- 1Dipartimento di Fisica and MECENAS, Università di Bari, Bari, Italy
- 2INFN, Sezione di Bari, Bari, Italy
- 3Institute of Physics, Faculty of Physics, Astronomy and Informatics, Nicolaus Copernicus University, Toruń, Poland
We analyze the multitime statistics associated with pure dephasing systems repeatedly probed with sharp measurements, and search for measurement protocols whose statistics satisfy the Kolmogorov consistency conditions possibly up to a finite order. We find a rich phenomenology of quantum dephasing processes which can be interpreted in classical terms. In particular, if the underlying dephasing process is Markovian, we find sufficient conditions under which classicality at every order can be found: this can be reached by choosing the dephasing and measurement basis to be fully compatible or fully incompatible, that is, mutually unbiased bases (MUBs). For non-Markovian processes, classicality can only be proven in the fully compatible case, thus revealing a key difference between Markovian and non-Markovian pure dephasing processes.
1 Introduction
Quantum processes are fundamentally different from classical ones: therefore, a proper understanding of the classical–quantum boundary, involving the identification of the genuinely quantum features of physical systems—those which cannot be simulated and/or reproduced by any system satisfying the laws of classical physics—is of particular importance (Żurek, 2003; Joos et al., 2004; Schlosshauer, 2005; Horodecki et al., 2009; Modi et al., 2012). Aside from its intrinsic theoretical interest, this boundary also has practical implications for quantum technologies: taking advantage of the underlying quantum nature of the natural world, e.g. quantum correlations (Modi et al., 2012) and coherence (Żurek, 2003; Streltsov et al., 2017), is the key of diverse technological proposals such as quantum teleportation, cryptography or computation (Nielsen and Chuang, 2000). A groundbreaking example is provided by the violation of Bell inequalities by quantum correlations (Bell, 2011); among many other such examples, we may point out quantum states of light corresponding to non-positive values of their Wigner function (or singular Glauber–Sudarshan P-representation) (Mandel and Wolf, 1995; Gardiner and Zoller, 1999).
A thorough analysis of physical systems must involve both their free evolution as well as their behavior under external interventions; this information can be encoded by a multitime statistics of joint probability distributions (correlation functions). In this framework, it was proposed in (Smirne et al., 2019; Milz et al., 2020) to define the classicality of quantum systems in terms of the classicality of their multitime statistics. Let us briefly revise this approach. We shall consider a quantum system living on a Hilbert space
this map being, by construction, completely positive and trace preserving (CPTP). The map is said to be CP-divisible if it satisfies the additional property
We shall consider the idealized scenario in which such a system is repeatedly probed via sharp, identical and instantaneous measurements at times t1, … , tn, and evolves freely between each couple of consecutive measurements. This procedure brings about a family of time-continuous joint probability distributions (multitime statistics) defined as follows. Letting
with
holds, the statistics associated with a quantum system as described above will generally violate this condition. In this regard, notice that Eq. 3 essentially means that not performing a measurement at the time tj is equivalent to performing a measurement at the same time and then forgetting about its outcome—in other words, measurements do not affect the system, which is generally not true in the quantum realm. On the other hand, by the Kolmogorov extension theorem (Kolmogorov, 1933), Eq. 3 is satisfied if and only if there exist some classical stochastic process reproducing the full multitime statistics; in this case the results of the experiment may be consistently explained in the framework of classical physics, whence no genuinely quantum feature is exhibited by the system.
Because of that, following (Smirne et al., 2019; Milz et al., 2020), we shall adopt this definition: the process defined by the global Hamiltonian H, the initial state
• N-classical, if Eq. 3 is satisfied for all n = 1, … , N.
• classical, if Eq. 3 is satisfied for all
Interestingly, a quantum process with classical multitime statistics always satisfies the Leggett–Garg inequalities (LGI) (Leggett and Garg, 1985; Leggett, 2008; Emary et al., 2014), which can be interpreted as a temporal analog of Bell inequalities; a violation of LGI necessarily implies that the underlying process is genuinely quantum.
For an N-classical process, the intrinsically quantum nature of the system will only possibly emerge after N+1 measurements in the prescribed PVM, but will be effectively “hidden” otherwise—that is, N+1 is the minimal number of measurements that must be performed on the system in order to see a genuinely quantum behavior. Most importantly, all these definitions are strictly dependent on both the measurement PVM, the state
A particularly simple scenario is observed when the multitime statistics satisfies the Markov property:
with
thus reducing to only two consistency conditions; in particular, in the Markovian case, 3-classicality is sufficient for (hence equivalent to) classicality. It is also worth noting that the validity of the Markov property is ensured whenever the regression formula holds (Lax, 1963; Gardiner and Zoller, 1999), that is, when the full multitime statistics (2) induced by the system can be expressed in terms of the reduced dynamics alone:
conversely, if the statistics is Markovian and Eq. 7 holds for n = 1, 2, then Eq. 7 holds for all n.
