- 1Center for Neuropsychological Research and Department of Neurosciences, Institute of Neurology Policlinico Gemelli, Catholic University of Rome, Rome, Italy
- 2Department of Clinical and Behavioral Neurology, IRCCS Fondazione Santa Lucia, Rome, Italy
The present review aims to summarize the debate in contemporary neuroscience between inborn and experience-dependent models of conceptual representations that goes back to the description of category-specific semantic disorders for biological and artifact categories. Experience-dependent models suggest that categorical disorders are the by-product of the differential weighting of different sources of knowledge in the representation of biological and artifact categories. These models maintain that semantic disorders are not really category-specific, because they do not respect the boundaries between different categories. They also argue that the brain structures which are disrupted in a given type of category-specific semantic disorder should correspond to the areas of convergence of the sensory-motor information which play a major role in the construction of that category. Furthermore, they provide a simple interpretation of gender-related categorical effects and are supported by studies assessing the importance of prior experience in the cortical representation of objects On the other hand, inborn models maintain that category-specific semantic disorders reflect the disruption of innate brain networks, which are shaped by natural selection to allow rapid identification of objects that are very relevant for survival. From the empirical point of view, these models are mainly supported by observations of blind subjects, which suggest that visual experience is not necessary for the emergence of category-specificity in the ventral stream of visual processing. The weight of the data supporting experience-dependent and inborn models is thoroughly discussed, stressing the fact observations made in blind subjects are still the subject of intense debate. It is concluded that at the present state of knowledge it is not possible to choose between experience-dependent and inborn models of conceptual representations.
Introduction
Contemporary debates about the foundations of categories and concepts have very ancient roots. Indeed, discussions about the nature of concepts, which have tried to clarify whether or not they are essentially grounded in our senses and in our actions with objects, go back to the early days of Plato and Aristotle (Kiefer and Pulvermüller, 2012; Markie, 2013). According to Plato and other rationalist philosophers concepts are mental entities and are fundamentally distinct from sensory impressions. By contrast, according to Aristotle and other empiricist philosophers all concepts are derived from sensory experiences. The rationalist position has been endorsed in more recent years by Pylyshyn (1973), Fodor (1975), Caramazza et al. (1990) and Patterson and Hodges (2000). These authors proposed the existence of a unitary, abstract and amodal semantic system, that is accessed by the highest levels of the various perceptual modalities (“structural descriptions”), which include a complete perceptual specification of objects prior to their meaningful recognition. According to the above mentioned cognitive authors, there are no traces of the various sensory-motor modalities beyond the level of the corresponding “structural descriptions”, because the format of semantic representations is symbolic, abstract, amodal and propositional. On the contrary, the “empirical” line of thought has been endorsed in recent years by Allport (1985) and Jackendoff (1987). These authors challenged the model of an abstract and amodal conceptual/semantic system. They claimed that conceptual representations keep the stamp of the perceptual mechanisms through which they were formed and are stored in the same format in which they were constructed by the sensory-motor experience. Drawing in part on the latter cognitive models and in part on Hebb’s (1949) model of “cell assemblies”, Damasio (1989, 1990), proposed the dynamic construct of “higher-order convergence zones”, which assumes that concepts are retrieved by a process of recollection of modality-specific bits of memories, that are stored near the sensory portals and motor output sites of the system. Damasio’s (1989, 1990) construct of “higher-order convergence zones” was refined by Barsalou (1999, 2008), who added the similarity-in-topography (SIT) principle (Simmons and Barsalou, 2003), according to which the proximity of two conjunctive neurons in a convergence zone increases with the similarity of the features they conjoin. As a result, conjunctive neurons become topographically organized into local regions that represent properties and categories. From the viewpoint of the cognitive neurosciences, an important difference between the rationalist and the empiricist approach concerns the fact that these two lines of thought have different neurobiological implications concerning the anatomical correlates of conceptual representations. The rationalist approach, which assumes that conceptual categories are represented in an abstract and amodal format, has no reason to make predictions about the brain structures subsuming concepts in general or specific categories of knowledge. On the other hand, the empiricist approach, which assumes that conceptual categories result from the convergence in specific cortical areas of sensory-motor information that plays a leading role in the construction of each category, allows making predictions based on what is known about the brain structures processing this sensory-motor information.
