Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Phys., 26 October 2020
Sec. High-Energy and Astroparticle Physics
This article is part of the Research Topic Qubits and Spacetime View all 10 articles

Simulating Indefinite Causal Order With Rindler Observers

  • 1Faculty of Physics, University of Belgrade, Belgrade, Serbia
  • 2Departamento de Física, Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais, Belo Horizonte, Brazil
  • 3Physics Department and Research Center Optimas, Technische Universität Kaiserslautern, Kaiserslautern, Germany
  • 4Faculty of Physics, Vienna Center for Quantum Science and Technology (VCQ), University of Vienna, Vienna, Austria
  • 5Institute for Quantum Optics and Quantum Information (IQOQI), Austrian Academy of Sciences, Vienna, Austria

Realization of indefinite causal order (ICO), a theoretical possibility that even causal relations between physical events can be subjected to quantum superposition, apart from its general significance for the fundamental physics research, would also enable quantum information processing that outperforms protocols in which the underlying causal structure is definite. In this paper, we start with a proposition that an observer in a state of quantum superposition of being at two different relative distances from the event horizon of a black hole, effectively resides in ICO space-time generated by the black hole. By invoking the fact that the near-horizon geometry of a Schwarzschild black hole is that of a Rindler space-time, we propose a way to simulate an observer in ICO space-time by a Rindler observer in a state of superposition of having two different proper accelerations. By extension, a pair of Rindler observers with entangled proper accelerations simulates a pair of entangled ICO observers. Moreover, these Rindler-systems might have a plausible experimental realization by means of optomechanical resonators.

1. Introduction

The principle of causality is an implicit assumption of every physical theory and it is universally supported by our experience of nature. From an operational point of view, causality can be understood as a system of signaling or communication relations between physical systems; an information flow whose properties are intimately related to the nature of space and time. One may even say that the very essence of the classical structure of space and time is to impose a physical constraint on information processing.

In the old Newtonian picture of the World, space and time are two generically different entities, universal for all observers. There is a single, three-dimensional flat Euclidean space and a single global time that enable us to unambiguously distinguish between past, present and future. Together, they constitute an absolute, independent background structure relative to which every physical event takes place. Signals can propagate in space with unlimited speed (action at a distance) and, consequently, each event can be caused by any other in its present or past. The special theory of relativity (SR) changed this paradigm: space and time became united into the (3+1)-dimensional space-time continuum—Minkowski space - in which signals cannot travel faster than the speed of light, enforcing them to stay within the local light cone. Nevertheless, the structure of Minkowski space adhered to the character of an independent, fixed background on which dynamical matter fields propagate.

The radical change came with Einstein’s general theory of relativity (GR). The gravitational field came to be understood as the curved space-time itself, gravity being encoded in a metric tensor coupled to dynamical matter fields. There is no fixed, independent metric structure, no absolute background stage relative to which locations of physical events are to be defined, there are just dynamical fields, the metric being one of them, and physical events can only be located relative to each other. The possibility of communication between different observers, i.e. the causal order, is entirely determined by the dynamical configuration of light cones, and so, although dynamical, space-time, as a landscape of physical events, has definite causal order (DCO). Thinking about Quantum Mechanics (QM) of gravitating objects, the question arises whether there is a way to relax the restrictions of classical space-time structure and enable processes that do not obey definite causal relations, i.e., can there be a quantum superposition of different causal orders—an indefinite causal order (ICO)?

It is generally expected that unification of QM and gravitational physics will provide us with some deeper insights concerning the nature of space and time and their relationship with matter. However, the standard methods of quantization of matter fields employed in Quantum Field Theory (QFT) do not seem to work for Einstein’s gravity; it holds a status of a non-renormalizable effective theory with undetermined high-energy degrees of freedom. In order to surpass the traditional concepts of GR and QFT, various ways of “quantizing” gravity were proposed so far, such as String Theory, Quantum Loop Gravity, Noncommutative Geometry, Supergravity, etc. However, to date, there has been no conclusive empirical evidence that would support or disprove any of the proposed “high-energy theories.” This state of affairs motivates us to reconsider in which sense and to what extent can the seemingly contradictory principles of QM and GR be reconciled, while adhering to the tenets of both theories [1, 2].