While adopting in this paper these mathematical definitions of Markovianity and classicality, it should be stressed that both physical concepts have been variously identified with diverse, generally inequivalent, mathematical properties. We refer to the reviews (Breuer et al., 2016; Li et al., 2019a; Li et al., 2019b) for a general discussion about quantum non-Markovianity; various definitions of quantum Markovianity and the intricate relations between them are presented in (Rivas et al., 2014; Li et al., 2018), while we refer to (de Vega and Alonso, 2017) for an overview of various approaches to describe the dynamics of non-Markovian open systems, and (Chruściński, 2022) for the mathematical and physical properties of non-Markovian dynamical maps.
The definition adopted in this paper is closely related to the mathematical formulation of quantum Markov stochastic processes proposed in (Davies and Lewis, 1970; Lindblad, 1975; Accardi et al., 1982) (cf. also the review (Milz and Modi, 2021)) and closely related to the recent approach to quantum Markovianity proposed in (Pollock et al., 2018a; Pollock et al., 2018b; Milz et al., 2019), where the Markovianity of the corresponding process is characterized in terms of the factorization of the so-called quantum process tensor of the underlying quantum system, this property in turn being equivalent to the validity of quantum regression (Li et al., 2018). For a discussion of Markovianity based on the quantum regression formula see also (Guarnieri et al., 2014; Lo Gullo et al., 2014); exact results on the validity of quantum regression in simple models were found in (Lonigro and Chruściński, 2022a; Lonigro and Chruściński, 2022b; Chruściński et al., 2022).
Similarly, many other approaches to the problem of classicality of quantum systems can be found in the literature. For example, in (Chen et al., 2018) the quantum evolution of an open system represented by a dynamical map Λt,s is said to be classical it can be simulated by an ensemble of Hamiltonians {pk, Hk} on
with
In this paper we shall investigate the multitime statistics for a quantum system undergoing a pure dephasing evolution, focusing on the existence of particular choices of the initial state
The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we provide a brief introduction about dephasing processes, in particular recalling a simple characterization of Markovian dephasing processes. In Section 3 we show that a system initially prepared in a state which is diagonal in the dephasing basis, when measured with a proper class of unbiased bases with respect to the dephasing one, is 2-classical but generally not 3-classical; an analogous result is then shown to hold, under some conditions on the environment, for an arbitrary measurement basis if the initial state is the maximally mixed one. In Section 4 we finally focus on the Markovian scenario and find conditions under which, in this case, the system is in fact classical when measured with each of these unbiased bases. Final considerations are outlined in Section 5.
2 Dephasing-type systems
Reprising the notation of Section 1, we shall consider global Hamiltonians on
with
with
thus being dependent on a matrix-valued function which we shall refer to as the dephasing matrix of the process, crucially depending on the interplay between the block Hamiltonians
The multitime statistics describing repeated measurements with a given PVM
again with
Proposition 2.1. (Lonigro and Chruściński, 2022b). The dephasing system satisfies the regression equality (2) if and only if
with
While this claim is proven in (Lonigro and Chruściński, 2022b) for a standard dephasing channel (i.e., all projectors Ej being rank-one), its extension to the general case is immediate. Eq. 14 means that, for dephasing processes, the validity of the regression formula—and hence Markovianity—reduces to a factorization property of the n-time dephasing tensor in terms of 2-time tensors, i.e. dephasing matrices. This condition is clearly independent of the particular preparation–measurement protocol: the Markovianity of any dephasing process only depends on the initial environment state ϱB and the Hamiltonian H, without any dependence on either the initial system state
The hierarchy of conditions (14) has two important consequences. First of all, it contains the following condition
which, for time-independent Hamiltonians, implies, for some
and clearly means that the reduced dynamics induced by H must satisfy the semigroup property, whence Λt,s must be a GKLS semigroup (Gorini et al., 1976; Lindblad, 1976). However, keep in mind that this is only a necessary condition: counterexamples of dephasing semigroups blatantly violating regression can be easily constructed. However, while very restrictive, this condition is satisfied in (at least) one case of physical interest: by choosing H as the dephasing-type spin–boson model with flat form factor, and ϱB as the vacuum state of the boson field, the couple (H, ϱB) does indeed satisfy the full hierarchy (14), as shown in (Lonigro and Chruściński, 2022b).