In the following sections of this survey, I will first consider the neuropsychological data about category-specific semantic disorders on which all the theoretical models and the controversies among these models are based. Then I will identify the brain structures that process the sensory-motor information on which our knowledge of different categories could be based and their involvement in category-specific semantic disorders. My next step will be to analyze the arguments of inborn and experience-dependent models of categorical brain organization, including their interpretation of gender-related effects in category-specific semantic disorders and of the relationships between tool knowledge and the left ventral fronto-parietal areas. In this section I will discuss data which suggest that innate connectivity patterns mediate the integration of information critical for the organization of each category. Finally, I will survey experimental data supporting the importance of prior experience in the cortical representation of objects.
Neuropsychological Studies of Category-Specific Disorders Tend to Support Sensorimotor Models of Semantic Knowledge
The Discovery of “Category-Specific” Semantic Disorders
The data on category-specific semantic disorders, on which all of the following theoretical models (and in particular the empiricists’ predictions) are based, can be traced back to a seminal series of papers in which Warrington et al. showed that the disruption of conceptual knowledge is not necessarily homogeneous across categories but is sometimes “category-specific” (Warrington and McCarthy, 1983, 1987; Warrington and Shallice, 1984). These category-specific semantic disorders usually affect the biological (“living”) more than the artifact (“non-living”) categories, but sometimes preferentially impair the artifact categories (see Saffran and Schwartz, 1994; Gainotti et al., 1995; Gainotti, 2000, 2005; Capitani et al., 2003 for reviews). Warrington et al. (Warrington and McCarthy, 1983, 1987; Warrington and Shallice, 1984) also noticed that in their patients the semantic disorders did not respect the boundaries between biological and artifact categories. For instance, the representation of “body parts” tended to be disrupted in association with the representation of artifact categories, whereas the representation of “musical instruments” tended to be disrupted in association with the representation of living items. This was explained as due to the fact that our knowledge of animals and musical knowledge is based on similar visual (shape) and acoustic (sound) information, whereas our knowledge of body parts and tools (or other artifacts) is mainly based on actions and somato-sensory information. More generally, these observations suggested that “category-specific semantic disorders” are not due to disruption of true “biological” and “artifact” categories, but are rather the by-product of a more basic dichotomy, concerning the differential weighting that visual-perceptual and functional attributes have in the representation of biological and, respectively, artifact categories. Warrington’s model (which has been called “the differential weighting hypothesis”) is based on the assumption that each conceptual representation derives from the convergence of different sensory, motor and verbal features, but that the weight of these features is different for different conceptual categories. For example, the distinction between a lion, a tiger and a leopard is mainly based on visual features, namely the plain, striped or spotted aspect of their skin. On the other hand, tools and other artifacts are distinguished by making reference to the actions they require and the functions they support and only marginally to their visual features. As the weight of the features that converge in a conceptual representation is related to the subject’s experience, this model implies that conceptual representations are experience-dependent. Furthermore, since Warrington et al. had maintained that our knowledge of biological entities is mainly based upon their perceptual features, whereas our knowledge of artifacts in mainly based upon their function, this model was called the Sensory/Functional Theory/SFT.