There are two main incentives for this paper. The first came from the work of Oreshkov, Costa and Brukner [3], where it was found that it is possible to formulate quantum mechanics without any reference to a global causal structure, i.e. without predefined space-time. The resulting framework - the process matrix formalism - allows for processes incompatible with any definite causal order between operations performed on quantum systems. These abstract indefinite causal structures are shown to be advantageous for quantum computing [4, 5] and quantum communication [68]. One particular example that has an experimental demonstration is the so called “quantum switch” [4, 914], where the main idea is to use an auxiliary quantum system that can coherently control the order in which certain operations are applied. In the case of the so-called gravitational quantum switch (GQS) [15] the role of the control system is played by a gravitating object prepared in a state of quantum superposition of being at two different spatial locations. The second incentive comes from the intriguing idea of quantum reference frames (QRF) [16, 17] where one regards reference frames not as abstract systems of coordinates, but as actual physical objects subjected to the laws of quantum mechanics and describes the world from their perspective.

In this paper, we propose a way to simulate ICO processes by considering the fact that the near-horizon geometry of a Schwarzschild black hole (BH) is that of a Rindler space-time. Namely, a Rindler observer in a state of superposition of having two different proper accelerations corresponds to a near-horizon Schwarzschild observer in a state of superposition of being at two different locations along a single radial direction. From the viewpoint of such an observer the geometry of space-time is indefinite. This correspondence can be extended to a pair of Rindler observers with entangled proper accelerations simulating a pair of entangled ICO observers, as we illustrate by means of a simple example. Although they represent idealizations, these Rindler-systems could become a valuable resource for studying ICO processes in laboratory conditions, with plausible experimental realization in the form of opto-mechanical oscillators [1821].

2. Rindler Observers

In order to set the stage, consider the (1 + 1)-dimensional Minkowski space 2 and a central light cone defined by t=±x (we set c=1). In these globally inertial coordinates (t,x) the Minkowski metric is given by ds22=dt2+dx2. If we introduce Rindler coordinates (η,ρ) defined by t=ρsinh(η) and x=ρcosh(η), the metric becomes ds22=ρ2dη2+dρ2. However, these new coordinates do not cover the whole Minkowski space, only the patch given by x0 and |t|x. This region is called the right Rindler wedge or simply the R-wedge [see Figure 1 (left panel)]. The family of coordinate lines of constant ρ are the branches of hyperbolas x2t2=ρ2 embedded in the R-wedge (the other set of branches belongs to the L-wedge, defined by x0 and |t|x) asymptotically approaching the Rindler horizon t=±x (ρ=0 and η±). They correspond to the worldlines of physical systems that have constant proper acceleration of magnitude α(ρ)=1/ρRindler observers. The proper time of a Rindler observer, with a given ρ=const., is dτ=ρdη. Therefore, we can define a worldline of a Rindler observer in the R-wedge with proper acceleration α by a pair of parametric equations:

t(τ)=1αsinh(ατ),x(τ)=1αcosh(ατ).(1)
FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 1. Rindler observers. (Left panel): Coordinate lines in the right (R) Rindler wedge of the Minkowski space. Coordinate lines of constant ρ are hyperbolas and they correspond to worldlines of Rindler observers. Regions L and R, called the left and the right Rindler wedge, respectively, are causally disconnected due to the presence of the Rindler horizon t=±x. (Right panel): Photon’s worldline intersects the Rindlers. A pair of Rindler observers in the R-wedge with different proper accelerations α1 and α2, α1<α2. A photon sent from the source S, located at ts=0 and xs=x0>0, intersects the worldlines of the Rindler observers at their respective proper times τ1 and τ2. One can arrange things so that τ1=τ2.

Rindler observer with greater proper acceleration has a more curved worldline (closer to the Rindler horizon). Note also that, due to the presence of the Rindler horizon, Rindler observers in the R-wedge are causally disconnected from the ones in the L-wedge, meaning that they are unable to communicate with each other.

