Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychiatry, 09 August 2023
Sec. Computational Psychiatry
This article is part of the Research Topic From Brain Priorities to Brain Modeling View all 6 articles

Modeling intentionality in the human brain

  • Independent Researcher, Athens, Greece

This paper is focusing on a rather neglected issue that concerns both aspects of philosophy and neurobiology in relation to the concept of intentionality. Intentionality is concerned with the ‘directedness’ or ‘aboutness’ of mental phenomena towards an object. Despite the fact that in philosophy both concepts of aboutness and directedness are conceptually identical with intentionality, a careful neuroscientific approach can demonstrate that these two phenomena represent two distinct conceptual and neurobiological aspects of intentionality with complementary functions. We described the interaction between a series of intentionality and pathogenetic psychobiological factors, the corresponding brain topography, and the resulting clinical manifestation and psychopathology. A permanent failure of intentionality dominates in psychosis, which includes an inappropriateness of the intentional object or connection, from the outset, or even from the prodromal phase of the disorder. Affective disorders may result from imprecise interoceptive prediction error signals, due to a confused identification of the intentional object. In suicidal patients there is an emotional intentionality failure, characterized by an absence of intentional object or a loss of conscious access to normal intentional objects. We may model an ‘intentional system’ as a higher order system, with a monitoring and regulatory role attributed to the brain and behavior. Also, we may consider mental disorders as the result of a radical disruption of intentionality, due to an inappropriateness or lack of the intentional object or due to an inappropriate connection in some points of the suggested brain pathways of intentionality.

Introduction

The term ‘intentionality’ was coined in the 13th century by St Thomas Aquinas, with the aim of Christianizing Aristotle’s biological concept by utilizing this concept to describe the process by which human beings and animals thrust their existence into the world. According to Brentano, intentionality is considered to be the directedness of mental phenomena towards an object (1). Husserl argues that every aspect of consciousness contains intentionality, in the sense that all these aspects are always directed towards something and are always about something (2), whilst according to Heidegger, the subject is structured with intentionality within its own self (3). Spinoza emphasizes that every being by its very nature tends to maintain its existence, by naming this tendency ‘conatus’, a Latin term that denotes will and appetite. In his philosophy, “what a thing is” becomes identical with its power, its energy, its force of life (4). According to Searle, intentionality is that characteristic of the mind with which mental states are directed at or deal with (about) or refer to or are aimed at states of the world (5). His theory also raises the problem of the intentionality of perception, by using the expression relating to the “experience of” and emphasizing that the preposition “of” in the “experience of” is precisely the “of” in the “intentionality of.”

Human intentionality is closely associated with consciousness and agency. Intentionality appears to have strong connections to both consciousness as well as evolutionarily selected functions, by constituting the initiation, construction, and direction of behavior within the world. Consciousness consists in the proposition that X is a state of consciousness if and only if there is “something it is like” for the organism to be in that state (6). Several theories of consciousness are based on a connectionist approach, having a model of large webs with interacting neurons, fundamental to understand brain functionality, cognition, and behavior, while recently have been identified fundamental principles common to theories of consciousness, both classical and quantum (7). The Husserlian correlation between acts of thought – noesis – and intentional objects of thought – noema – becomes the first step in the constitution of analyses of consciousness. The feeling that one is the owner of his or her mental states consists in a contingent relation between consciousness and its intentional objects (8). We will say that intentional states (intentionally) represent their intentional contents (9). In saying that the mind is intentional, phenomenologists imply that the mind is relational. ‘Being in the-world’ (Heidegger) and the ‘lived body-environment’ (Merleau-Ponty) are different ways of articulating this kind of relation. The later emphasized the body as the primary site of knowing the world, demonstrating a corporeity of consciousness, as much as an intentionality of the body (10).

The naturalistic theory of intentionality

Naturalizing intentionality in terms of tracking or functional roles is one of the most important goals in philosophy of mind (9). ‘Naturalization’ and ‘naturalism’ are frequently conflated with ‘reduction’ and ‘reductive physicalism’. Many philosophers think that metaphysical naturalism entails meta-philosophical naturalism, i.e., the view that philosophy is continuous with the empirical science (11). According to the metaphysical naturalism, the scientific version of naturalism, the view that human mind is part of the natural world, necessarily entails epistemological naturalism, i.e., the view that natural scientific understanding is the only way of making things in the natural world intelligible (12).

Neander’s main assumptions is that most intentionality is ultimately derived from the underived (or original) intentionality of nonconceptual sensory-perceptual representations and perhaps some core concepts (13). Millikan’s theory (14) explains intentionality in mainly biological and teleological terms within this context, by using the interpretive sources of natural selection. What thoughts and desires are ‘about’ is ultimately determined by why they have been chosen, namely what advantages they provided to ancestors once upon a time. Central to these teleological approaches is the idea that the production of mental representations needs to benefit the organism if not always, at least in some occasions. This is the rationale behind the very existence of the representational mechanisms historically carried over generations of organisms. However, in a teleological and behavioral view, free will is not something people essentially have or do not have, while the kind of actions that are typically seen as free are the same as those seen as self-controlled (15). The various degrees of freedom depend on our knowledge of the causal goings-on that affect us. The more we know, such as the various physical, biological, psychological, or sociological factors that affect our lives, can be considered as an expression of our rationality and consequently of our freedom (12, 16).