Furthermore, Eq. 14 cannot hold in the commutative case—that is, when the Hamiltonians
for all values of the parameters: the reduced dynamics induced on
To conclude, for future convenience let us list here some elementary properties of the dephasing matrix and tensor.
Proposition 2.2. For every n and every value of the indices, we have
besides, in the case in which the dephasing is either Markovian or generated by commuting Hamiltonians, for every k = 1, … , n we have
That is: in the general case, all entries of the n-time dephasing tensor characterized by the nth couple of indices (jn, ℓn) having equal values can be evaluated by substituting the unitary map
3 Classical dephasing processes
We shall now search for particular preparation–measurement protocols which yield a classical or N-classical process. This will ultimately depend on the interplay between the two PVMs that enter the process:
• the dephasing PVM
• the measurement PVM
but in general may—and will—also depend non-trivially on the properties of the environment.
Clearly, if the two PVMs coincide, then the process is indeed classical—and shows a trivial dependence on time. Indeed, in this case we must set
thus obtaining an elementary process, independent of all times t1, … , tn, which is clearly classical: this is an obvious consequence of the fact that the measurement do not interfere at all with the dephasing. More generally, the same happens if the two PVMs are commuting. Clearly, a genuinely time-dependent (and generally non-classical) process can only be obtained when the two PVMs do not commute, that is, when the measurement is not fully compatible with the dephasing.
We may wonder whether there exist preparation–measurement protocols which yield time-dependent dephasing processes exhibiting a classical behavior, that is, satisfying the consistency condition 3) possibly up to some finite order, despite the fact that the system is measured with some PVM not fully compatible with its “natural” one. We shall start in this section by analyzing some of these configurations which ensure 2-classicality, and then proceed in Section 4 to investigate the Markovian case, where classicality at any order can be in fact achieved.
3.1 Classicality in the qubit case
We shall start from the case d = 2, that is, a qubit undergoing pure dephasing in some orthonormal basis {|e0⟩, |e1⟩} under the action of a global Hamiltonian H in the form
Let us consider a measurement basis
for some angles ϕ, θ. Up to global phases which do not affect the multitime statistics, the vectors (22)–(23) span all possible measurements on the qubit; up to a flip of the two basis vectors, it suffices to consider 0 ≤ θ ≤ π/2: in particular, the value θ = 0 yields the dephasing basis, while θ = π/4 yields (setting |mx(ϕ, π/4)⟩ ≡|mx(ϕ)⟩)
Importantly, for any value of ϕ we have |⟨mx(ϕ)|ej⟩|2 = 1/2 for all x, j = 1, 2: that is, the basis (24) and the dephasing basis are mutually unbiased bases (MUBs) (Wootters and Fields, 1989; Durt et al., 2010). In particular, the choices ϕ = 0 and ϕ = π/2 correspond respectively to the eigenvectors of the Pauli operators σx and σy, two choices of obvious practical relevance.
Choosing the initial state to be diagonal in the dephasing basis:
a long but straightforward calculation allows one to determine the 1-time and 2-time probability distributions associated to this preparation–measurement protocol. For any choice of θ and ϕ, one obtains
The above result, which does not depend on ϕ, corresponds to the product of a time-independent term ∝ sin 2θ sin 4θ encoding all information about the measurement, times a time-dependent term depending on the choice of initial state and the properties of the environment. 2-classicality is obtained, regardless the properties of the environment, in the cases θ = 0 (fully compatible measurement) and θ = π/4 (fully incompatible measurement). The calculation above clearly shows that, in the qubit case, there are no other possibilities to obtain 2-classicality without making further assumptions on the initial state of the system (the value of p) or on the properties of the environment.
Proposition 3.1. Let d = 2; consider an initial state
• θ = 0, that is, the measurement basis is fully compatible with the dephasing one;
• θ = π/4, that is, the measurement basis is fully incompatible (unbiased) with the dephasing one;
In all other cases, the process will fail the 2-classicality test: two measurements will be enough to reveal the non-classicality of the process. In particular, for any fixed choice of the initial state, the deviations from classicality will be maximal when sin 2θ sin 4θ is maximal: this happens for
We may wonder whether the cases listed in Proposition 3.1 are the only possible ones in which 2-classicality is achieved. An (almost) affirmative answer to this question can be obtained by making one of the following assumptions on the environment. Suppose that either the process is Markovian, or the Hamiltonians H0, H1 generating the environment dynamics, cf. Eq. 21, commute. In both cases, setting for brevity
by using Proposition 2.2 Eq. 27 simplifies as such:
Excluding the trivial case
Proposition 3.2. Let d = 2; consider an initial state
• θ = 0, that is, the measurement basis is fully compatible with the dephasing one;
• θ = π/4, that is, the measurement basis is fully incompatible (unbiased) with the dephasing one;
• p = 1/2, that is, the system is prepared in the maximally mixed state.