Consider now a pair of Rindler observers in the R-wedge, with different proper accelerations α1 and α2. Let the worldline of the second one be more curved. That is, let α1<α2. A photon sent to the left from the source S, located at ts=0 and xs=x0>0, intersects worldlines of the Rindler observers at proper times τ1 and τ2, respectively [see Figure 1 (right panel)]. At t=0 both observers are closer to the origin than S, implying that α2x0>α1x0>1. This configuration has an interesting feature that will turn out to be important. Namely, given the values of x0 and α1, there exists a unique value of α2, defined as the non trivial solution (α2α1) of the equation

α2x0=(α1x0)α2α1,(2)

for which τ1=τ2 (for details, see Supplementary Material).

3. Indefinite Causal Order via Rindler Observers

Let us assume that we have a pair of Rindler observers in the R-wedge, Rindler-Amber (AR) and Rindler-Blue (BR). Amber and Blue are the colors by which we distinguish the two observers, see Figure 2. Note, however, that these “observers” need not be actual macroscopic measuring devices of any sort, nor sentient beings; they could be microscopic physical systems with some internal degrees of freedom (like spin). On the other hand, they have definite worldlines since they are confined within accelerating laboratories (imagine well-enough localized classical “boxes” each carrying an atom). We assume that these internal degrees of freedom are such that they do not get affected by the accelerated motion of the Rindler laboratory, which we also assume to be completely isolated. Source S emits a photon whose worldline intersects the worldlines of AR and BR. The photon starts in some polarization state |Ψ and the Rindler observers can perform instantaneous unitary transformations on it.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 2. Entangled Rindler observers. Worldline of a photon emitted by the source S intersects worldlines of the two Rindler observers, AR and BR, that have entangled proper accelerations. On the left panel, AR has greater proper acceleration (α2) than BR(α1), and on the right panel the accelerations are “switched”. By choosing a suitable pair of values for the proper accelerations, these meetings (events a and b) occur at the same proper time τ*. Rindler observers act on the polarization of the photon according to their “color”, amber (A) or blue (B), that distinguishes them. Observer AR performs a unitary transformation UA at τ* and observer BR performs a unitary transformation UB at τ*. When Rindler observers meet the photon, they come to rest and remain that way until some particular moment tm at which a projective measurement is performed in order to disentangle the state of the photon from that of the Rindler observers. The photon is observed at C.

When their worldlines intersect, AR performs a unitary transformation UA on the photon’s polarization state. This constitutes event a. In general, UA is a function of AR’s proper time. We can abstractly think of AR as a Rindler “clock” whose worldline and the ticking rate are defined by the proper acceleration αA. The state of AR will therefore be denoted by |ταA;A, without getting into details of what AR’s actual degrees of freedom are and what kind of Hamiltonian governs the dynamics thereof. And the same protocol applies to BR. Its meeting with the photon and application of a unitary transformation UB constitutes event b. By choosing a suitable values of the proper accelerations αA and αB, we can arrange that meetings of the Rindler observers with the photon (events a and b) occur at the same proper times τa=τb=τ* (see the discussion at the end of Section 2).

Here we want to stress that physical events are not regarded as pure geometrical points that constitute space-time manifold (modulo diffeomorphisms) with some definite set of causal relations defined by the metric. Rather they are defined operationally, through application of a specific unitary transformation, or more generally a specific completely positive trace-preserving (CPTP) map. Taking quantum mechanics into account, we consider the possibility that the same physical event can be in a superposition of occurring at different space-time locations. This would enable the realization of indefinite causal order between pairs of events, such as a and b in the above discussion. One example of this situation is the already mentioned quantum switch [914].

On the left panel of Figure 2, the proper acceleration of AR (α2) is greater than the proper acceleration of BR (α1) and on the right panel, the values are interchanged, AR has the smaller proper acceleration (α1) and BR has the greater proper acceleration (α2). In the reference frame of the inertial observer sitting at x=0 the initial state (at t=0) of the whole system (Rindlers photon) in the former case is the separable state |τα2(0),A|τα1(0),B|Ψ; the photon first meets BR and then AR. In the latter case, when the initial state of the system is |τα1(0),A|τα2(0),B|Ψ, the photon first meets AR and then BR. If the Rindler observers are prepared in the entangled state that is a superposition of the two previous ones, at t=0 we have

