- School of Speech, Language, and Hearing Sciences, San Diego State University, San Diego, CA, United States
1. Introduction
Modern humans are biologically predisposed to the ability to create symbolic elements and to combine them systematically to share feelings, thoughts, or beliefs. In considering paleoanthropological evidence, we hypothesize that this particular innate ability emerged in early members of the Homo group but evolved from (nonhuman) primates. Here, we identify four, closely interconnected evolutionary stages that may have brought about an extended syntax: (a) binary signal binding, (b) symbolic signs, (c) pragmatic grammar and (d) extended syntax. Basic signal binding can be occasionally observed in primates. Various cortical changes in the early hominin lineage enabled the creation of symbolic signs (words) and a pragmatic grammar consisting of two or three words. At this stage, cognitive strategies (e.g., AGENT-first) may have mimicked perceived event-structures and determined asymmetry between these words. Finally, lexical grouping, syntactic frames, argument structures, semantic roles and morphological markers are the outcome of an accumulative cultural process that resulted in an extended syntax. We conclude that the origin of syntax is deeply conceptually rooted and emerged along with an increase of cognitive control, rehearsal and global workspace capacity (Baars et al., 2013; Aboitiz, 2018a,b; Corballis, 2019).
Our evolutionary syntax approach is in sharp contrast to the minimalist program which claims that syntactic recursion is an innate property of a universal grammar (e.g., Chomsky, 1965; Hauser et al., 2002; Berwick and Chomsky, 2016). Although we do not argue against the idea of a universal grammar, we do not consider syntactic recursion, which iteratively merges syntactic objects of the lexicon to create bottom-up larger phrases in a binary fashion (Kayne, 1984), as crucial for defining the human language capacity. For example, hit has the feature “uninterpretable noun” and ball “object noun,” which projects hit as being prominent compared to ball (Chomsky, 2001, 2004). Merge, which can be infinitely recursively applied to its own output, continuous after this initial step with a bottom-up binary operation. In the case of a simple declarative sentence, such as Bill hit the ball, labeling will be projected by the head (the prominent word of the respective set), and 6x binary hierarchical branching of {x{xx}}is required. The generated tree structure is relatively complex for a short declarative phrase but it is considered as minimal because the same computation applies iteratively.
More recent evidence favor user-based computational accounts, such as construction, unification grammar, or simpler syntax because they cover many syntactic patterns, including syntactic frames and various degrees of lexical freedom, not covered by the generative approach (e.g., Culicover and Jackendoff, 2005; Goldberg, 2005). Thus, the generative approach complements a computational syntax model. Construction-based models, for example, do not rely on a single binary operation but emphasize multiple branching (Shieber, 1986). They consider in particular, the idiomaticity, fixedness, and scheme-like structure of an expression or phrase (e.g., Fillmore et al., 1988; Goldberg and Suttle, 2010; Hoffmann, 2022). English examples are semi-fixed expressions (e.g., weapons of mass destruction or look the answer up) that must be part of the mental lexicon (Jackendoff and Wittenberg, 2014, 2017). Phrasal idiomaticity and fixedness are a matter of degree and affect all sentence types. Such phrasal frame constructions are, for example, “the X-er the Y-er” (comparative correlates), “X causes Y to move Z” (caused-motion frames), “the more X, the less Y,” “X was V-ed by Y” (passive sentence). Other examples are syntactic nuts, such as the grammar of geographic names (*the River of X or *the X River) or number systems (Jackendoff, 1997, 1999, 2011; Jackendoff and Wittenberg, 2017). Syntactic frames with different grades of flexibility defined by variables are not a peripheral linguistic typology but a core property of all languages.
Construction-based and Merge accounts do not exclude each other. Merge is a specific structural construction that may be particularly useful in novel formats, for which the speaker did not acquire a scheme. Both approaches are, however, of great significance for discussing the origin of lexical grouping and syntax.