These results can be summarized as follows. Excluding the elementary case of a fully compatible measurement, preparation–measurement protocols yielding a genuinely time-dependent and 2-classical dephasing process do exist: one prepares the system in a state
This discussion clearly shows the distinguished role played by MUBs in the classicality of qubit dephasing processes; in fact, we will now see that similar properties hold in the general case d > 2.
3.2 Classicality vs. MUBs
Going beyond the qubit scenario, let us now consider a system of arbitrary dimension d. Suppose Ej = |ej⟩⟨ej| for some orthonormal basis
let us define
For ϕ = (0, … , 0), this is the discrete Fourier transform of the dephasing basis. Of course, since the vectors are uniquely associated to their projectors only up to a global phase, we have in fact d−1 free parameters (we may e.g. set ϕ0 = 0). This expression generalizes Eqs 24, 25; indeed, for any choices of the phases,
By Eq. 13, one easily computes the joint probability distributions associated with this protocol. For simplicity, hereafter we shall often abuse the notation by setting
In the cases n = 1, 2,
this structure being immediately generalizable to n-time probabilities, for example
Interestingly, in all cases only the sums on the indices j1 and ℓ1 carry a dependence on the phases ϕ0, … , ϕd−1 which appear in the definition Eq. 32 of the measurement basis.
Now, at the level of 2-time probability distributions, the only non-trivial consistency condition is the following:
since marginalizing over the last outcome always yields the 1-time probability. On the other hand, by Eq. 36, summing over x1 we have
and, in general, the quantities in Eq. 35, and Eq. 39 do not coincide. However, let us consider again the particular case in which the initial state
Proposition 3.3. Consider an initial state
Proof. Recalling that
this quantity being independent of time—indeed, independent of any parameter of the process but the dimension of the Hilbert space: the evolution is trivial because of the initial state being diagonal in the dephasing basis, and all outcomes are equally probable at any time due to the fact that the measurement and the dephasing basis are MUBs. Besides, by Eq. 39 one finds
where we have used the fact that
This result generalizes Proposition 3.1 to the qudit case: 2-classicality holds for any preparation–measurement protocol involving a diagonal state
Finally, notice that in general the results of Proposition 3.3 (as well as its qubit version) cannot be improved from 2-classicality to higher orders: a direct check shows indeed that, without further assumptions, the process is not 3-classical. We have a full family of quantum processes which are 2-classical but generally not classical: the quantum nature of the system will only emerge when taking into account the 3-time probability distribution, i.e., by performing three measurements on the system. By doing so, the particular features of the environment will play a fundamental role, crucially determining the statistics of the system and generally disrupting classicality. In this sense, we may say that the process exhibits, in general, a hidden non-classicality, only accessible with a sufficient number of measurements.
3.3 Classicality for maximally mixed initial state
In the qubit scenario, 2-classicality was shown to hold, other than by choosing the dephasing and measurement bases to be fully compatible or incompatible, also by simply preparing the system in the maximally mixed state. As it turns out, this property has, again, a simple extension to the qudit case.
We shall consider the general setting in which both the dephasing and the measurement PVMs,
where we used the properties EjEℓ = δjℓEj and
In general, this expression cannot be further simplified by using the property
Proposition 3.4. Consider the process with initial state
• if the process is Markovian;
• if the Hamiltonians
Proof. Recalling Proposition 2.2, in both cases listed above we have
Therefore, in both cases, Eq. 43 yields
and marginalizing
which is the same expression as in Eq. 42.
The above result generalizes what was already observed in the qubit case (cf. Proposition 3.2): choosing the initial state to be maximally mixed always ensures 2-classicality, no matter how the system is measured. Incidentally, for non-Markovian processes, this proposition provides an operational way of checking whether the dephasing process is generated by a commutative family of Hamiltonians—a property that cannot be checked by simply looking at the reduced dynamics of the process, no matter the choice of the initial state. Any violation of this condition signals the presence of non-commuting blocks.
Again, the argument does not work for higher orders: similar computations can be carried out when marginalizing on the last variable x1, but not for the remaining ones. For example:
Marginalizing over x1 correctly yields the 2-time probability distribution, but marginalizing over x2 does not. Again, we can thus construct examples of 2-classical processes which fail to be classical at higher orders.
4 Classical markovian dephasing processes
We shall now reprise the scheme presented in Section 3.2, i.e. a dephasing process on a basis
In this case, recalling the discussion in Section 1, classicality is equivalent to the fulfillment of the two Chapman–Kolmogorov equalities, the first one being satisfied because of Proposition 3.3. Consequently, the process will be classical at any order if and only if the following marginalizing condition for the 3-time probability distribution holds:
We will show that this happens in a particular case, starting from the qubit scenario and then discussing the general scenario.