12(|τα2(0),A|τα1(0),B+|τα1(0),A|τα2(0),B)|Ψ.(3)

It is important to realize that the event a has to be one and the same in both “branches” of the superposition. The meeting of the photon with AR in the case when AR has greater proper acceleration than BR and the meeting of the photon with AR when AR has smaller proper acceleration than BR, have to be locally indistinguishable events in every respect. That is why we demand that the event occurs at the same proper time, τ*, in both situations. In principle, the state of the photon could be affected by the kinematic state of a Rinldler laboratory, which might give rise to entanglement between proper accelerations of the Rindler laboratories and photon'|’s polarization state. To avoid this possibility, we put them to rest just before they meet the photon, thus making them inertial from that point on. Conditional deacceleration of the laboratories along the Rindler trajectories can be performed sufficiently fast, yet gradually, not to produce the Unruh radiation.

For t<t1 (where t1 is the time coordinate of the intersection of the photon’s worldline with the less curved Rindler worldline) the state is

12(|τα2(t),A|τα1(t),B+|τα1(t),A|τα2(t),B)|Ψ.(4)

By the time the photon went through the laboratories, unitary transformations, UA(τ*) and UB(τ*), have been applied on it. At some instant t>t2 (where t2 is the time coordinate of the intersection of the photon'|’s worldline with the more curved Rindler worldline) the state of the whole system is given by

12(|τ*+tt2,A|τ*+tt1,BUA(τ*)UB(τ*)+|τ*+tt1,A|τ*+tt2,BUB(τ*)UA(τ*))|Ψ,(5)

where tt1 and tt2 are the time intervals during which the respective Rindler laboratories were at rest.

Finally, we need to disentangle the state of the photon from the state of the Rindler observers. To this end, at some moment tm, a projective measurement (postselection on the internal state of the Rindlers) is performed in the superposition basis {|mi,|mi|i=1,2}, separately for each laboratory. The basis states are given by

|mi=12(|τ*+tmti,A+|τ*+tmti,B),|mi=12(|τ*+tmti,A|τ*+tmti,B).(6)

Postselection on any pair of possible measurement results leads to the final state of the photon

12(UA(τ*)UB(τ*)±UB(τ*)UA(τ*))|Ψ.(7)

Subsequently, the photon may be observed at C. However, being in the state 7, there is no way to distinguish, given the photon alone, which of the two events (a and b) lies in the causal future of the other, and the information about the causal order is lost.

4. Gravitational Scenario

Imagine now that we have a system that involves a Schwarzschild BH and an observer (outside the horizon) in a state of superposition of being at two different relative proper distances from the horizon. The observer is well-enough localized and has a negligible effect on the gravitational field. Also, we do not assume the existence of a fixed background geometry with reference to which we could define positions; only the relative distance between the BH (its horizon) and the observer has physical meaning.

In Schwarzchild coordinates (t,r,θ,ϕ), the metric of the BH exterior is

ds2=f(r)dt2+dr2f(r)+r2dΩ22,(8)

with f(r)=1RSr and Ω22=dθ2+sin2θdϕ2. We are only interested in a single radial direction, so we can ignore the angular part of the metric. The proper radial distance between the stationary observer at rlab and the event horizon at RS=2MG (M being the mass of the BH) is

ρ=Rsriabdrf(r).(9)

Therefore, our bipartite system can be interpreted as a situation where we have an observer in the state 12(|ρ1+|ρ2) with indefinite proper distance from the horizon in definite Schwarzchild geometry. On the other hand, from the viewpoint of the observer (quantum reference frame), the gravitational field appears to be indefinite, as if the BH is in the state of superposition of being at two different places relative to the observer.

The idea that a gravitating object in a state of quantum superposition of being at two different locations somehow “induces” a quantum superposition of different geometries, dates back to Feynman [22] and it has been successfully promoted recently [15, 2326]. Although this seems as a natural way to combine GR and the linearity of QM, it remains unclear in which sense can a gravitational field (i.e., space-time geometry) be in a state of quantum superposition, see for example [27]. Here, we propose a way of looking at this situation based on the relational character of quantum superposition [28].