2. Signal binding in primates
Two claims were made in association with the emergence of Merge (Chomsky, 2010; Berwick and Chomsky, 2019; Tattersall, 2019). First, language is the result of a single Merge operation. That is, syntax did not evolve as no intermediate gradual steps are possible: a species has or has no access to Merge. The argument is that the syntactic capacity should be exclusively linked to Homo sapiens since significant archeological finds that may represent symbolic behavior would not be older than 100 k years (Henshilwood et al., 2018). Thus, the claim is that a sudden mutation occurred during this period in some individuals of Homo sapiens. These genetic changes would have led to brain rewiring for the capacity to generate Merge.
Initial Merge can be traced back to various precursor stages, which does not favor but diminishes the claim of a sudden mutation causing brain rewiring in early modern humans. Some favor a structured protosystem that would have been integrated into an extended syntax system (e.g., Di Sciullo, 2013; Miyagawa et al., 2013; Nóbrega and Miyagawa, 2015). However, it remains unclear how the protosystem became ready for integration. It is a post-hoc argument: the properties of a precursor stage do not necessarily reflect properties of the succeeding stage. Moreover, the evolution of brain structures in the human lineage supports an incremental increase of cognitive capacities, including the creation of symbols and lexical grouping (e.g., Pinker and Bloom, 1990; Bickerton, 1998; McBrearty and Brooks, 2000; Johansson, 2005; Kinsella, 2009; Progovac, 2010; Fitch, 2014; Tallerman, 2014, 2017; Hillert, 2015, 2021; Martins and Boeckx, 2019). The all-or-nothing Merge account reminds us of the hopeful monster hypothesis stating that small-scaled mutations cannot produce new species (Goldschmidt, 1940). The botanist Hugo de Vries was one of the most prominent defenders of such a saltation model at the turn of the 19th century (De Vries, 1901–03). Still, his evidence refers to plants rather than to cortical evolution (Zuberbühler, 2019).
If initial grouping is defined as a binary set requiring a label, it can be decomposed into different subcomponents. Based on observations with monkeys and chimpanzees, this may include the production of discrete vocal signals or binary vocal signal binding. The latter structure is in most cases asymmetric. The positional structure is typically fixed rather than free and is perceptually driven (e.g., AGENT-first). Studies with encultured and wild great apes show that signed or vocalized binary binding is the main combinatory operation to express pragmatic needs (e.g., Greenfield and Savage-Rumbaugh, 1991; Crockford and Boesch, 2005; Spillmann et al., 2010; Clay and Zuberbühler, 2011; Hedwig et al., 2015; Schlenker et al., 2016; Girard-Buttoz et al., 2022). The order of the elements is, in principle, free but seems to follow mostly pragmatic strategies. The workspace capacity of monkeys and great apes restricts emittance to small sequences (Pasternak and Greenlee, 2005; Read et al., 2022). It is most significant that great apes never start to develop a symbolic system on their own to communicate beyond their immediate needs. Further studies are required to suggest that they vocalize about events in the past and future.
3. Acquisition of extended syntax
Typically developing children produce at around 18–24 months largely two-word utterances, such as want-juice or car-go. Inflections or function words are rarely produced during this two-word stage (Bloom, 1993). If the language acquisition process is delayed, the child still goes through this stage. Two deaf children who were not exposed to sign language until the age of 6 years showed the same acquisition pattern (Berk and Lillo-Martin, 2012). Bigrams are also the basic syntactic layer of particular sign languages. The first generation of deaf children of the “Idioma de Señas de Nicaragua” combined signs to bigrams such as AGENT-EVENT, and the next generation elaborated on these structures (e.g., Senghas et al., 2004). Similarly, adult speakers, who learn a second language without explicit instructions, acquire first bigrams before they learn more extended syntactic structures (Klein and Perdue, 1997). The trend is to acquire first content words without inflections and to rely on a pragmatic word-order strategy. For example, the AGENT-first strategy is sufficient in interpreting the free-ordered sequence hit girl boy as The girl hit the boy.
Again, headless phrases are common in the Malayan dialect “Riau Indonesian” (Gil, 2005). An often-quoted example is the word pair comprising makan (chicken) and ayam (eat). The free-positioned word pairs makan ayam or ayam makan are open to the same readings and unmarked for grammatical roles. The speaker's semantic network consist not only of lexical relations but may also include situational attributes. An asymmetry is not syntactically marked but mentally represented (e.g., X eat chicken may be a more frequent reading than Chicken eat Y). Generally, the range of language typologies, which primarily displays grammar by inflections (polysynthetic) or word order (analytic), varies strongly concerning lexical grouping and dependencies. Although the basic syntactic layer of human language and great apes appears to be quite similar regarding the use of bigrams, there is a critical difference: at an early age, the human child already has access to a large number of words which they can freely combine without any boundaries, a mental property great apes lack.