4.1 Qubit case
Recall that, in the qubit case, the unbiased bases as defined by Eq. 32 are given by Eqs 24, 25.
Proposition 4.1. Let
is real-valued.
Proof. As discussed, classicality in this case is ensured if and only if Eq. 48 holds. For any initial state
while
whence
The sum between parentheses is equal to d = 2 when (j3−ℓ3) − (j2−ℓ2) is an integer multiple of d = 2, and zero otherwise. The quantity (j3−ℓ3) − (j2−ℓ2) can take values at most between ±2, whence the sum equals 2 whenever this quantity equals either −2, 0, 2, and is zero otherwise. That is,
We end up with
We can now compute the difference between the two-time probability and the marginalized three-time probability: noting that all terms with j3 = ℓ3 cancel out, and using the shorthand (Eq. 49) and the Markovianity property
therefore this quantity vanishes if and only if the phase is real, thus completing the proof.
The difference between the 2-time correlation function and the 3-time correlation function marginalized on its central variable is thus directly related to the magnitude of the imaginary part of the dephasing function φt,s. In particular, if the global Hamiltonian is time-independent, then
and thus
whence classicality holds if and only if ɛ = 0. We remark that, in the case in which H is a Markovian dephasing-type spin–boson model (i.e. with the spin–boson coupling being mediated by a flat form factor, cf. (Lonigro and Chruściński, 2022b)), ɛ corresponds to the excitation energy of the qubit. This means that the process is classical in the limit in which the excitation energy vanishes—that is, the difference between the energy levels of the qubit is negligible.
Finally, for completeness let us compute the whole 2-time and 3-time statistics in the Markovian qubit scenario under the assumption of a real dephasing function. In this case, we have explicitly
and one immediately checks that all consistency conditions are satisfied.
4.2 General case
A generalization of Proposition 4.1 holds in the general case,
Lemma 4.1. Let
with δjℓ being the Kronecker delta.
Proof. Given
obviously with all solutions being characterized by j = ℓ iff k = 0 and j ≠ ℓ iff k ≠ 0.
Now, the quantity in Eq. 60 corresponds to the cumulative number of solutions of the three equations
Suppose e.g. h > 0. Then, by Eq. 61, the first equation admits d−h solutions, the second one admits d−|h−d| = h solutions, and the third one does not admit solutions; whence Eq. 60 is proven. The same holds for h < 0.
Proposition 4.2. Let
for some real-valued function φt,s. Then the process is classical.
In words, in the larger-dimensional scenario classicality holds under the following, quite restrictive, requirement: all off-diagonal elements of the density operator in the dephasing basis must evolve in the same way—in particular, with real-valued dephasing factors.
Proof. Assume Eq. 63. The two-time probability is given by
As for the three-time probability, notice that Eq. 53 generalizes as
whence, by following analogous computations as in the qubit case,
where we have applied Lemma 4.1.
5 Conclusion
We have analyzed the multitime statistics associated with generic quantum dephasing processes, finding scenarios in which the family of probability distributions is either classical up to a finite order or exhibits a full-fledged classical character. In particular, excluding the case in which the system is probed via measurements compatible with the dephasing basis, a classical behavior emerges for a wide class of measurement bases which are unbiased with respect to the dephasing basis; in particular, in the Markovian case sufficient conditions for classicality at any order can be found. As a consequence of this property, the following dichotomy can be observed; classicality can be achieved in two very different scenarios: either the measurement system is fully compatible with the dephasing basis, or it is fully incompatible with it.
Besides, a simple and interesting link between classicality and the commutativity of the Hamiltonians which generate the dephasing dynamics: this means that, when preparing the system in the maximally mixed state, the corresponding process will be 2-classical, regardless the choice of the measurement basis, whenever these Hamiltonians commute; in the non-Markovian case, any violation of classicality at the level of 2-time correlation functions will be a witness of non-commutativity. More generally, while the commutativity between the Hamiltonians has no direct influence on the reduced dynamics of the system, it does have a potentially crucial role when taking into account the role of interventions on the system, since it implies a highly non-trivial constraint on the n-time dephasing tensor which affects the property of the multitime statistics of the process. A more systematic study of the role of commutativity in the properties of dephasing processes is highly desirable.