Objections Raised to the Sensory/Functional Theory and Emergence of the “Sensory-Motor Models of Semantic Knowledge”
Several objections were raised against the SFT by Caramazza et al. (e.g., Caramazza, 1998; Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Capitani et al., 2003; Mahon and Caramazza, 2003; Caramazza and Mahon, 2006) and by other authors following a similar line of thought. The first objection was that there is no consistent correlation between conceptual impairment for living things and greater disruption of visual knowledge compared with functional knowledge (see Caramazza, 1998; Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Mahon and Caramazza, 2001; Capitani et al., 2003 for discussion). There are, however, cases of intensively studied patients with category-specific semantic impairments for living things (e.g., Basso et al., 1988; Sartori and Job, 1988; Silveri and Gainotti, 1988; De Renzi and Lucchelli, 1994; Gainotti and Silveri, 1996; Rosazza et al., 2003) in whom the disproportionate impairment of the visual (i.e., compared with the functional) attributes predicted by the SFT, has been confirmed. On the other hand, the review by Capitani et al. (2003) raised methodological issues with some of those studies and the study by Rosazza et al. (2003) was challenged by Mahon and Caramazza (2004). In any case, the comparison between visual and functional knowledge of living beings is hindered by the need to define what is the meaning of a “functional” attribute when dealing with animals, in particular wild animals. More generally, “functional features” are a heterogeneous class of properties that includes actions accomplished with objects, notions about the objects’ use and verbally-mediated encyclopedic knowledge. This fact has been stressed, for instance, by Buxbaum et al. (2000), Buxbaum and Saffran (2002) and Boronat et al. (2005), who have distinguished, within functional knowledge, the function of an object from its manipulation, suggesting that since “manipulation” is related to a sensorimotor activity, it could be the component most tightly linked to the “differential weighting” hypothesis. Furthermore, the same authors showed that not only the properties denoted by the term “functional” are heterogeneous, but also those subsumed by the term “sensory” because different types of sensory data could have different weights in different kinds of semantic categories. Thus, visual perception could play a leading role in the mental representation of animals and somatosensory data in that of tools. These considerations led several authors (e.g., Gainotti et al., 1995; Chao et al., 1999; Gainotti, 2000, 2006; Martin et al., 2000; Martin and Chao, 2001; Martin, 2007; Barsalou, 2008) to suggest that the “sensory-functional theory” should be replaced with the “embodied cognition” theory (Barsalou, 2008) or with the “sensory-motor model of semantic knowledge”, (Gainotti et al., 1995; Chao et al., 1999; Gainotti, 2000, 2006; Martin et al., 2000; Martin and Chao, 2001; Martin, 2007). The latter takes into account various kinds of perceptual, functional, motor and verbally-coded properties, that can contribute to the construction of a conceptual representation. Other important models that have tried to explain the differences between biological and artifact categories on the basis of the different set of underlying features and of their interconnections are the correlated feature based (CFB) accounts (e.g., Tyler et al., 2000; Tyler and Moss, 2001; Randall et al., 2004; Bright et al., 2005, 2007; Taylor et al., 2009, 2011). These models underline the different levels of interconnections that exist between shared (perceptual and functional) attributes of living and non-living things and assume that this structural difference is more important than the differential weighting of perceptual and functional attributes in explaining category-specific semantic disorders. Although these models are interesting, they will not be taken into account here because they would not allow us to make clear predictions about the experience-dependent vs. innate models of conceptual representations.