4. Discussion
The literature discusses numerous factors on how syntax might have emerged from basic signal binding in nonhuman great apes. Without discussing specific socioecological conditions, most critical is the evolution of full bipedalism, the expansion and rewiring of cortical structures, along with the evolution of workspace systems, control circuits, and structure-building capacities for self-organization and planning (Aboitiz, 1995, 2018b; Murphy and Benítez-Burraco, 2018; Murphy, 2019). About 3.4 mya Australopithecus africanus (Stw 505 Sterkfontein), whose brain was not larger than that of chimpanzees, had a posterior placement of the lunate sulcus (Holloway et al., 2004). It implies that the temporal lobe (TL) increased. In modern humans, this structure has various language-related functions, amongst other the anterior TL is involved in semantic and the posterior TL in syntactic processing (e.g., Levy et al., 2004; Matar et al., 2021).
The hominin evolution had a significant breakthrough after the appearance of Homo erectus, about 1.8 mya. Their brain size increased to 950–1,230 cc (Rightmire, 2013), reaching almost the size of modern humans with 1,350 cc. Moreover, they had human-like prefrontal and temporoparietal regions, including a Broca's cap morphology (Rilling et al., 2008; Holloway, 2015; Nishimura, 2018; Ponce de León et al., 2021). Homo erectus was a Homo faber. He developed and refined the Acheulian tool industry, used fire, had a hunter-gatherer culture, traveled to East China and Java, and even produced symbol-like objects indicated by engraved Trinil shells (Dubois, 1894; Joordens et al., 2015; Rizal et al., 2020). Most traces suggest that this species developed a premodern language system to coordinate their activities and increase the chance of survival in challenging conditions. However, what kind of language system did our ancestors create?
Considering that structure-building is a piecemeal sociological process, we assume that this species developed a symbol system and a pragmatic grammar consisting of two to three symbolic elements. The development of event-based discrete iconic and then symbolic signs must have followed emotional signals used by primates, whereas we assume that vocal signs gradually replaced gestures due to an increasing demand for manual actions, such as tool development. Along with the development of words, they were pairwise combined according to recurrent perceived event-structures. Then, an unspecified binary and a ternary mental scheme were created through unspecified set formations, whereas context provides information about prominence. Finally, a head is assigned and provides an asymmetric structure, extendable to a partly flat structure, such as catch-fish-spear: [ACTION [OBJECT, ACTION]] + [TOOL]. These schemes, basic syntactic branching, such as treelets or flat structures, may have been applied to other semantic categories defined today in linguistic theories as argument structures. It is a starting point for diverse syntactic branching and various degrees of lexical freedom that is semantically rooted in our evolutionary ancestry. We conclude that H. erectus' brain was language-ready and extended syntax results from cultural refinements of a pragmatic grammar.
Author contributions
The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to the constructive comments of the reviewers.
Conflict of interest
The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
The author DH declared that they were an editorial board member of Frontiers, at the time of submission. This had no impact on the peer review process and the final decision.
Publisher's note
All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.
References
Aboitiz, F. (1995). Working memory networks and the origin of language areas in the human brain. Med. Hypotheses 44, 504–506. doi: 10.1016/0306-9877(95)90514-6
Aboitiz, F. (2018a). A brain for speech. Evolutionary continuity in primate and human auditory-vocal processing. Front. Neurosci. 12, 174. doi: 10.3389/fnins.2018.00174
Aboitiz, F. (2018b). Voice, gesture and working memory in the emergence of speech. Interact. Stud. 19, 70–85. doi: 10.1075/is.17032.abo
Baars, B., Franklin, S., and Ramsøy, T. (2013). Global workspace dynamics: cortical “binding and propagation” enables conscious contents. Front. Psychol. 4, 200. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00200
Berk, S., and Lillo-Martin, D. (2012). The two-word stage: motivated by linguistic or cognitive constraints? Cogn. Psychol. 65, 118–140. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2012.02.002
Berwick, R. C., and Chomsky, N. (2016). Why Only Us. Cambridge MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.7551/mitpress/9780262034241.001.0001
Berwick, R. C., and Chomsky, N. (2019). All or nothing: no half-Merge and the evolution of syntax. PLoS Biol. 17, e3000539. doi: 10.1371/journal.pbio.3000539
Bickerton, D. (1998). “Catastrophic evolution: the case for a single step from protolanguage to full human language,” in Approaches to the Evolution of Language, eds J. R. Hurford, M. Studdert-Kennedy, and C. Knight (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 341–358.