These results reveal a key difference between Markovian and non-Markovian dephasing processes. In the Markovian case, a genuinely time-dependent dephasing process can be fully classical, in the sense adopted in the present paper, modulo a proper choice of initial state and a suitable choice of measurement basis, i.e. any of the unbiased bases in Eq. 32. In the qubit case, this choice of basis is indeed necessary other than sufficient to obtain classicality; we conjecture that the same holds for the qudit case. Instead, in the non-Markovian case the same choices of initial state and measurement basis do not guarantee classicality: only 2-classicality is guaranteed. We may conjecture that, in the non-Markovian case, a pure dephasing process can only be classical, possibly modulo very special choices of initial state, if one performs a fully compatible measurement with respect to the dephasing basis—that is, no genuinely time-dependent dephasing process can ultimately “hide” its quantumness.
In this regard, we recall that, in (Smirne et al., 2019; Milz et al., 2020), an interesting characterization of classical Markovian processes was found: a Markovian process was found to be classical if and only if it can be reproduced by means of an initial system
where Δ = ∑xPx(⋅)Px denotes the completely dephasing channel with respect to the measurement basis. Importantly, both
which implies Eq. 67. Note that measuring the system with respect to an arbitrary MUB one creates quantum coherences with respect to the dephasing basis in an extreme manner: however, such generated coherences cannot be detected at a later time by means of the employed measurement basis.
Let us recall that, due to the seminal paper by Leggett and Garg (Leggett, 2008; Emary et al., 2014), a violation of classicality is understood as measurement invasiveness (impossibility to perform a measurement without altering the state of the system). Recently (Smirne et al., 2020) it was experimentally verified that the violation of the Kolmogorov conditions is proportional to the amount of quantum coherence (of the measured observable). Such connection between coherence and non-classicality was probed in a time-multiplexed optical quantum walk (Smirne et al., 2020) (cf. also (Emary et al., 2014) for other experiments testing the violation of Leggett-Garg inequalities).
To conclude, reprising the discussion in Section 1, it will be useful to compare our results to the ones in (Sakuldee and Cywiński, 2022). The authors, while still taking into account dephasing phenomena, analyze the different scenario in which the system is reset at its initial state after each measurement. With this approach, a simple and elegant characterization of classicality is found: using our nomenclature, the multitime statistics corresponding to a dephasing process which is repeatedly measured and reset to a given initial state is classical at any order if and only if the environment Hamiltonians
Finally, as a further connection between the two approaches, we observe that the authors of (Sakuldee and Cywiński, 2022) examine the situation in which the system is measured with the eigenbasis of the Pauli operators σx, σy, and propose the use of MUBs as a higher-generalization of such results—the very same scenario considered in this work, in which MUBs do indeed play a decisive role.
This brief discussion strongly hints at the existence of a deeper connection between the results of (Sakuldee and Cywiński, 2022) and those presented in this work; this shall be examined in the future.
Data availability statement
The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/Supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding authors.
Author contributions
All authors listed have made a substantial, direct, and intellectual contribution to the work and approved it for publication.
Acknowledgments
We acknowledge valuable discussions with Fattah Sakuldee and Lukasz Cywiński. DL was partially supported by Istituto Nazionale di Fisica Nucleare (INFN) through the project “QUANTUM” and by the Italian National Group of Mathematical Physics (GNFM–INdAM), and acknowledges support by MIUR via PRIN 2017 (Progetto di Ricerca di Interesse Nazionale), project QUSHIP (2017SRNBRK); he also thanks the Institute of Physics at the Nicolaus University in Toruń for its hospitality. DC was supported by the Polish National Science Center project No. 2018/30/A/ST2/00837.
Conflict of interest
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Publisher’s note
All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.
Footnotes
1For simplicity we shall mostly focus on the case in which the latter is time-independent, thus generating a homogeneous unitary propagator Ut,s = e−i(t−s)H on
2Since we are dealing with possibly unbounded operators, this is to be interpreted in the following sense:
References
Accardi, L., Frigerio, A., and Lewis, J. T. (1982). Quantum stochastic processes. Publ. Res. Inst. Math. Sci. 18, 97–133. doi:10.2977/prims/1195184017
Bell, J. S. (2011). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press.
Breuer, H. P., Laine, E. M., Piilo, J., and Vacchini, B. (2016). Colloquium: Non-Markovian dynamics in open quantum systems. Rev. Mod. Phys. 88, 021002. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.88.021002
Burgarth, D., Facchi, P., Garnero, G., Nakazato, H., Pascazio, S., and Yuasa, K. (2017). Can decay Be ascribed to classical noise? Open Syst. Inf. Dyn. 24, 1750001. doi:10.1142/s1230161217500019
Chen, H.-B., Gneiting, C., Lo, P.-Y., Chen, Y.-N., and Nori, F. (2018). Simulating open quantum systems with Hamiltonian ensembles and the nonclassicality of the dynamics. Phys. Rev. Lett. 120, 030403. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.120.030403
Chen, H.-B., Lo, P.-Y., Gneiting, C., BaeChen, J. Y.-N., and Nori, F. (2019). Quantifying the nonclassicality of pure dephasing. Nat. Commun. 10, 3794. doi:10.1038/s41467-019-11502-4
Chruściński, D. (2022). Dynamical maps beyond Markovian regime. Phys. Rep. 992, 1–85. doi:10.1016/j.physrep.2022.09.003
Chruściński, D., Hesabi, S., and Lonigro, D. (2022). On Markovianity and classicality in multilevel spin-boson models. arXiv:2210.06199 [quant-ph].