Objections to Warrington’s “Differential Weighting Hypothesis”
The second objection raised by Caramazza et al. to the SFT is that the assumption of differential weighting of sensory and functional information in the representation of living things and artifacts is not systematically confirmed by studies conducted in normal subjects. In fact, Farah and McClelland (1991) and Caramazza and Shelton (1998) obtained conflicting results when they tried to assess the weight of different kinds of information in the representation of different conceptual categories in healthy subjects, by asking them to underline either visual or functional descriptors in dictionary definitions of living things or artifacts. Farah and McClelland (1991) found a much larger ratio of visual to functional attributes for living beings than for artifacts, whereas Caramazza and Shelton (1998) found only a non significant difference between these two domains of knowledge. These results were discrepant because in Farah and McClelland’s (1991) study a property was considered “functional” only if it described “what the item does or what it is for,” whereas in Caramazza and Shelton’s (1998) study all “non-sensorial” (namely functional, encyclopedic, etc.) descriptors were contrasted with the sensory properties. Feature lists were used by other authors (e.g., McRae and Cree, 2002; Cree and McRae, 2003; Vanoverberghe and Storms, 2003; Ventura et al., 2005; Zannino et al., 2006) to check the assumption of a differential weighting of sensory and functional information in the representation of living things and artifacts. These studies have generally provided an empirical support for the claim that sensory and functional features have different importance in the representation of living and non-living entities, but, as Hoffman and Lambon Ralph (2013) have rightly noted, feature lists may not give a complete picture of how knowledge is distributed amongst the various sensory-motor modalities available from our experience of the environment. Much more appropriate for testing the principles of the “sensory-motor model of conceptual knowledge” is a method proposed by Tranel et al. (1997b) and used by Gainotti et al. (2009, 2013a) and Hoffman and Lambon Ralph (2013). This method consists of asking normal subjects to evaluate (with Likert scales) the influence of different perceptual (visual, auditory, tactual, olfactory, and gustative) and motor activities, as well as encyclopedic information, in the mental representation of living and artifact categories. Using this procedure, all these authors showed: (a) that normal subjects consider the visual modality the main source of knowledge for all (biological and artifact) categories taken into account; and (b) that in biological categories the most important source of knowledge after vision is represented by other perceptual modalities, whereas in artifact categories it is represented by the actions performed with objects.
Apart from the major importance attributed to vision in the mental representation of every kind of concrete entity (which is not surprising if we consider that most of our knowledge of the world is acquired through this sensory modality) other perceptual data therefore prevailed in the representation of biological entities, whereas actions and somatosensory data prevailed in the representation of artifact categories. Taken together, all these data suggest that the greatest difference between living and artifact categories does not reside in the prominent role played by vision in the representation of living beings, and by functional features in the representation of artifacts, but in the interaction between visual data and other perceptual (auditory, olfactory, and gustatory) attributes in the case of living beings, and among visual data, action-related properties, and somato-sensory information, in the case of artifacts.
The Hypothesis of an “Innate” Categorical Organization of Conceptual Knowledge
The third more general objection raised by Caramazza et al. (e.g., Caramazza, 1998; Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Mahon and Caramazza, 2001, 2003; Capitani et al., 2003; Caramazza and Mahon, 2006) to the SFT (and other similar models) concerns the assumption that “category-specific semantic disorders” may be due to the different weight of different sources of knowledge in the construction of different categories, rather than to the disruption of true “biological” and “artifact” categories. Caramazza et al. labeled their interpretation of category-specific semantic disorders “the domains of knowledge’ hypothesis”; this model assumes the existence of an “innate” categorical organization of conceptual knowledge. More specifically, the “domains of knowledge” hypothesis’ posits that category-specific impairments for animals (potential predators), plant life (possible source of food), and artifacts reflect the disruption of innate brain networks, shaped by natural selection to support rapid identification of objects very relevant for survival. Thus, Caramazza et al. (e.g., Caramazza, 