Einstein’s equivalence principle states that a gravitational field is locally equivalent to an accelerating reference frame in flat space-time. As a consequence, for every well-enough localized stationary (r=const.) observer in Schwarzschild geometry there is an equivalent uniformly accelerating observer in Minkowski space. Moreover, the near-horizon geometry of a Schwarzschild BH is that of a Rindler space-time, and therefore a Schwarzschild observer whose proper distance from the horizon is ρ corresponds to the Rindler observer whose proper acceleration is 1/ρ (see Supplementary Material for details).

By extending this reasoning, we propose a “quantum” version of Einstein’s equivalence principle by stating that ICO space-time is locally equivalent to a non-inertial reference frame with superposed proper accelerations. In particular, we can relate a Schwarzschild observer in the state 12(|ρ1+|ρ2) of being at two different relative distances from the horizon, to the Rindler observer in the state of superposition of having proper accelerations 1/ρ1 and 1/ρ2, respectively. The similar principle has been invoked and derived within quantum reference frames formalism [16] in the Newtonian limit.

Consider now a pair of observers in the near-horizon region of a Schwarzschild BH, Schwarzschild-Amber (AS) and Schwarzschild-Blue (BS). Let the observers have entangled proper distances from the horizon (along a single radial ray) and fixed relative distance between each other. From the reference frame of the BH, space-time has a definite geometry and the state of this tripartite system is 12|0BH(|ρ1A|ρ2B+|ρ2A|ρ1B), where |0BH is the position state of the black hole. Observers AS and BS correspond to a pair of Rindler observers, AR and BR, both in the R-wedge, with entangled proper accelerations. On the other hand, from the point of view of the pair of observers, we have a BH in a state of superposition of being “at two different sides” of the observers, symmetrically. These states of the BH are denoted by |L and |R, see Figure 3. The middle point between AS and BS is well defined in relative terms. From the reference frame associated to this point [29] the joint state of the system is 12(|L+|R)|ρ¯A|ρ¯B, where ρ¯=ρ2ρ12 is the half-distance between the two observers.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

FIGURE 3. Gravitational quantum switch. The system involves a photon source S, two observers, AS and BS, and a BH in a state of superposition of being at two different positions relative to them, |L or |R. The direction in which the photon is emitted depends on the position of the BH and therefore the BH plays the role of a quantum control for the whole process. As a result, the photon is in a superposition of traveling in two opposite directions.

We can perform a photon experiment, similar to the one described in Section 3, that involves the observers AS and BS and a source S that emits a photon in the direction that depends on the position of the BH relative to the observers. The position of the BH plays the role of a quantum control for the whole process (gravitational quantum switch). Due to the gravitational time dilation, we can arrange things so that the photon passes through both laboratories at the same moment of their local proper time (see Supplementary Material for details). This is analogous to the case of the Rindler quantum switch from Section 2. When the photon gets inside the laboratory, a unitary transformation, UA or UB, depending on the laboratory, is applied instantaneously on its polarization state. The meeting of the photon and the laboratory AS and the application of the unitary UA is the event a, and likewise, the meeting of the photon and the laboratory BS and the application of the unitary UB is the event b. After performing a projective measurement in the superposition basis 1/2(|L±|R) of the BH (to disentangle its state from the photon'|’s state, as described in [15]), the final state of the photon implies the two events do not possess definite causal order.

5. Conclusion

In this paper, we proposed a way to characterize ICO space-time as a space-time associated with the reference frame of a quantum observer - quantum observer perceives ICO space-time. As an illustration, we considered a bipartite system that involves a Schwarzschild BH and an observer outside the horizon, in a state of quantum superposition of being at two different relative distances. By invoking the fact that near-horizon geometry is that of a Rindler space-time, we can relate this ICO observer to the Rindler observer in a state of superposition of having two different proper accelerations. By extension, a pair of ICO observers with entangled proper distances from the BH horizon corresponds to a pair of Rindler observers with entangled proper accelerations. As an example, we analyzed Rindler quantum switch and the related gravitational quantum switch.