Biologists view every form of intentionality as the result of evolution through natural selection. ‘Intrinsic intentionality’ and ‘nano-intentionality’ have been proposed as microscopic forms of aboutness, which are innate in eukaryotic cells that include a goal-directed ability to adaptively respond to new situations. This nano-intentionality is a necessary precondition for the capacity of human organisms to have full-blooded intentional thoughts (17). A recently suggested estimator theory (18) is based upon an internal probabilistic process that is contained in every organism, which can estimate the evolutionary robustness of each organism. According to this theory, a naturalistic theory of intentionality must describe and explain the following properties of intentionality: (a) Directedness must be “many-to-one,” i.e., a single entity may simultaneously be the target of many prepositional pieces; (b) Directedness may be “one-to-many,” i.e., a simple prepositional piece may simultaneously be the target of multiple entities; and (c) a capacity should exist for contingent errors, as well as systematic errors, which implies that a prepositional object must have the capacity to misrepresent (see Figure 1).

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. The interactions between the environmental and the pathogenetic psychobiological and intentionality factors, following by the involved brain regions, as well as the resulting clinical manifestation and psychopathology.

Intentionality and domain specificity within the brain

Human intentionality has a profoundly biological origin, whereby people have to produce intentional states (1923). At micro-level, the so called ‘micro-intentionality’ or ‘nano-intentionality’ of cells, as a form of ‘intrinsic intentionality’, is extended by analogy in hearts or kidneys, which can have “derived” intentionality (17). In accordance with the theory of ‘autopoiesis’ (24), the essence of ‘perspectivity’ is a relational process taking place between the system and its world, characterized by relationality and transcendence (25). At macro-level, we are thinking about ‘macro-intentionality’ and the emergence of collective knowledge and cumulative culture in animals, humans and machines (26). Active exploration of an organism’s spatial environment and predation were the most important selective pressure to create learning (27), while the ‘first’ brains were formed and became powerful prediction machines (28). Findings in human brains indicate that the Default Mode Network, perhaps centralized to the dmPFC, primes the intentional stance to social stimuli. Default Mode Network activity in between moments of cognitive activity seems to be the biological basis for the powerful human tendency to adopt the intentional stance (29).

Despite the fact that in philosophy the concepts of ‘aboutness’ and ‘directedness’ are conceptually identical with ‘intentionality’, a careful neuroscientific observation is in a position to indicate that these two phenomena represent two distinct components with a complementary function. It has no relation with the proposed views of intentionality, such as linguistic, derived or original intentionality (9), but with inner parts or structure of intentionality. In a recent paper, using relative neuroscientific findings (19, 3033), we provided an overview of possible pathways of an ‘intentional system’ in the brain, according to the conceptual and neurobiological traces of ‘aboutness’ and ‘directedness’ in the brain and in the behavior (34) (Table 1).

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. The main conceptual features of the aboutness’ and directedness’ aspects of intentionality.

Firstly, we suggested a common conceptual and neurophysiological ground for both ‘intentionality’ and ‘conatus’, through the study of the complementary and interacting functions of aboutness and directedness. We hypothesized an ‘aboutness sub-system’, which has been designed having the ability to ‘be about things’, to ‘predict’ and ‘be present’ in the world. Also, it has been designed having the ability to support ‘homoeostasis’, through an ‘ego-centric’ mode of operation. On the other hand, the ‘directedness sub-system’ has been designed so as to be able to direct existence “toward” the world, by having a close relationship with the conative elements of appetite, creation and renewal. Also, to support ‘reward’ behavior, in parallel with an ‘allo-centric’ way of function.

The vestibular system is the first sensory system to begin development in utero, and it is the first fully developed by the eighth month of intrauterine life (35). It is a sensory system that never “sleeps,” since gravity impacts any movements in relation to the world around us. Anecdotal observations indicate that whirling by Sufi semazen-artists or mindful movements by yogic practitioners profoundly impact vestibular stimulation, supporting a state of presence and tranquility (36). Conceptually, ‘aboutness’ seems to be strongly associated with the vestibular network. We hypothesize that aboutness sub-system is primarily based upon the vestibular network and the interoceptive system, where thalamus and insula are the main hubs. The directedness sub-system is mainly based upon the dopaminergic network and the orexigenic/anorexigenic neurons connected to hypothalamus (34).

An intentional transfer of information is central to human communication (22). The parietofrontal pathway relays bottom-up target information for sensory-driven reflexive movement, while the frontoparietal pathway relays top-down target information that is cognitive rule-based (37). Also, the predictive processing framework indicates existence of two types of prediction error neurons: positive prediction error neurons, subtracting a top-down prediction from the sensory input, and negative prediction error neurons, subtracting sensory input from the top-down prediction (38). In a similar way, and having in mind the rest aspects of intentionality function, we hypothesize the aboutness sub-system has a bottom-up direction of information flow, running mostly in a non-conscious way. On the other hand, the information flow is top-down in the directedness sub-system, running mostly in a conscious way (34). It has been proposed that some of consciousness in unreflective actions can be characterized by intentionality being inhibited. In these cases of ‘inhibited intentionality’ an agent feels a diminished sense of authorship in relation to self-understanding (39).