1998; Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Capitani et al., 2003; Mahon and Caramazza, 2003; Caramazza and Mahon, 2006) questioned Warrington et al.’s (Warrington and McCarthy, 1983, 1987; Warrington and Shallice, 1984) statement that in their patients the semantic disorders did not respect the boundaries between biological and artifact categories, because the representation of “body parts” tended to be disrupted in association with that of artifacts, whereas the representation of “musical instruments” tended to be disrupted together with that of living items. These observations of Warrington et al. were, however, confirmed by several authors. For instance, Basso et al. (1988), Damasio (1990), Breedin et al. (1994), Farah et al. (1996), Silveri and Gainotti (1988) and Dixon et al. (2000) confirmed the association between living beings and musical instruments. Similarly, Basso et al. (1988), Hillis and Caramazza (1991), Goldenberg (1992), Hart and Gordon (1992), Breedin et al. (1994), De Renzi and Lucchelli (1994), Forde et al. (1997), Humphreys et al. (1997), Silveri and Gainotti (1988) and Kolinsky et al. (2002) confirmed the association between artifacts and body parts. However, Barbarotto et al. (2001) and Capitani et al. (2003) considered these results as spurious and due to the influence of unmatched “nuisance” variables, such as familiarity, age of acquisition and lexical frequency. On the other hand, this interpretation is at variance with data reported by Dixon et al. (2000), who confirmed the particular status of musical instruments, by using lists of living beings, artifacts and musical instruments that were well controlled for frequency, stimulus complexity and familiarity and by Masullo et al. (2012). Using a Semantic Knowledge Questionnaire (Laiacona et al., 1993), these authors studied a patient affected by a severe apperceptive visual agnosia, and found that the number of errors made on the musical instruments was similar to that obtained on the living categories of animals, fruits and vegetables and significantly higher of that made in the other artifact categories. This difference was still significant when familiarity, frequency of use and prototypicality of each stimulus entered into a logistic regression analysis. Furthermore, these clinical data were confirmed by experiments conducted with a neural network model (Gales et al., 2001), in which living things and musical instruments elicited greater recognition failures than the other categories. The discrepancy between the different accounts of the associations between biological entities and “musical instruments” given by the “sensory-motor model of semantic knowledge” and by the “domains of knowledge hypothesis”, is probably due to the fact that only a partial overlap exists between the sources of knowledge typical of these domains. Thus, visual and auditory attributes play an important role in the representation of both animals and musical instruments, but visual attributes are more important for animals and auditory features for musical instruments. Furthermore, motion is typical of animals, but not of musical instruments. Depending on the exact lesion location and accuracy in the control of nuisance variables, it is therefore possible that the association between animals and musical instruments may be due to joint disruption of their representations or to the influence of uncontrolled nuisance variables.
In conclusion, neuropsychological data are rather consistent with the “sensory-motor model of semantic knowledge”, because the main assumption of this model, namely the hypothesis that various kinds of perceptual, motor and verbally-coded properties may have differential weighting in the construction of different conceptual categories, is strongly supported by empirical data (e.g., Cree and McRae, 2003; Vigliocco et al., 2004; Gainotti et al., 2009, 2013a; Hoffman and Lambon Ralph, 2013). However, the “domains of knowledge hypothesis” raises important methodological objections to interpretations of the neuropsychological data based on the “differential weighting hypothesis”.
The Sensorimotor Models of Semantic Knowledge Allow Explaining the Cerebral Correlates of Biological and Artifact Categories
Anatomical Correlates of Category-Specific Semantic Disorders
Gainotti et al. (1995), Martin et al. (1996) and Gainotti (2000) were the first authors to suggest that the anatomical locus of lesion in category-specific semantic disorders might be informative about the nature of the underlying cognitive impairment. The title of Gainotti’s (2000) paper (“What the locus of brain lesion tells us about the nature of the cognitive defect underlying category-specific disorders”) explicitly stressed this point, which had been hitherto neglected because previous (cognitively oriented) authors (e.g., Warrington and Shallice, 1984; Hart et al., 1985; Warrington and McCarthy, 1987; Sartori and Job, 1988), who had reported the anatomical locus of lesions in their patients, had not proposed a general interpretation of the relationships between clinical