Bloom, L. (1993). The Transition from Infancy to Language: Acquiring the Power of Expression. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511752797
Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. doi: 10.21236/AD0616323
Chomsky, N. (2001). “Derivation by phase,” in Ken Hale: A Life in Language, eds M. Kenstowicz (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 1–52.
Chomsky, N. (2004). “Beyond explanatory adequacy,” in Structures and Beyond, ed A. Belletti (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 104–131.
Chomsky, N. (2010). “Some simple evo devo theses: how true might they be for language?” in The Evolution of Human Language. Biolinguistic Perspectives, eds R. K. Larson, V. Deprez, and H. Yamakido (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 45–62. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511817755.003
Clay, Z., and Zuberbühler, K. (2011). Bonobos extract meaning from call sequences. PLoS ONE 6, e0018786. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0018786
Corballis, M. C. (2019). Language, memory, and mental time travel: an evolutionary perspective. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 13, 217. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2019.00217
Crockford, C., and Boesch, C. (2005). Call combinations in wild chimpanzees. Behaviour 142, 397–421. doi: 10.1163/1568539054012047
Culicover, P. W., and Jackendoff, R. (2005). Simpler Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199271092.001.0001
De Vries, H. (1901–03). Die Mutationstheorie. Versuche und Beobachtungen über die Entstehung von Arten im Pflanzenreich. Leipzig: Veit and Comp (English edition Vol. 2 1909-10). doi: 10.5962/bhl.title.11336
Di Sciullo, A. M. (2013). Exocentric compounds, language and proto-language. Lang. Inf. Soc. 20, 1–25. doi: 10.29211/soli.2013.20..001
Dubois, E. (1894). Pithecanthropus Erectus. Eine Menschenaehnliche Uebergangsform aus Java. New York, NY: G.E. Stechert.
Fillmore, C. J., Kay, P., and O'Connor, M. C. (1988). Regularity and idiomaticity in grammatical constructions: the case of let alone. Language 64, 501–538. doi: 10.2307/414531
Fitch, W. T. (2014). Toward a computational framework for cognitive biology: unifying approaches from cognitive neuroscience and comparative cognition. Phys. Life Rev. 11, 329–364. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2014.04.005
Gil, D. (2005). “Word order without syntactic categories: how riau Indonesian does it,” in Verb First: On the Syntax of Verb-initial Languages, eds A. Carnie, H. Harley, and S. A. Dooley (Amsterdam: John Benjamins), 243–263. doi: 10.1075/la.73.17gil
Girard-Buttoz, C., Zaccarella, E., Bortolato, T., Friederici, A. D., Wittig, R. M., Crockford, C., et al. (2022). Chimpanzees produce diverse vocal sequences with ordered and recombinatorial properties. Commun. Biol. 5, 410. doi: 10.1038/s42003-022-03350-8
Goldberg, A. (2005). Constructions at Work. The Nature of Generalization in Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199268511.001.0001
Goldberg, A. E., and Suttle, L. (2010). Construction grammar. Wires Cogn. Sci. 1, 468–477. doi: 10.1002/wcs.22
Greenfield, P. M., and Savage-Rumbaugh, E. S. (1991). “Imitation grammatical development and the invention of protogrammar by an ape,” in Biological Behavioral Determinants of Language Development, eds N. A. Krasnegor, D. M. Rumbaugh, R. L. Schiefelbusch, and M. Studdert-Kennedy (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum), 235–257.
Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N., and Fitch, W. T. (2002). The faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve? Science 298, 1569–1579. doi: 10.1126/science.298.5598.1569
Hedwig, D., Mundry, R., Robbins, M. M., and Boesch, C. (2015). Contextual correlates of syntactic variation in mountain and western gorilla close-distance vocalizations: indications for lexical or phonological syntax? Anim. Cogn. 18, 423–435. doi: 10.1007/s10071-014-0812-6
Henshilwood, C. S., d'Errico, F., van Niekerk, K. L., Dayet, L., Queffelec, A., and Pollarolo, L. (2018). An abstract drawing from the 73,000-year-old levels at Blombos Cave, South Africa. Nature 562, 115–118. doi: 10.1038/s41586-018-0514-3
Hillert, D. (2021). How did language evolve in the lineage of higher primates? Lingua 264, 103158. doi: 10.1016/j.lingua.2021.103158
Hillert, D. G. (2015). On the evolving biology of language. Front. Psychol. 24, 1796. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01796
Hoffmann, T. (2022). Construction Grammar. The structure of English. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Holloway, R. L. (2015). “The evolution of the hominid brain,” in Handbook of Paleoanthropology, eds W. Henke, and I. Tattersall (Berlin: Springer), 1961–1987. doi: 10.1007/978-3-642-39979-4_81
Holloway, R. L., Clark, R. J., and Tobias, P. V. (2004). Posterior lunate sulcus in Australopithecus africanus: was Dart right? Comptes Rendus Palevol 3, 287–293. doi: 10.1016/j.crpv.2003.09.030
Jackendoff, R. (1999). Possible stages in the evolution of language. Trends in Cogn. Sci. 3, 272–279. doi: 10.1016/S1364-6613(99)01333-9
Jackendoff, R. (2011). “Alternative minimalist visions of language,” in Non-transformational Syntax: Formal and Explicit Models of Grammar, eds R. D. Borsley, and K. Börjars (Oxford: Blackwell), 268–296. doi: 10.1002/9781444395037.ch7
Jackendoff, R., and Wittenberg, E. (2014). “What you can say without syntax: a hierarchy of grammatical complexity,” in Measuring Grammatical Complexity, eds F. J. Newmeyer and L. B. Preston (Oxford: Oxford Academic), 65–82. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199685301.003.0004
Jackendoff R. and Wittenberg, E.. (2017). Linear grammar as a possible stepping-stone in the evolution of language. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 24, 219–224. doi: 10.3758/s13423-016-1073-y
Johansson, S. (2005). Origins of Language: Constraints on Hypotheses. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. doi: 10.1075/celcr.5
Joordens, J. C. A., d'Errico, F., Wesselingh, F. P., Munro, S., de Vos, J., Wallinga, J., et al. (2015). Homo erectus at Trinil on Java used shells for tool production and engraving. Nature 518, 228–231. doi: 10.1038/nature13962
Kinsella, A. R. (2009). Language Evolution and Syntactic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511596919
Klein, W., and Perdue, C. (1997). The basic variety (or: couldn't natural languages be much simpler?). Second Lang. Res. 13, 301–347. doi: 10.1191/026765897666879396
Levy, D. A., Bayley, P. J., and Squire, L. R. (2004). The anatomy of semantic knowledge: medial vs. lateral temporal lobe. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 101, 6710–6715. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0401679101
Martins, P. T., and Boeckx, C. (2019). Language evolution and complexity considerations: the no half-Merge fallacy. PLoS Biol. 17, e3000389. doi: 10.1371/journal.pbio.3000389
Matar, S., Dirani, J., Marantz, A., and Pylkkänen, L. (2021). Left posterior temporal cortex is sensitive to syntax within conceptually matched Arabic expressions. Sci Rep 11, 7181. doi: 10.1038/s41598-021-86474-x
McBrearty and Brooks, A.S.. (2000). The revolution that wasn't: a new interpretation of the origin of modern human behavior. J. Hum. Evol. 39, 453–563. doi: 10.1006/jhev.2000.0435
Miyagawa, S., Berwick, R. C., and Okanoya, K. (2013). The emergence of hierarchical structure in human language. Front Psychol. 4, 71. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00071