Dennett emphasized that the intentional stance of things is a strong position, which could be developed into a reliable intentionality theory (40). Based on the philosophical, social and neuroscientific findings, as well as the hypothesized aspects, features and functions of intentionality, we may suggest an intentional system, as a higher order system, which plays a supervisory role in both the brain and behavior. The cybernetic model (41) emphasizes on intention and includes the lack of awareness of ones’ goals, which leads to disorders of willed action, the lack of awareness of intention, which leads to movement disorders, and the lack of awareness of intentions of others, which leads to paranoid delusions and hallucinations. The theories of metarepresentation involves mainly output mechanisms, like the frontal cortex, while the input mechanism involves posterior brain systems, including the parietal lobe (42). The inferior part of the posterior parietal cortex seems to be a crucial area for the updating of information in the working memory and the BA 46 & 9/46 encode it into an “abstract/symbolic form,” in order to achieve the controlled monitoring in the active mnemonic process. This system has the capacity to hold symbolically coded information in an active state, in order to supervise the between them relation and their relation with the intended programmed behavior (43).

At the social level, Mead develops William James’ distinction between the ‘I’ and the ‘Me’. He postulated ‘Me’ is the social self and the ‘I’ is the response to the ‘Me’. The ‘I’ is the response of an individual to the attitudes of others, while the ‘Me’ is the organized set of attitudes of others which an individual assumes. ‘Me’ is the object and ‘I’ is the subject. ‘Me’ is the known and ‘I’ is the knower (44). Extending, we can hypothesize that ‘aboutness’ is corresponding to ‘Me’, which is an organized set of attitudes, and continuously enriching by the ‘directedness of ‘I’, i.e., the response of an individual to the attitudes of others. Moreover, we can also hypothesize that ‘aboutness’ contains the priors, including the predisposing, i.e., the distal factors, while ‘directedness’ contains the accelerating or proximal factors of the self.

Modeling the failure of intentionality in the human brain: implications for mental disorders

Inappropriatness of an intentional object or connection

The mind functions normally to the extent where its intentional objects and connections are appropriate. Bolton speculated whether mental disorders could be considered as a group of radical failures of intentionality. He pointed that a failure in intentionality that is due to the inappropriateness of intentional object or a corresponding connection, or even the absence of an intentional object, can lead to a mental disorder (45, 46). In the philosophy of mind, ‘aboutness’ is considered to be synonymous with intentionality, referring to the concept where a phrase, image or action is on or about a certain object. If human intentionality is closely related to consciousness and agency, what could play the role of a specific network in the brain for the aboutness formation? Moreover, could an inappropriate intentional object or connection of that system result in a mental disorder? In the Table 2 are summarizing the failure of intentionality, the corresponding brain regions, the resulting clinical syndromes, and the possible therapeutic implications.

TABLE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Summarizing the failure of intentionality, the corresponding brain regions, the resulting clinical syndromes, and the possible therapeutic implications.

For Jaspers, schizophrenia principally refers to the loss of the basic sense of ownership and agency of one’s own experiences, thoughts, or actions (47). Corollary discharge, is a basic neurophysiological mechanism that is involved in sensory prediction and contributes to the distinction between self-generated and externally generated sensory information (48). This helps the organism to establish the difference between self and non-self (49) and to prevent self-induced desensitization (50). It has been argued that delusions and hallucinations is the result of the failure of corollary discharges to suppress self-generated inputs, resulting in the absence of “feelings of agency” in the ego-centric system, and in the compensatory enhancement of allo-centric priors (51). In addition, the salience network plays an important role in stimulus processing, attention, and the switching from the default network to the executive system. The structures involved are the anterior insula and the anterior cingulate cortex, whilst dysfunction of this network is considered to be involved in the development of various mental disorders (52, 53).

The intentional content of the visual experience in the Muller-Lyer illusion lines example comes into conflict with and is overridden by the intentional content of our beliefs. The perceiver has the same experience in the case of hallucinations, but there is no intentional object present (5). Schizophrenia patients showed a severe loss of the ability to detect internal bodily signals and to attribute them to themselves, while interoceptive accuracy was associated to patients’ positive symptomatology (54). The distinction between the correct and incorrect representation is often regarded as a central normative distinction and a capacity to misrepresent is often considered to be essential for representation: if there is no possibility of misrepresentation, there is no representation. This is connected to concerns with non-existent objects, where a capacity to misrepresent amounts to a basic capacity to represent non-existent objects (55). We may argue that a loss of both may exist in psychosis: namely, the intentional object and the capacity to misrepresent (18, 34). We may moreover suggest that a permanent disturbance of intentionality dominates in the negative syndrome of schizophrenia, which may include the inappropriatness of an intentional object or connection, from the outset, or even from the prodromal phase of the disorder (34, 56, 57).

The subjective experience in psychosis seems to be rooted in the disturbance of intentionality and diminished sense of agency (58), while their referential and persecutory ideation motivates inappropriate mentalizing when objective cues of intentionality are absent (59). Psychotis exhibit a striking bias on over attribute intentionality, and especially an inability to inhibit the automatic attribution of intentionality (60). Schizotypy was found to be associated with perceiving ambiguous actions as intentional, particularly in social contexts (61), Also, a hyper-intentionality state has been found to be prominent in psychosis and a hypo-intentionality state in autistic spectrum disorders (62). Psychotics show an amplified bias for intentionality, or they have trouble controlling this bias? (30). Or, do they lose conscious access to the normal intentional object of their emotional experience, providing a delusional explanation for the absent intentional object? (45, 46). Theories of self-monitoring and error-checking agree with the theory concerning the use of a salience network. In psychosis, the initial hyperactivation of the salience network is likely followed by the hyper-activation of the default mode network and subsequently by the suppression of the salience and attention network (63).