Furthermore, a Bell’s inequality for temporal order of events was found in [15]. The same kind of inequality can be derived by using two pairs of Rindler observers, one in the left and the other in the right Rindler wedge. In the corresponding gravitational scenario we would have to take into account the Kruskal extension of the Schwarzschild solution. In this case, the gravitational quantum switch would involve two pairs of observers residing in conformally flat space-times connected by Einstein-Rosen bridge. We postpone this interesting analysis for future work.

On a more practical side, there is a growing effort in demonstrating quantum features of nano-to-mesoscale optomechanical systems. This may provide a challenging, yet feasible experimental realizations for the proposed Rindler systems [18]. Recently, mesoscopic mechanical resonators were considered as quantum non-inertial reference frames [19, 20] and entanglement of two massive mechanical oscillators is achieved [21]. It has been proposed to utilize quantum optical fields in order to prepare and measure the quantum states of mechanical resonators, conceivably opening the possibility to quantum-mechanically control the acceleration of such quantum non-inertial reference frames [18].

In an actual experiment, potential decoherance effects can compromise the predicted result [30]. Moreover, QFT effects could also be taken into account. In this context, our Rindler observers could be viewed as Unruh-DeWitt detectors, where an increase of the thermal noise, due to the Unruh effect, may affect the evolution of the system, such that it can no longer be considered as a coherent superposition, but rather a (convex) classical mixture. However, since we can choose proper accelerations of the Rindler observers to be arbitrarily small by putting the photon source at suitable position, the Unruh effect can always be made negligible. Just to put some numbers, if we set x0=1m, the accelerations would be of order 1017m/s2, which corresponds to the Unruh temperature of order 104K, and this is far too small for the Unruh effect to be detectable. Correspondingly, for a solar mass black hole with Rs=3km, we have a Schwarzschild observer at 1m proper distance from the horizon, which is a good near-horizon approximation. Furthermore, depending on the parameters of the objects involved, e.g., masses of the laboratories, these Rindler systems could be used to test hypotheses such as the Ghirardi-Rimini-Weber (GRW) model of objective collapse [31]. Namely, a failure to maintain a coherent macroscopic superposition even after screening off the system from decoherence effects, might be taken as an indication of a spontaneous GRW-type collapses. However, as we noted in the text, the systems involved in our setting need not be macroscopic systems (they can be microscopic ones, such as atoms). Moreover, the issues concerning macroscopic systems may still be avoided by performing the experiment ”sufficiently fast” (before the alleged GRW-type of collapse should take place). This kind of assessment was provided in [15] for gravitational quantum switch. Finally, we should also mention that there is a relativistic version of the GRW model [32]. Our relativistic Rindler systems could perhaps be used for studying and testing such models.

Finally, and perhaps most importantly, we would like to establish a more rigorous framework that would allow us to formally define an ICO space-time related to a general quantum reference frame. This could be an important step towards a better understanding of the quantum nature of space-time.

Data Availability Statement

All datasets generated for this study are included in the article.

Author Contributions

AD, MM, DG, and ČB conceived the research. AD, MM, and DG provided main theoretical idea and equally contributed to writing the paper. NM participated in discussion concerning entangled laboratories. ČB supervised the project.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

This is a significantly revised version of the paper that can already be found on the arXiv [33]. The authors thank Dejan Simić, Marko Vojinović, Nikola Paunković, and Ämin Baumeler for helpful comments. AD, MM, and DG acknowledge support from the bilateral project SRB 02/2018, Causality in Quantum Mechanics and Quantum Gravity, between Austria and Serbia. AD and MM acknowledge support from the project No. ON171035 and D.G. from the project No. ON171031 of Serbian Ministry of Education and Science. Additionally, AD acknowledges support from scholarship awarded from The Austrian Agency for International Cooperation in Education and Research (OeAD-GmbH). AD and DG acknowledge grant FQXi-MGA-1806 that supported their stay in Vienna. AD and DG would also like to thank University of Vienna and IQOQI for hospitality during their stay. NM thanks Marcelo Terra Cunha, Nelson Yokomizo, Raphael Drumond, Leonardo Neves, and Davi Barros for useful discussions. NM acknowledge Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior (CAPES), Conselho Nacional de Desenvolvimento Científico e Tecnológico (CNPq) and Fundação de Amparo à Pesquisa do Estado de Minas Gerais (FAPEMIG) for financial support and VI Paraty Quantum Information School for the introduction into the topic. ČB acknowledges the support from the research platform TURIS, from the European Commission via Testing the Large-Scale Limit of Quantum Mechanics (TEQ) (No. 766900) project, and from the Austrian-Serbian bilateral scientific cooperation no. 451-03-02141/2017-09/02, and by the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) through the SFB project BeyondC and a grant from the Foundational Questions Institute (FQXi) Fund. This publication was made possible through the support of the ID 61466 grant from the John Templeton Foundation, as part of the The Quantum Information Structure of Space-time (QISS) Project (qiss.fr). The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation.