and anatomical data. Gainotti (2000) argued that, if distinctive sources of knowledge play a critical role in the construction of different semantic categories, then the brain structures disrupted in a given type of category-specific semantic disorder should correspond to the areas of convergences of the sensory-motor information which has played a major role in the construction of that category. More specifically, the anterior parts of the temporal lobes (where the ventral stream of visual processing converges with auditory, olfactory and gustatory inputs) should play a critical role in the representation of biological entities; and the fronto-temporo-parietal, sensory-motor cortices (where the dorsal stream of visual processing converges with body-related and action-oriented structures) should play a major role in the representation of artifacts. Furthermore, a different degree of lateralization of the brain representation of biological entities and artifacts should be predicted, because the main sources of knowledge about living beings (namely visual and other perceptual inputs) are bilaterally represented, whereas (in right-handed subjects) the action oriented structures, which provide an important source of knowledge about artifacts, are mainly represented in the left hemisphere, which controls the movements of the right side of the body. Both of these predictions are substantiated by a number of anatomo-clinical and neuroimaging studies. Several reviews of the anatomical correlates of category-specific semantic disorders (e.g., Saffran and Schwartz, 1994; Gainotti et al., 1995; Damasio et al., 1996; Tranel et al., 1997a; Gainotti, 2000, 2005, 2006; Capitani et al., 2003), have, indeed, confirmed the critical role played by lesions of the anterior parts of the temporal lobes in semantic disorders for biological entities. These reviews showed that brain structures located in the rostral parts of the ventral stream of visual processing (such as the infero-temporal (IT) cortices) or integrating highly processed visual data with other sensory modalities (such as the perirhinal and entorhinal cortices) are usually disrupted in patients with category-specific semantic disorders for living things. Data consistent with these views were also obtained by Strauss et al. (2000) and by Luckhurst and Lloyd-Jones (2001), who showed that temporal lobectomy patients are disproportionately more impaired in naming living than nonliving entities.
Results of Functional Neuroimaging Investigations
Data in agreement with this model were also obtained in a series of neuroimaging studies by Grabowski et al. (2001), Devlin et al. (2002), Tyler et al. (2004), Bright et al. (2005) and Moss et al. (2005). These authors showed that the human perirhinal cortex and neighboring anterior temporal structures provide the neural infrastructure for living categories. For instance, Devlin et al. (2002) entered data from seven PET studies into a single multifactorial design which crossed category (living vs. man-made) with a range of tasks and found that living things activated medial aspects of the anterior temporal poles bilaterally and that tools activated a left posterior middle temporal region. On the other hand, Bright et al. (2005) reviewed recent neuropsychological and neuroimaging studies and found that the human perirhinal cortex and contiguous anteromedial temporal structures provide the neural infrastructure for making fine-grained discriminations among objects. This suggests that damage within the perirhinal cortex may underlie the emergence of category-specific semantic deficits for living things.
If we pass from living beings to artifacts, we see that lesions of a network involving the infero-lateral part of the left frontal lobe, the left inferior parietal lobe and the left middle temporal gyrus, where different components of action schemata are represented (see Saygin et al., 2004), provoke prevalent impairment for tools and other man-made artifacts, whose knowledge is mainly based upon active manipulation and physical contact with objects. This claim is not only supported by the results of Gainotti’s (2000) systematic review of the anatomical correlates of category-specific semantic disorders, but also by other more recent reviews (e.g., Capitani et al., 2003; Kellenbach et al., 2003; Gainotti, 2005, 2013; Buxbaum and Kalénine, 2010; Campanella et al., 2010).
In conclusion, results of anatomo-clinical and of functional neuroimaging investigations confirm that distinctive sources of knowledge have a critical role in the construction of different semantic categories and that the brain structures disrupted in a given type of category-specific semantic disorder (or activated in neuroimaging experiments using items from the same category) overlap with areas of convergence of sensory-motor information which has a major role in the construction of that category. The main results of anatomo-clinical and of functional neuroimaging investigations on the cerebral correlates of biological and artifact categories are reported in Figure 1.
