. (2021). Social innovation related to ecological crises: a systematic literature review and a research agenda for strong sustainability. J. Clean. Prod. 325:129316. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2021.129316

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Heikkinen, T. (2020). A study of degrowth paths based on the von Neumann equilibrium model. J. Clean. Prod. 251:119562. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2019.119562

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Hickel, J. (2020). The sustainable development index: measuring the ecological efficiency of human development in the Anthropocene. Ecol. Econ. 167:106331. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.05.011

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Holling, C. S. (1973). Resilience and stability of ecological systems. Annu. Rev. Ecol. Syst. 4, 1–23. doi: 10.1146/annurev.es.04.110173.000245

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Irwin, E. G., Gopalakrishnan, S., and Randall, A. (2016). Welfare, wealth, and sustainability. Ann. Rev. Resour. Econ. 8, 77–98. doi: 10.1146/annurev-resource-100815-095351

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Jain, P., and Jain, P. (2013). Sustainability assessment index: a strong sustainability approach to measure sustainable human development. Int J Sust Dev World 20, 116–122. doi: 10.1080/13504509.2013.766910

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kallis, G. (2011). In defence of de-growth. Ecol. Econ. 70, 873–880. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2010.12.007

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kallis, G., Kerschner, C., and Martinez-Alier, J. (2010). The economics of de-growth. Ecol. Econ. 84, 172–180. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2012.08.017

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kemp-Benedict, E. (2018). Dematerialization, decoupling, and productivity change. Ecol. Econ. 150, 204–216. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2018.04.020

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Khmara, Y., and Kronenberg, J. (2020). Degrowth in the context of sustainability transitions: in search of a common ground. J. Clean. Prod. 267:122072. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2020.122072

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Kopnina, H. (2020). Education for the future? Critical evaluation of education for sustainable development goals. J. Environ. Educ. 51, 280–291. doi: 10.1080/00958964.2019.1710444

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lehmann, C., Delbard, O., and Lange, S. (2022). Green growth, a-growth or degrowth? Investigating the attitudes of environmental protection specialists at the German environment agency. J. Clean. Prod. 336:130306. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2021.130306

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Li, T., Dong, Y., and Liu, Z. (2020). A review of social-ecological system resilience: mechanism, assessment and management. Sci. Total Environ. 723:138113. doi: 10.1016/j.scitotenv.2020.138113

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Lou, X., Lin, Y., and Li, L. M. W. (2022). Predicting priority of environmental protection over economic growth using macroeconomic and individual-level predictors: evidence from machine learning. J. Environ. Psychol. 82:101843. doi: 10.1016/j.jenvp.2022.101843

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Nadeau, R., Lachapelle, E., and Bergeron, T. (2022). Environment versus economy policy preferences: follow-up questions reveal substantial heterogeneity within the environmental coalition. Int. J. Public Opinion Res. 34:031. doi: 10.1093/ijpor/edac031

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

O'Neill, D. W. (2015). The proximity of nations to a socially sustainable steady-state economy. J. Clean. Prod. 108, 1213–1231. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2015.07.116

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Paulson, L., and Büchs, M. (2022). Public acceptance of post-growth: factors and implications for post-growth strategy. Futures 143:103020. doi: 10.1016/j.futures.2022.103020

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Ramsey, F. P. (1928). A mathematical theory of saving. Econ. J. 38, 543–559. doi: 10.2307/2224098

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Rousell, D. (2020). Doing little justices: speculative propositions for an immanent environmental ethics. Environ. Educ. Res. 26, 1391–1405. doi: 10.1080/13504622.2018.1517408

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Salas-Zapata, W. A., Ríos-Osorio, L. A., and Mejía-Escobar, J. A. (2017). Social-ecological resilience and the quest for sustainability as object of science. Environ. Dev. Sustain. 19, 2237–2252. doi: 10.1007/s10668-016-9852-1