Supplementary Material

The Supplementary Material for this article can be found online at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fphy.2020.525333/full#supplementary-material

References

1. Hardy L. Probability theories with dynamic causal structure: a new framework for quantum gravity. arXiv preprint gr-qc/0509120 (2005)

Google Scholar

2. Hardy L. Towards quantum gravity: a framework for probabilistic theories with non-fixed causal structure. J Phys A: Math Theor (2007) 40:3081–9. doi:10.1088/1751-8113/40/12/s12

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

3. Oreshkov O, Costa F, and Brukner Č. Quantum correlations with no causal order. Nat Commun. (2012) 3:1092. doi:10.1038/ncomms2076

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

4. Chiribella G, D’Ariano GM, Perinotti P, and Valiron B. Quantum computations without definite causal structure. Phys Rev A (2013) 88:022318. doi:10.1103/physreva.88.022318

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Araújo M, Costa F, and Brukner Č. Computational advantage from quantum-controlled ordering of gates. Phys Rev Lett (2014) 113:250402. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.113.250402

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

6. Feix A, Araújo M, and Brukner Č. Quantum superposition of the order of parties as a communication resource. Phys Rev A (2015) 92:052326. doi:10.1103/physreva.92.052326

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

7. Guérin PA, Feix A, Araújo M, and Brukner Č. Exponential communication complexity advantage from quantum superposition of the direction of communication. Phys Rev Lett (2016) 117:100502. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.117.100502

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Ebler D, Salek S, and Chiribella G. Enhanced communication with the assistance of indefinite causal order. Phys Rev Lett (2018) 120:1205020. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.120.120502

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Chiribella G, Giovannetti V, Maccone L, and Perinotti P. Teleportation transfers only speakable quantum information. Phys Rev A (2012) 86:040301. doi:10.1103/physreva.86.010304

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

10. Friis N, Dunjko V, Dür W, and Briegel HJ. Implementing quantum control for unknown subroutines. Phys Rev A (2014) 89:030303. doi:10.1103/physreva.89.030303

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Procopio LM, Moqanaki A, Araújo M, Costa F, Alonso Calafell I, Dowd EG, et al. Experimental superposition of orders of quantum gates. Nat Commun (2015) 6:7913. doi:10.1038/ncomms8913

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

12. Rambo TM, Altepeter JB, Kumar P, and D'Ariano GM. Functional quantum computing: an optical approach. Phys Rev A (2016) 93:052321. doi:10.1103/physreva.93.052321

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

13. Rubino G, Rozema LA, Feix A, Araújo M, Zeuner J. M, Procopio LM, et al. Experimental verification of an indefinite causal order. Sci Adv (2017) 3:e1602589. doi:10.1126/sciadv.1602589

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

14. Goswami K, Giarmatzi C, Kewming M, Costa F, Branciard C, Romero J, et al. Indefinite causal order in a quantum switch. Phys Rev Let (2018) 121:090503. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.121.090503

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

15. Zych M, Costa F, Pikovski I, and Brukner Č. Bell's theorem for temporal order. Nat Commun (2019) 10:3772. doi:10.1038/s41467-019-11579-x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

16. Giacomini F, Castro-Ruiz E, and Brukner Č. Quantum mechanics and the covariance of physical laws in quantum reference frames. Nat Commun (2019) 10:494. doi:10.1038/s41467-018-08155-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Guérin PA, and Brukner Č. Observer-dependent locality of quantum events. New J Phys (2018) 20:103031. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/aae742