Murphy, E. (2019). No country for Oldowan men: emerging factors in language evolution. Front. Psychol. 10, 1448. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01448
Murphy, E., and Benítez-Burraco, A. (2018). Toward the language oscillogenome. Front. Psychol. 9, 1999. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01999
Nishimura, T. (2018). The descended larynx and the descending larynx. Anthropol. Sci. 126, 3–8. doi: 10.1537/ase.180301
Nóbrega, V. A., and Miyagawa, S. (2015). The precedence of syntax in the rapid emergence of human language in evolution as defined by the integration hypothesis. Front Psychol. 6, 271. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00271
Pasternak, T., and Greenlee, M. (2005). Working memory in primate sensory systems. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 6, 97–107. doi: 10.1038/nrn1603
Pinker, S., and Bloom, P. (1990). Natural language and natural selection. Behav. Brain Sci. 13, 707–784. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X00081061
Ponce de León, M. S., Bienvenu, T., Marom, A., Engel, S., Tafforeau P, Alatorre Warren, J. L., et al. (2021). The primitive brain of early Homo. Science. 3372, 165–171. doi: 10.1126/science.aaz0032
Progovac, L. (2010). “When clauses refuse to be recursive: an evolutionary perspective,” in Recursion and Human Language, ed H. van der Hulst (Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton), 193–211. doi: 10.1515/9783110219258.193
Read, D. W., Manrique, H. M., and Walker, M. J. (2022). On the working memory of humans and great apes: strikingly similar or remarkably different? Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 134, 104496. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2021.12.019
Rightmire, G. P. (2013). Homo erectus and Middle Pleistocene hominins: brain size, skull form, and species recognition. J. Hum. Evol. 65, 223–52. doi: 10.1016/j.jhevol.2013.04.008
Rilling, J. K., Glasser, M. F., Preuss, T. M., Ma, X., Zhao, T., Hu, X., et al. (2008). The evolution of the arcuate fasciculus revealed with comparative DTI. Nat. Neurosci. 11, 426–428. doi: 10.1038/nn2072
Rizal, Y., Westaway, K. E., Zaim, Y., van den Bergh, G. D., Bettis, E. A., Morwood, M. J, et al. (2020). Last appearance of Homo erectus at Ngandong Java 117000-108000 years ago. Nature 577, 381–385. doi: 10.1038/s41586-019-1863-2
Schlenker, P., Chemla, E., and Zuberbühler, K. (2016). What Do Monkey Calls Mean? Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 894–904. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2016.10.004
Senghas, A., Kita, S., and Ozyurek, A. (2004). Children creating core properties of language: evidence from an emerging sign language in Nicaragua. Science 305, 1779–1782. doi: 10.1126/science.1100199
Spillmann, B., Dunkel, L. P., Noordwijk, M. A., Amda, R. N., Lameira, A. R., Wich, S. A., et al. (2010). Acoustic properties of long calls given by flanged male orang-utans (Pongo pygmaeus wurmbii) reflect both individual identity and context. Ethology 116, 385–395. doi: 10.1111/J.1439-0310.2010.01744.X
Tallerman, M. (2014). No syntax saltation in language evolution. Lang. Sci. 46(B), 207–219. doi: 10.1016/j.langsci.2014.08.002
Tallerman, M. (2017). Can the integration hypothesis account for language evolution? J. Neurolinguistics 43(B), 254–262. doi: 10.1016/j.jneuroling.2016.06.006
Tattersall, I. (2019). The minimalist program and the origin of language: a view from paleoantyhropology. Front. Psychol. 10, 677. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00677
Keywords: Homo erectus, language evolution, lexical grouping, pragmatic grammar, syntax, workspace
Citation: Hillert DG (2023) On how “early syntax” came about. Front. Lang. Sci. 2:1251498. doi: 10.3389/flang.2023.1251498
Received: 01 July 2023; Accepted: 07 August 2023;
Published: 21 August 2023.
Edited by:
Antonio Benítez-Burraco, University of Seville, SpainReviewed by:
Elliot Murphy, University of Texas Health Science Center at Houston, United StatesShigeru Miyagawa, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, United States
Copyright © 2023 Hillert. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Dieter G. Hillert, ZGhpbGxlcnQmI3gwMDA0MDtzZHN1LmVkdQ==