Figure 1. In the upper part of the figure are reported the left hemisphere brain structures that play a critical role in the representation of tools and other artifacts. Within this network, the inferior frontal cortex subsumes action-related features, the inferior parietal cortex is connected with somato-sensory information and the middle temporal gyrus processes visual information, coming through the dorsal stream of visual processing and concerning the objects’ movements. In the lower part of the figure are reported the connections between the anterior temporal lobes, which bilaterally subsume the representations of living beings and the sources of knowledge that mainly contribute to the construction of these representations: visual and auditory features for the category of animals and visual, gustatory and olfactory features for the plant-life categories (flowers, fruits and vegetables). Both right and left anterior temporal lobes are equally involved in the representation of living beings because the perceptual sources of knowledge on which these categories are based are bilaterally represented. By contrast, the network subsuming tools and artifacts knowledge is lateralized to the left hemisphere because the action-related and somato-sensory information on which these categories are based come (in right-handed subjects) from the right side of the body.
Inborn and Experience-Dependent Models of Categorical Brain Organization and the Interpretation of Gender-Related Effects
The Domains of Knowledge’ Hypothesis
In previous sections of this review, we saw that the “embodied cognition” theory (Barsalou, 2008) and the “sensory-motor model of semantic knowledge”, (Gainotti, 2000, 2006; Martin and Chao, 2001; Martin, 2007) can account for the neuropsychological aspects of category-specific semantic disorders (even if the evidence and the arguments that have been made against those theories cannot be ignored) and allow for correct predictions about the brain structures subsuming specific categories of knowledge. Nevertheless, these models are at variance with the “domains of knowledge’ hypothesis”, proposed by Caramazza et al. (Caramazza, 1998; Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Capitani et al., 2003; Caramazza and Mahon, 2006), which assumes the existence of an “innate” categorical organization of conceptual knowledge, and posits that category-specific impairments for animals (potential predators), plant life (possible source of food), and artifacts reflect the disruption of innate brain networks, which are shaped by natural selection to support rapid identification of objects that are very important for survival. The distinction within “living beings” between category-specific disorders for animals and plant life is certainly correct. It is, indeed, supported by at least three sources of evidence: (a) results of hierarchical cluster analyses used in feature listing studies (e.g., Cree and McRae, 2003; Vigliocco et al., 2004 ) or in investigations conducted using Likert scales (e.g., Gainotti et al., 2009, 2013a; Hoffman and Lambon Ralph, 2013), which have documented a tripartite organization of knowledge (with three major clusters corresponding to animals, fruits and vegetables and artifacts); (b) single case studies of patients showing a selective impairment for animals (e.g., Damasio et al., 1990; Hart and Gordon, 1992; De Renzi and Lucchelli, 1994; Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Blundo et al., 2006) or for fruits and vegetables (e.g., Hart et al., 1985; Hanley et al., 1989; Farah and Wallace, 1992; Goldenberg, 1992; Forde et al., 1997; Kensinger et al., 2003; Samson and Pillon, 2003; Siri et al., 2003); and (c) results of a group study conducted by Capitani et al. (2009), which showed that the anatomical locus of lesion is not exactly the same in patients with selective disorders for animals and plant life stimuli.
The Interpretation of Gender-Related Effects
The claim that the difference between animals and plant life categories is inborn and shaped by natural selection was, however, questioned by Gainotti (2005, 2010). This author’s reviews showed that only the distinction between biological and artifact categories reflects an anatomically-based categorical organization and that the discrepancy (within the living entities) between animals and plant life categories is mainly due to gender and social roles related familiarity factors. In fact, Gainotti’s (2005, 2010) reviews showed that in patients with category-specific semantic impairments for living beings men were systematically more impaired with plant life categories and women were usually more impaired with animals. The presence of a gender effect was not unexpected, because an interaction between gender and familiarity with different kinds of living and non-living categories had already been documented by several authors. In a normative study conducted by McKenna and Parry (1994) and in later investigations conducted in normal subjects by Capitani et al. (1999), Laws (1999, 2000, 2004), Albanese et al. (2000), Barbarotto et al. (2002) and Funnell et al. (2006), men were usually more familiar with artifacts and women with living things. Furthermore, a detailed analysis of data gathered in normal subjects suggested a further gender by category interaction even within biological categories, because men were more proficient with animals and women with fruits and vegetables (McKenna and Parry, 1994; Albanese et al., 2000; Laws, 2004; Barbarotto et al., 2008; Cameron et al., 2008). What was surprising, however, was the size of the gender effect. In fact, in Gainotti’s (2005) review 18 out of the 19 patients who showed a selective impairment for fruits and vegetables were men, whereas 7 out of the 9 patients who showed a prevalent impairment for animals were women. Gainotti (2005) and Marra et al. (2007) explained these gender effects on the basis of the greater familiarity that men might have with tools and with certain kinds of animals (probably because they are more involved in hunting activities) and women for fruits and vegetables (probably because of their cooking activities).