The intentionality bias in psychosis, particularly in social contexts, can be better understand through the theories on ‘shared intentionality’. The Japanese philosopher Watsuji developed the concept of ‘betweeness’, reporting that the character and structure of intentionality is constitutively dependent upon an individual’s deep integration with their sociocultural environment (64). According to Searle, there could not be any social reality without collective intentionality and there could not be any collective intentionality without a pre-intentional sense of community. Shared intentionality, in a synonymous sense to collective intentionality, is described as the power of the mind to share mental states, such as feelings, intentions and beliefs with others (65). Shared intentionality, sometimes called “we” intentionality, refers to collaborative interactions in which participants have a shared commitment for pursuing a shared goal (65). Shared intentionality arises within human ontogeny and provides the basis for other capacities that are also apparently unique to humans (66). With the maturation of particular brain regions in infants we can see the emergence of the mental state of the idea of me – the “I know I know” and “I know you know,” which then subsequently allows for “I know you know I know” (67). Two types of implied intentionality have been proposed: (a) ‘Joint intentionality’ relies on the agents’ mentalizing abilities, such as mind reading and the ability to factor in their partner’s intentions, during an action planning. (b) ‘We-intentionality’ relates to the ability to perceive others as members of a group and to adopt the group’s expectations, a process found to be impaired in psychosis, while in severe autism spectrum disorder, both forms of shared intentionality found to be impaired (68).

However, in real world changes in many outcomes are rarely linear, and failures of intentionality in psychosis seem to occur through a non-linear and multifactor fluctuating pattern. Brain systems reflect components of an intentional system, where, as non-linear dynamics, can explain the complex behavior of such fuzzy systems (69). Recently we suggested that in psychosis there exist a failure of intentionality, due to a constant inappropriateness of an intentional object or connection (56). Using the cusp catastrophe model paradigm (70), we explained why relatively small changes in a parameter can result in catastrophic changes in the system state, while the sudden collapse can be explained by an already fragile system, rather than by a novel stressor. For example, the dysmyelination-induced delays in psychosis may cause a discrepancy in sensory feedback mechanisms, resulting in chronic prediction error, and in a generally fragile system. Treatments that preserve white matter integrity or ameliorate white matter disruption may enhance information-processing and functional outcome in psychosis (71).

The loss of intentional object

Intentionality is also considered to include the ‘directedness’ of mental phenomena towards an object. Could it possible that the loss of the intentional object can result in a mental disorder? Also, could a specific place exist for ‘directedness’ in the brain?

The reward circuits could represent such functions. These include the amygdale, which is associated with emotional learning, the ventral tegmental area, which contains dopaminergic neurons and signals motivation and reward seeking behavior, the nucleus accumbens, which is centrally involved in reward learning, and the lateral hypothalamus, which completes these reward signals, by uniting the homeostatic system with the hedonic system (72). Reward circuit starts from the ventral tegmental area and projects into many parts of the limbic system, such as the amygdala, the orbitofrontal cortex, the anterior cingulate and the nucleus accumbens (73, 74). The reward-dependent plasticity of basal ganglia neurons is caused by inputs from dopamine neurons located in the substantia nigra pars compacta and ventral tegmental area, which encode the ‘reward prediction error’ (75). As a key node in the reward pathway, the nucleus accumbens is important for determining motivation-to-action outcomes (76). The pleasure response is related to the mesolimbic dopaminergic system, which is involved in eating, in the use of psychoactive substances and in sexuality. The dopamine-guided plasticity would guide animals to choose actions that lead to better rewards (77). According to Pankseep, the brain contains a system of exploration and search (seeking system) that is responsible for the ability to have an urge towards something and this system sets the ability to open a primordial time horizon (78). We may consider that appetite and feeding, combining both aboutness and directedness sub-systems, are regulated by two interacting systems: the homeostatic system, which ensures that the individual receives sufficient calories for survival, and the hedonic system, which regulates the pleasure and reward aspects of feeding (79).

Another field of interest may be the networks associated with predictive processing, a function of vital significance for survival. Predictive coding appears as a universal evolutionary pathway and is constantly modified by environmental and internal mental information. The insula plays a role in not only error estimation but also in the updating of the probabilities of an outcome. It has been described as a specific hub of the autonomous, emotional and cognitive integration, and is associated with a range of stimuli, such as cognitive, emotional, olfactory, interoceptive and pain sensations (21, 33, 80). The interoceptive predictive coding supports a new view regarding emotions and the significance of the interoceptive system. It has been hypothesized that chronic anxiety is due to an increased interoceptive predictability of error signals, whilst the disrupted interoceptive predictive coding may be causally related to many psychiatric disorders (81). Interoceptive sensitivity is correlated with emotional stability. Atypically high interoception has been argued to characterize both panic disorder and anxiety syndromes, while poor interoceptive sensitivity has been observed in individuals with depression and schizophrenia (54).

It would appear that moods are pre-intentional states, which constitute the background within which the prepositional directed emotions target the objects. It is considered that the emotions shape the expectant structure of experience, which is a structure that makes intentional, mental, and bodily actions possible. This is why these phenomena have been suggested as background feelings, or possibility structures, or styles of anticipation of experience (82). Bodily feelings have intentional objects within the body, whereas feelings towards have an intentional object outside the body (83). In the case of depression, grief-pang is associated with the feeling of grief, which is apparently manifested through a process of “borrowing” the lost intentional object of grief (84). Furthermore, alexithymia, characterised by both atypical interoceptive sensitivity and loss of intentional object, has been found to co-occur with a number of affective disorders (85). Alexithymia and dissociation have been consistently linked in the literature, particularly in psychiatric populations. Both arise from a disconnection between conscious aspects of self-experiences and perceptions at both the mental self and bodily levels (86). Moreover they have been linked with a broader loss of emotional color, while psychopathology may result from imprecise interoceptive prediction error signals, due to a confused identification of the intentional object (21, 80).