Davies, E. B., and Lewis, J. T. (1970). An operational approach to quantum probability. Commun. Math. Phys. 17, 239–260. doi:10.1007/bf01647093
de Vega, I., and Alonso, D. (2017). Dynamics of non-Markovian open quantum systems. Rev. Mod. Phys. 89, 015001. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.89.015001
Durt, T., Englert, B.-G., Bengtsson, I., and Życzkowski, K. (2010). On mutually unbiased bases. Int. J. Quantum Inf. 8, 535–640. doi:10.1142/s0219749910006502
Emary, C., Lambert, N., and Nori, F. (2014). Corrigendum: Leggett–Garg inequalities (2014 rep. Prog. Phys. 77 016001). Rep. Prog. Phys. 77, 039501. doi:10.1088/0034-4885/77/3/039501
Gneiting, C., Anger, F. R., and Buchleitner, A. (2016). Incoherent ensemble dynamics in disordered systems. Phys. Rev. A 93, 032139. doi:10.1103/physreva.93.032139
Gneiting, C., and Nori, F. (2017). Disorder-induced dephasing in backscattering-free quantum transport. Phys. Rev. Lett. 119, 176802. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.119.176802
Gneiting, C., and Nori, F. (2017). Quantum evolution in disordered transport. Phys. Rev. A 96, 022135. doi:10.1103/physreva.96.022135
Gorini, V., Kossakowski, A., and Sudarshan, E. C. G. (1976). Completely positive dynamical semigroups of N-level systems. J. Math. Phys. 17, 821. doi:10.1063/1.522979
Guarnieri, G., Smirne, A., and Vacchini, B. (2014). Quantum regression theorem and non-Markovianity of quantum dynamics. Phys. Rev. A 90, 022110. doi:10.1103/physreva.90.022110
Horodecki, R., Horodecki, P., Horodecki, M., and Horodecki, K. (2009). Quantum entanglement. Rev. Mod. Phys. 81, 865–942. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.81.865
Joos, E., Zeh, H. D., Kiefer, C., Giulini, D., and Kupsch, J. (2004). Decoherence and the appearance of a classical world in quantum theory. 2nd ed. Berlin: Springer.
Kolmogorov, A. N. (1933). “Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung,” in Foundations of the theory of probability (BerlinChelsea, New York, 1956: Springer).
Kropf, C. M., Gneiting, C., and Buchleitner, A. (2016). Effective dynamics of disordered quantum systems. Phys. Rev. X 6, 031023. doi:10.1103/physrevx.6.031023
Lax, M. (1963). Formal theory of quantum fluctuations from a driven state. Phys. Rev. 129, 2342–2348. doi:10.1103/physrev.129.2342
Leggett, A. J., and Garg, A. (1985). Quantum mechanics versus macroscopic realism: Is the flux there when nobody looks? Phys. Rev. Lett. 54, 857–860. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.54.857
Leggett, A. J. (2008). Realism and the physical world. Rep. Prog. Phys. 71, 022001. doi:10.1088/0034-4885/71/2/022001
Li, C. F., Guo, G. C., and Piilo, J. (2019). Non-Markovian quantum dynamics: What does it mean? EPL Europhys. Lett. 127, 50001. doi:10.1209/0295-5075/127/50001
Li, C. F., Guo, G. C., and Piilo, J. (2019). Non-Markovian quantum dynamics: What is it good for? EPL Europhys. Lett. 128, 30001. doi:10.1209/0295-5075/128/30001
Li, L., Hall, M. J. W., and Wiseman, H. M. (2018). Concepts of quantum non-markovianity: A hierarchy. Phys. Rep. 759, 1–51. doi:10.1016/j.physrep.2018.07.001
Lindblad, G. (1975). Completely positive maps and entropy inequalities. Commun. Math. Phys. 40, 147–151. doi:10.1007/bf01609396
Lindblad, G. (1976). On the generators of quantum dynamical semigroups. Commun. Math. Phys. 48, 119–130. doi:10.1007/bf01608499
Lo Gullo, N., Sinayskiy, I., Busch, T., and Petruccione, F. (2014). Non-Markovianity criteria for open system dynamics. arXiv:1401.1126 [quant-ph].