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

18. Kaltenbaek R, Aspelmeyer M, Barker PF, Bassi A, Bateman J, Bongs K, et al. Precise and robust optical beam steering for space optical instrumentation. EPJ Quant Technol (2015) 3:5. doi:10.1007/s12567-019-00271-x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Katz BN, Blencowe MP, and Schwab KC. Mesoscopic mechanical resonators as quantum noninertial reference frames. Phys Rev A (2015) 92:042104. doi:10.1103/physreva.92.042104

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

20. Abdi M, Degenfeld-Schonburg P, Sameti M, Navarrete-Benlloch C, and Hartmann MJ. Dissipative optomechanical preparation of macroscopic quantum superposition states. Phys Rev Lett (2016) 116:233604. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.116.233604

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

21. Ockeloen-Korppi CF, Damskägg E, Pirkkalainen J-M, Asjad M, Clerk AA, Massel F, et al. Stabilized entanglement of massive mechanical oscillators. Nature (2018) 556:478. doi:10.1038/s41586-018-0038-x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Feynman R. Chapel Hill conference proceedings, 1957. Available at: http://www.edition-open-sources.org/sources/5/3/.

Google Scholar

23. Anastopoulos C, and Hu BL. Probing a gravitational cat state. Class Quant Grav (2015) 32:165022. doi:10.1088/0264-9381/32/16/165022

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

24. Bose S, Mazumdar A, Morley GW, Ulbricht H, Toroš M, Paternostro M, et al. Spin entanglement witness for quantum gravity. Phys Rev Lett. (2017) 119:240401. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.119.240401

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

25. Marletto C, and Vedral V. Gravitationally induced entanglement between two massive particles is sufficient evidence of quantum effects in gravity. Phys Rev Lett (2017) 119:240402. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.119.240402

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

26. Christodoulou M, and Rovelli C. On the possibility of laboratory evidence for quantum superposition of geometries. Phys Lett B (2019) 792:64–68. doi:10.1016/j.physletb.2019.03.015

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

27. Penrose R. On the gravitization of quantum mechanics 1: quantum state reduction. Found Phys (2014) 44:557–575. doi:10.1007/s10701-013-9770-0

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

28. Zych M, Costa F, and Ralph TC. Relativity of quantum superpositions. arXiv preprint arXiv:1809.04999 (2018)

29. Vanrietvelde A, Hoehn PA, Giacomini F, and Castro-Ruiz E. A change of perspective: switching quantum reference frames via a perspective-neutral framework. Quant (2020) 4:225. doi:10.22331/q-2020-01-27-225

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

30. Joos E, Zeh HD, Kiefer C, Giulini DJ, Kupsch J, and Stamatescu IO. Decoherence and the appearance of a classical world in quantum theory. Berlin, Germany: Springer Science Business Media (2013)

Google Scholar

31. Ghirardi GC, Rimini A, and Weber T. Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Phys Rev D. (1986) 34(2):470. doi:10.1103/physrevd.34.470

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

32. Tumulka R. A relativistic version of the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber model J. Stat. Phys. (2006) 125:821–840.

33. Dimić A, Milivojević M, Gočanin D, and Brukner Č. Simulating spacetime with indefinite causal order via Rindler observers. arXiv preprint arXiv:1712.02689 (2017).

Keywords: Rindler observer, quantum switch, indefinite causal order, equivalence principle, causality

Citation: Dimić A, Milivojević M, Gočanin D, Móller NS and Brukner Č (2020) Simulating Indefinite Causal Order With Rindler Observers. Front. Phys. 8:525333. doi: 10.3389/fphy.2020.525333

Received: 08 January 2020; Accepted: 18 September 2020;
Published: 26 October 2020.

Edited by:

Rosa Poggiani, University of Pisa, Italy

Reviewed by:

Jonathan S Ben-Benjamin, Texas A&M University, United States
Paolo Grigolini, University of North Texas, United States
Rainer Kaltenbaek, University of Ljubljana, Slovenia

Copyright © 2020 Dimić, Milivojević, Gočanin, Móller and Brukner. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Aleksandra Dimić, aleksandra.dimic@ff.bg.ac.rs

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.