In the case of suicidality, ‘entrapment’ was found to be the strongest predictive indicator for suicide (20, 57, 87). We may suggest that in suicidal patients there is an emotional intentionality failure, characterized by an absence of intentional object or a loss of conscious access to normal intentional objects. The suicidal action is accordingly the result of despair, loss of emotional intentionality, and entrapment, in a psychological environment with vague feelings (20). In our relative paper (88) we proposed an intentionality failure theory for suicidality, pointing that theories of emotional intentionality can enrich understanding of the transition phase from suicidal ideation to suicidal action. Taking the idea from the cusp catastrophe model (70), we demonstrated a multifactor fluctuating pattern of suicidality where intentionality failure was strongly tied with entrapment. If distal risk of suicidality is low, then proximal risk will be linearly related to a suicidal episode, but, if distal risk is high, then proximal risk is nonlinearly related to suicidality, and small changes in proximal risk predict a sudden lapse. It should be noted that people who commit suicide without having a psychiatric diagnosis can also be fitted in the proposed model, since the majority of people who die by suicide have never seen a mental health professional (89). This model suggests that strategies for sustainable management of such cases should focus on maintaining resilience (88). Also, different psychotherapeutic treatments focusing on the body (90), such as, yoga and mindfulness (91), dance therapy (92), dance moving therapy (93), or mirror exposure/gazing (94), can help patients, to rediscover and define their lost intentional object.

Epilogue

This manuscript is focusing on a rather neglected issue that concerns both aspects of philosophy and neurobiology, relating to the concept of intentionality. Although it is difficult to identify the associations between the observational feature of phenomenal concepts and the theoretical feature of intentional concepts (32), we may suggest an intentional system, as a higher order system, which plays a supervisory role in both the brain and behavior. A series of potential associations of this system in the brain have been presented in this manuscript, by observing the conceptual and neurobiological traces of aboutness and directedness. Additionally, a series of mental disorders have been suggested as the result of the failures of this neurophenomenological construction. We may consider that clarifications of the relationship between these associations shall further assist with comprehending the interaction between the brain and the mind, as well as our extension and interaction in the world.

The present paper is constrained by the well-known limits regarding suggested theoretical models, suffering from issues related to consistency and generalizability. Many parts of the paper are only theoretical and they need further support by clinical and preclinical studies, since these are philosophical ideas which have not or cannot be adequately supported by neuroscientific evidence.

However, when more scientific evidence will be gathering, we could be in a position to study ‘disordered intentionality’ in a dimensional framework, as a transdiagnostic biobehavioral system, according to the Research Domain Criteria (RDoC) or/and the Hierarchical Taxonomy of Psychopathology (HiTOP), which have the potential to inform the development of a unified, dimensional, and biobehaviorally-grounded psychiatric nosology (95). Finally, having in mind the etiological and diagnostic heterogeneity of psychiatric disorders, as well as the emphasis of the recent treatment approaches on the potential of brain-circuit-based interventions for precision psychiatry (96), we may think that the perspective of targeting brain circuits related to intentionality could offer hopeful treatment approaches in the future.

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

1. Brentano, F . Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul (1874) [1911, 1973]).

Google Scholar

2. Bernet, R . Husserl Edmund: analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: lectures on transcendental logic, Trans. A. J. Steinbock. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers (2001).

Google Scholar

3. Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and Time, Trans. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. (Eds.), New York: Harper and Row Publishers

Google Scholar

4. Aksoy, N . Spinoza’s conatus: a teleological Reading of its ethical dimension. Conatus – J Phil. (2021) 6:107–30. doi: 10.12681/cjp.25661

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Searle, JR . Intentionality: an essay in the philosophy of mind Cambridge University Press (1983).

Google Scholar

6. Nagel, T. (1974) What is it like to be a bat? T. Nagel (Eds.) Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 83, 435

Google Scholar

7. Guevara, R, Mateos, DM, and Velázquez, JLP. Consciousness as an emergent phenomenon: a tale of different levels of description. Entropy. (2020) 22:921. doi: 10.3390/e22090921

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Klein, SB . The feeling of personal ownership of one’s mental states: a conceptual argument and empirical evidence for an essential, but underappreciated, mechanism of mind. Psychol Conscious Theory Res Pract. (2015) 2:355–76. doi: 10.1037/cns0000052

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Mendelovici, A, and Bourget, David. (2020). Consciousness and intentionality. Uriah Kriegel (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of consciousness. New York, USA: Oxford University Press. 560–585

Google Scholar

10. Merleau-Ponty, M . The primacy of perception. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press (1964).

Google Scholar

11. Risjord, M. (2016). Inroduction, M. Risjord (Ed.), Normativity and naturalism in the philosophy of the social sciences, New York and London: Routledge, 1–8

Google Scholar

12. Dimitrakos, T . Intergrating first and second nature: rethinking John McDowell’s Liberal naturalism. Phil Inq. (2020) 8:37–68. doi: 10.4454/philinq.v8i1.216

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

13. Neander, K . A mark of the mental, In Defense of Informational Teleosemantics The MIT Press (2017).

Google Scholar

14. Millikan, R . Beyond concepts: unicepts, language, and natural information, UK: Oxford University Press (2017).

Google Scholar

15. Rachlin, H . Free will from the viewpoint of teleological behaviorism. Behav Sci Law. (2007) 25:235–50. doi: 10.1002/bsl.746