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Sandberg, M., Klockars, K., and Wilén, K. (2019). Green growth or degrowth? Assessing the normative justifications for environmental sustainability and economic growth through critical social theory. J. Clean. Prod. 206, 133–141. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2018.09.175

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Savin, I., Drews, S., and van den Bergh, J. (2021). Free associations of citizens and scientists with economic and green growth: a computational-linguistics analysis. Ecol. Econ. 180:106878. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2020.106878

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Shao, Q. (2020). Paving ways for a sustainable future: a literature review. Environ. Sci. Pollut. Res. 27, 13032–13043. doi: 10.1007/s11356-020-08247-9

PubMed Abstract | Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Strunz, S., and Bartkowski, B. (2018). Degrowth, the project of modernity, and liberal democracy. J. Clean. Prod. 196, 1158–1168. doi: 10.1016/j.jclepro.2018.06.148

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Van den Bergh, J. C. J. M. (2010). Externality or sustainability economics? Ecol. Econ. 69, 2047–2052. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2010.02.009

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Van den Bergh, J. C. J. M. (2011). Environment versus growth—a criticism of “de-growth” and a plea for “a-growth”. Ecol. Econ. 70, 881–890. doi: 10.1016/j.ecolecon.2010.09.035

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

van den Bergh, J. C. J. M., Savin, I., and Drews, S. (2019). Evolution of opinions in the growth-vs-environment debate: extended replicator dynamics. Futures 109, 84–100. doi: 10.1016/j.futures.2019.02.024

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

World Bank (2023). Available at: https://data.worldbank.org (Accessed June 30, 2023).

Google Scholar

Wu, Y., Zhu, Q., and Zhu, B. (2018). Comparisons of decoupling trends of global economic growth and energy consumption between developed and developing countries. Energy Policy 116, 30–38. doi: 10.1016/j.enpol.2018.01.047

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Yi, C., and Jackson, N. (2021). A review of measuring ecosystem resilience to disturbance. Environ. Res. Lett. 16:106878. doi: 10.1088/1748-9326/abdf09

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zagonari, F. (2020a). Environmental sustainability is not worth pursuing unless it is achieved for ethical reasons, nature – Palgrave. Communications 6, 1–8. doi: 10.1057/s41599-020-0467-7

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zagonari, F. (2020b). Comparing religious environmental ethics to support efforts to achieve local and global sustainability: empirical insights based on a theoretical framework. Sustain. For. 12, 1–36. doi: 10.3390/su12072590

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zagonari, F. (2021). Religious and secular ethics offer complementary strategies to achieve environmental sustainability, nature – humanities and social sciences. Communications 8, 1–13. doi: 10.1057/s41599-021-00802-0

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Zagonari, F. (2022) Environmental ethics, sustainability and decisions, literature problems and suggested solutions, New York: Springer.

Google Scholar

Zagonari, F. (2023). Pope Francis vs. patriarch Bartholomew to achieve global environmental sustainability: theoretical insights supported by empirical results. Sustain. For. 15:13789. doi: 10.3390/su151813789

Crossref Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: ethics, strong sustainability, weak sustainability, de-growth, a-growth, technological change, value change, OECD countries

Citation: Zagonari F (2024) Both de-growth and a-growth to achieve strong and weak sustainability: a theoretical model, empirical results, and some ethical insights. Front. Sustain. 5:1351841. doi: 10.3389/frsus.2024.1351841

Received: 07 December 2023; Accepted: 12 February 2024;
Published: 01 March 2024.

Edited by:

Carlo Ingrao, University of Bari Aldo Moro, Italy

Reviewed by:

Kiara Winans, Oregon Department of Environmental Quality (DEQ), United States
Maksims Feofilovs, Riga Technical University, Latvia
Rebecca Hanes, National Renewable Energy Laboratory (DOE), United States

Copyright © 2024 Zagonari. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Fabio Zagonari, fabio.zagonari@unibo.it

ORCID: Fabio Zagonari, https://orcid.org/0000-0002-9872-8731

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.