Lonigro, D., and Chruściński, D. (2022). Quantum regression beyond the Born-Markov approximation for generalized spin-boson models. Phys. Rev. A 105, 052435. doi:10.1103/physreva.105.052435
Lonigro, D., and Chruściński, D. (2022). Quantum regression in dephasing phenomena. J. Phys. A Math. Theor. 55, 225308. doi:10.1088/1751-8121/ac6a2d
Mandel, L., and Wolf, E. (1995). Optical coherence and quantum optics. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.
Milz, S., Egloff, D., Taranto, P., Theurer, T., Plenio, M. B., Smirne, A., et al. (2020). When is a non-markovian quantum process classical? Phys. Rev. X 10, 041049. doi:10.1103/physrevx.10.041049
Milz, S., Kim, M. S., Pollock, F. A., and Modi, K. (2019). Completely positive divisibility does not mean markovianity. Phys. Rev. Lett. 123, 040401. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.123.040401
Milz, S., and Modi, K. (2021). Quantum stochastic processes and quantum non-Markovian phenomena. PRX Quantum 2, 030201. doi:10.1103/prxquantum.2.030201
Modi, K., Brodutch, A., Cable, H., Paterek, T., and Vedral, V. (2012). The classical-quantum boundary for correlations: Discord and related measures. Rev. Mod. Phys. 84, 1655–1707. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.84.1655
Nielsen, M. A., and Chuang, I. L. (2000). Quantum computation and quantum information. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pollock, F. A., Rodriguez-Rosario, C., Frauenheim, T., Paternostro, M., and Modi, K. (2018). Non-Markovian quantum processes: Complete framework and efficient characterization. Phys. Rev. A 97, 012127. doi:10.1103/physreva.97.012127
Pollock, F. A., Rodriguez-Rosario, C., Frauenheim, T., Paternostro, M., and Modi, K. (2018). Operational Markov condition for quantum processes. Phys. Rev. Lett. 120, 040405. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.120.040405
Rivas, Á., Huelga, S. F., and Plenio, M. B. (2014). Quantum non-markovianity: Characterization, quantification and detection. Rep. Prog. Phys. 77, 094001. doi:10.1088/0034-4885/77/9/094001
Sakuldee, F., and Cywiński, L. (2020). Relationship between subjecting the qubit to dynamical decoupling and to a sequence of projective measurements. Phys. Rev. A 101, 042329. doi:10.1103/physreva.101.042329
Sakuldee, F., and Cywiński, L. (2022). Statistics of projective measurement on a quantum probe as a witness of noncommutativity of algebra of a probed system. Quantum Inf. process. 21, 244. doi:10.1007/s11128-022-03576-9
Schlosshauer, M. (2005). Decoherence, the measurement problem, and interpretations of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 76, 1267–1305. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.76.1267
Smirne, A., Egloff, D., Garcia Diaz, M., Plenio, M. B., and Huelga, S. F. (2019). Coherence and non-classicality of quantum Markov processes. Quantum Sci. Technol. 4, 01LT01. doi:10.1088/2058-9565/aaebd5
Smirne, A., Nitsche, T., Egloff, D., Barkhofen, S., De, S., Dhand, I., et al. (2020). Experimental control of the degree of non-classicality via quantum coherence. Quantum Sci. Technol. 5, 04LT01. doi:10.1088/2058-9565/aba039
Streltsov, A., Adesso, G., and Plenio, M. B. (2017). Colloquium: Quantum coherence as a resource. Rev. Mod. Phys. 89, 041003. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.89.041003
Wootters, W. K., and Fields, B. D. (1989). Optimal state-determination by mutually unbiased measurements. Ann. Phys. (N. Y). 191, 363–381. doi:10.1016/0003-4916(89)90322-9
Keywords: classical stochastic processes, quantum processes, quantum dephasing, quantum decoherence, Kolmogorov conditions, Markovian processes
Citation: Lonigro D and Chruściński D (2022) On the classicality of quantum dephasing processes. Front. Quantum Sci. Technol. 1:1090022. doi: 10.3389/frqst.2022.1090022
Received: 04 November 2022; Accepted: 28 November 2022;
Published: 19 December 2022.
Edited by:
Subhashish Banerjee, Indian Institute of Technology Jodhpur, IndiaReviewed by:
Bassano Vacchini, University of Milan, ItalyH. Z. Shen, Northeast Normal University, China
Copyright © 2022 Lonigro and Chruściński. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Davide Lonigro, davide.lonigro@ba.infn.it; Dariusz Chruściński, darch@fizyka.umk.pl