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

16. Leisman, G, Machado, C, Melillo, R, and Mualem, R. Intentionality and “free-will” from a neurodevelopmental perspective. Front Integr Neurosci. (2012) 6:36. doi: 10.3389/fnint.2012.00036

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Fitch, WT . Nano-intentionality: a defense of intrinsic intentionality. Biol Philos. (2008) 23:157–77. doi: 10.1007/s10539-007-9079-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

18. van Hateren, JH . Constructing a naturalistic theory of intentionality. Philosophia. (2021) 49:473–93. doi: 10.1007/s11406-020-00255-w

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Brüntrup, G. Quantum mechanics and intentionality. In: A. Corradini and M. Uwe (Editors). Quantum physics meets the philosophy of mind: new essays on the mind-body-relation in quantum-theoretical perspective. De Gruyter, (2014), 35–49.

Google Scholar

20. Giotakos, O . Intentionality and emotions. Dial Clin Neurosc Mental Health. (2020a) 3:133–42. doi: 10.26386/obrela.v3i3.167

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

21. Giotakos, O . Emotional intentionality and predictive processing. Dial Clin Neurosc Mental Health. (2021) 4:5–17. doi: 10.26386/obrela.v4i1.146

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Tomasello, M . Origins of human communication. The MIT Press (2008).

Google Scholar

23. Turner, CKA . Principle of intentionality. Front Psychol. (2017) 8:137. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.00137

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

24. Maturana, HR, and Varela, FJ. Autopoeisis and cognition: The Realization of the Living. D Reidel Publishing Company (1980).

Google Scholar

25. Jonas, H . The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology, Northwestern University Press (1968).

Google Scholar

26. O’Madagain, C, and Tomasello, M. Shared intentionality, reason-giving and the evolution of human culture. Phil Trans R Soc B. (2021) 377:20200320. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2020.0320

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

27. Solé, R, Moses, M, and Forrest, S. Liquid brains, solid brains. Phil Trans R Soc London B. (2019) 374:20190040. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2019.0040

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

28. Llinas, RR . I of the vortex: from neurons to self. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press (2001).

Google Scholar

29. Spunt, RP, Meyer, ML, and Lieberman, MD. The default mode of human brain function primes the intentional stance. J Cogn Neurosci. (2016) 27:1116–24. doi: 10.1162/jocn_a_00785

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

30. Buck, B, Hester, NR, Pinkham, A, Harvey, PD, Jarskog, LF, and Penn, DL. The bias toward intentionality in schizophrenia: automaticity, context, and relationships to symptoms and functioning. J Abnorm Psychol. (2018) 127:503–12. doi: 10.1037/abn0000360

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

31. Graham, KE, Wilke, C, Lahiff, NJ, and Slocombe, KE. Scratching beneath the surface: intentionality in great ape signal production. Phil Trans R Soc B. (2020) 375:20180403. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2018.0403

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

32. Miklós, M . Intentional and phenomenal properties: how not to be inseparatists. Philosophia. (2022) 50:127–47. doi: 10.1007/s11406-021-00362-2

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

33. Seth, AK . From unconscious inference to the Beholder’s share: predictive perception and human experience. Eur Rev. (2019) 27:378–410. doi: 10.1017/S1062798719000061

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

34. Giotakos, O . The intentional system: tracing the conative feature of aboutness and directedness in human brain. Dial Clin Neurosc Mental Health. (2022a) 5:143–8. doi: 10.26386/obrela.v5i4.242

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

35. Jamon, M . The development of vestibular system and related functions in mammals: impact of gravity. Front Integr Neurosci. (2014) 8:11. doi: 10.3389/fnint.2014.00011

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

36. Kearney, BE, and Lanius, RA. The brain-body disconnect: a somatic sensory basis for trauma-related disorders. Front Neurosci. (2022) 16:1015749. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2022.1015749

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

37. Hwang, EJ, Sato, TR, and Sato, TK. A canonical scheme of bottom-up and top-down information flows in the frontoparietal network. Front Neural Circuits. (2021) 15:691314. doi: 10.3389/fncir.2021.691314

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

38. Keller, GB, and Mrsic-Flogel, TD. Predictive processing: a canonical cortical computation. Neuron. (2018) 100:424–35. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2018.10.003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

39. Ingerslev, LR . Inhibited intentionality: on possible self-understanding in cases of weak agency. Front Psychol. (2020) 11:558709. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.558709

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

40. Dennett, DC . The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press (1987).

Google Scholar

41. Frith, CD . The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. London: Psychology Press (2015).

Google Scholar

42. Giotakos, O . Poor insight in psychosis and meta-representation models. Dial Clin Neurosc Mental Health. (2018) 1:12–24. doi: 10.26386/obrela.v1i1.5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

43. Petrides, M. (2013). The mid-dorsolateral prefronto-parietal network and the epoptic process. D.T. Stuss and R.T. Knight (Eds), Principles of frontal lobe function, chapter 7. New York: Oxford University Press, 79–89

Google Scholar

44. Mead, GH . Mind, self and society from the standpoint of a social behaviorist. CW Morris (Editor), Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press (1934).

Google Scholar

45. Bolton, D . Problems in the definition of mental disorder. Philos Q. (2001) 51:182–99. doi: 10.1111/j.0031-8094.2001.00223.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

46. Bolton, D . What is mental disorder? An essay in philosophy, science, and values. New York: Oxford University (2008).

Google Scholar

47. Jaspers, K . General psychopathology. Chicago, IL: University Of Chicago Press (1923).

Google Scholar

48. Poletti, M, Tortorella, A, and Raballo, A. Impaired corollary discharge in psychosis and at-risk states: integrating neurodevelopmental, phenomenological, and clinical perspectives. Biol Psychiatry Cogn Neurosci Neuroimaging. (2019) 4:832–41. doi: 10.1016/j.bpsc.2019.05.008

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

49. Parlikar, R, Bose, A, and Venkatasubramanian, G. Schizophrenia and corollary discharge: a neuroscientific overview and translational implications. Clin Psychopharmacol Neurosci. (2019) 17:170–82. doi: 10.9758/cpn.2019.17.2.170

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

50. Poulet, JFA, and Hedwig, B. New insights into corollary discharges mediated by identified neural pathways. Trends Neurosci. (2007) 30:14–21. doi: 10.1016/j.tins.2006.11.005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

51. Leptourgos, P, and Corlett, PR. Embodied predictions, agency, and psychosis. Front Big Data. (2020) 3:27. doi: 10.3389/fdata.2020.00027

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

52. Craig, AD . How do you feel—now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nat Rev Neurosci. (2009) 10:59–70. doi: 10.1038/nrn2555

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

53. Hohwy, J . New directions in predictive processing. Mind Lang. (2020) 35:209–23. doi: 10.1111/mila.12281

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

54. Ardizzi, M, Ambrosecchia, M, Buratta, L, Ferri, F, Peciccia, M, Donnari, S, et al. Interoception and positive symptoms in schizophrenia. Front Hum Neurosci. (2016) 10:379. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2016.00379

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

55. Chisholm, RM . Perceiving: a philosophical study Cornell University Press (1957).

Google Scholar

56. Giotakos, O . Modelling disruptions of intentionality in psychosis. Psychiatriki. (2023a). doi: 10.22365/jpsych.2023.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

57. Giotakos, O . Neurobiology of emotional trauma. Psychiatriki. (2020b) 31:162–71. doi: 10.22365/jpsych.2020.312.162

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

58. Hirjak, D, Breyer, T, Thomann, PA, and Fuchs, T. Disturbance of intentionality: a phenomenological study of body-affecting first-rank symptoms in schizophrenia. PLoS One. (2013) 8:e73662. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0073662

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

59. Langdon, R, Boulton, K, Connaughton, E, and Gao, T. Perceiving and attributing intentionality in schizophrenia. Cogn Neuropsychiatry. (2020) 25:269–80. doi: 10.1080/13546805.2020.1777093

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

60. Peyroux, E, Strickland, B, Tapiero, I, and Franck, N. The intentionality bias in schizophrenia. Psychiatry Res. (2014) 219:426–30. doi: 10.1016/j.psychres.2014.06.034

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

61. Roodenrys, S, Barkus, E, Woolrych, TJ, Miller, LM, and Favelle, SK. The intentionality bias in schizotypy: a social matter. Cogn Neuropsychiatry. (2021) 26:55–72. doi: 10.1080/13546805.2020.1865894

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

62. Bara, BG, Ciaramidaro, A, Walter, H, and Adenzato, M. Intentional minds: a philosophical analysis of intention tested through fMRI experiments involving people with schizophrenia, people with autism, and healthy individuals. Front Hum Neurosci. (2011) 5:7. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2011.00007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

63. Corlett, PR, Taylor, J, Wang, X, Fletcher, PC, and Krystal, JH. Toward a neurobiology of delusions. Prog Neurobiol. (2010) 92:345–69. doi: 10.1016/j.pneurobio.2010.06.007

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

64. Zanghellini, A, and Sato, M. A critical recuperation of Watsuji’s Rinrigaku. Philosophia. (2021) 49:1289–307. doi: 10.1007/s11406-020-00296-1

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

65. Searle, JR . The construction of social reality NY Free Press (1995).

Google Scholar

66. Tomasello, M, Carpenter, M, Call, J, Behne, T, and Moll, H. Understanding and sharing intentions: the origins of cultural cognition. Behav Brain Sci. (2005) 28:675–91. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X05000129

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

67. Lewis, M . Shared intentions without a self. Behav Brain Sci. (2005) 28:707–8. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X05390121

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

68. Salice, A, and Henriksen, MG. Disturbances of shared intentionality in schizophrenia and autism. Front Psychiatr. (2021) 11:570597. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2020.570597

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

69. Chinedu, A, Cabral, J, and Silbersweig, D. On a quantitative approach to clinical neuroscience in psychiatry: lessons from the Kuramoto model. Harv Rev Psychiatry. (2021) 29:318–26. doi: 10.1097/HRP.0000000000000301

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

70. Poston, T, and Stewart, I. Catastrophe theory and its applications Dover Publications (2012).

Google Scholar

71. Giotakos, O . Is psychosis a dysmyelination-related information-processing disorder? Psychiatriki. (2019) 30:245–55. doi: 10.22365/jpsych.2019.303.245

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

72. Friston, K . Prediction, perception and agency. Int J Psychophysiol. (2012) 83:248–52. doi: 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2011.11.014

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

73. Aberg, KC, and Paz, R. Average reward rates enable motivational transfer across independent reinforcement learning tasks. Front Behav Neurosci. (2022) 16:1041566. doi: 10.3389/fnbeh.2022.1041566

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

74. Ly, V, Wang, KS, Bhanji, J, and Delgado, MR. Reward-based framework of perceived control. Front Neurosci. (2019) 13:65. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2019.00065

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

75. Hikosaka, O, Kim, HF, Yasuda, M, and Yamamoto, S. Basal ganglia circuits for reward value-guided behavior. Annu Rev Neurosci. (2014) 37:289–306. doi: 10.1146/annurev-neuro-071013-013924

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

76. Turner, BD, Kashima, DT, Manz, KM, Grueter, CA, and Grueter, BA. Synaptic plasticity in the nucleus accumbens: lessons learned from experience. ACS Chem Neurosci. (2018) 9:2114–26. doi: 10.1021/acschemneuro.7b00420

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

77. Schultz, W . Predictive reward signal of dopamine neurons. J Neurophysiol. (1998) 80:1–27. doi: 10.1152/jn.1998.80.1.1

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

78. Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective neuroscience: the foundations of human and animal emotions. New York: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

79. Kinasz, KR, Ross, DA, and Cooper, JJ. Eat to live or live to eat? The neurobiology of appetite regulation. Biol Psychiatry. (2017) 81:e73–5. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2017.02.1177

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

80. Seth, AK, and Critchley, HD. Extending predictive processing to the body: emotion as interoceptive inference. Behav Brain Sci. (2013) 36:227–8. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X12002270

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

81. Seth, AK, Suzuki, K, and Critchley, HD. An interoceptive predictive coding model of conscious presence. Front Psychol. (2012) 2:395. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00395

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

82. Ratcliffe, M . Emotional intentionality. R Inst Philos Suppl. (2019) 85:251–69. doi: 10.1017/S1358246118000784

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

83. Sheredos, B . Embodied delusions and intentionality Georgia State University (2009). Available at: http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/4525/

Google Scholar

84. Goldie, P . Emotions, feelings, and intentionality. Phenomenol Cogn Sci. (2002) 1:235–54. doi: 10.1023/A:1021306500055

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

85. Murphy, J, Brewer, R, Catmur, C, and Bird, G. Interoception and psychopathology: a developmental neuroscience perspective. Dev Cogn Neurosci. (2017) 23:45–56. doi: 10.1016/j.dcn.2016.12.006

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

86. Goerlich, KS . The multifaceted nature of alexithymia – a neuroscientific perspective. Front Psychol. (2018) 9:1614. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01614

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

87. O’Connor, RC, and Kirtley, OJ. The integrated motivational – volitional model of suicidal behavior. Phil Trans R Soc London B. (2018) 373:20170268. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2017.0268

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

88. Giotakos, O . Disruptions of intentionality and suicidal behavior. Dial Clin Neurosc Mental Health. (2022b) 5:77–87. doi: 10.26386/obrela.v5i2.227

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

89. Tang, T, Reily, NM, Arena, AF, Batterham, PJ, Calear, AL, Carter, GL, et al. People who die by suicide without receiving mental health services: a systematic review. Front Public Health. (2021) 9:736948. doi: 10.3389/fpubh.2021.736948

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

90. Rosendahl, S, Sattel, H, and Lahmann, C. Effectiveness of body psychotherapy. A systematic review and meta-analysis. Front Psychiatry. (2021) 12:709798. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2021.709798

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

91. Sathyanarayanan, G, Vengadavaradan, A, and Bharadwaj, B. Role of yoga and mindfulness in severe mental illnesses: a narrative review. Int J Yoga. (2019) 12:3–28. doi: 10.4103/ijoy.IJOY_65_17

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

92. Karkou, V, Aithal, S, Zubala, A, and Meekums, B. Effectiveness of dance movement therapy in the treatment of adults with depression: a systematic review with meta-analyses. Front Psychol. (2019) 10:936. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00936

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

93. Koch, SC, Morlinghaus, K, and Fuchs, T. The joy dance specific effects of a single dance intervention on psychiatric patients with depression. Arts Psychother. (2007) 34:340–9. doi: 10.1016/j.aip.2007.07.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

94. Giotakos, O. (2023b). The mirror and I: a guide to self-treatment. iWrite publications, (kindle edition), ASIN: B0BYDSX3PS

Google Scholar

95. Michelini, G, Palumbo, IM, DeYoung, CG, Latzman, RD, and Kotov, R. Linking RDoC and HiTOP: a new interface for advancing psychiatric nosology and neuroscience. Clin Psychol Rev. (2021) 86:102025. doi: 10.1016/j.cpr.2021.102025

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

96. Scangos, Κ, State, Μ, Miller, ΑΗ, Baker, JT, and Williams, LM. New and emerging approaches to treat psychiatric disorders. Nat Med. (2023) 29:317–33. doi: 10.1038/s41591-022-02197-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: intentionality, intentional system, failure of intentionality, mental disorders, brain, modeling, philosophy, neuroscience

Citation: Giotakos O (2023) Modeling intentionality in the human brain. Front. Psychiatry. 14:1163421. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2023.1163421

Received: 10 February 2023; Accepted: 24 July 2023;
Published: 09 August 2023.

Edited by:

Andreea Oliviana Diaconescu, University of Toronto, Canada

Reviewed by:

Dimitrios Kontis, Psychiatric Hospital of Attica, Greece
George Konstantakopoulos, National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, Greece
Konstantinos Tsamakis, King’s College London, United Kingdom

Copyright © 2023 Giotakos. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Orestis Giotakos, info@obrela.gr

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.