An attempt to reconcile these gender effects with inborn models of categorical brain organization was proposed by Laws (2000, 2004) and developed by Laiacona et al. (2006). According to Laws (2000, 2004), greater development of brain circuits dealing with tools and animals in men and with fruits and vegetables in women may have been produced by the main subsistence activities of men (hunting) and women (gathering). Refining this line of thought, Laiacona et al. (2006), proposed that the evolutionary pressures which prompted the development of different brain networks dedicated to animals, plant life and tools might also have provided each gender with more efficient cognitive representations of their main working and foraging targets (i.e., tools and animals for men and fruits and vegetables for women). This inborn account of gender effects, based on evolutionary pressures is, however, at variance with the fact that gender effects do not respect the boundaries between artifacts, animals and plant life categories. Several authors (e.g., Albanese et al., 2000; Moreno-Martinez et al., 2008; Gainotti et al., 2013b) have shown that in the artifact categories, men fare better with tools and women with furniture and kitchen utensils. An objection that could be raised to the “greater familiarity hypothesis” is that, given that in developed countries men no longer hunt and women share their cooking activities with men, gender-related categorical effects should have disappeared by now. This, however, is exactly what was found by Moreno-Martinez et al. (2008) and by Gainotti et al. (2010, 2013b). No difference was observed by Moreno-Martinez et al. (2008) or by Gainotti et al. (2010) in any of the categories considered in their studies when young males and females (who belonged to a generation in which the traditional social roles have almost completely disappeared) were taken into account. The situation changed, however, when elderly subjects were investigated. In Moreno-Martinez et al.’s (2008) study, elderly females obtained better results with flowers, vegetables and kitchen utensils, whereas elderly males obtained better scores with musical instruments. In Gainotti et al.’s (2013b) study elderly men showed a greater familiarity for animals and women for flowers. Furthermore the suggestion advanced by Marra et al. (2007) that the higher male familiarity with animals might derive from their hunting activities was confirmed by Scotti et al. (2010). Then, they subdivided them into various categories and showed that males were more familiar with hunted animals.
In conclusion, data showing that gender effects do not respect the boundaries between artifacts, animals and plant life categories are clearly more consistent with an experience-dependent interpretation of gender-related asymmetries (Gainotti, 2005, 2010; Marra et al., 2007) than with the assumption that evolutionary pressures may have provided each gender with the most efficient cognitive representations of their main working and foraging targets (Laws, 2000, 2004; Laiacona et al., 2006).
Inborn and Experience-Dependent Interpretations of the Relationships Between Tool Knowledge and the Left Ventral Fronto-Parietal Areas
In Section “Neuropsychological Studies of Category-Specific Disorders Tend to Support Sensorimotor Models of Semantic Knowledge” of this review, regarding the functional knowledge of objects, I pointed out that Buxbaum et al. (2000) and Buxbaum and Saffran (2002) distinguished between knowledge of the function of objects and that of their manipulation, suggesting that “manipulation” (being related to a sensorimotor activity), might be the component more tightly linked to the “differential weighting” hypothesis. Kellenbach et al. (2003) and Boronat et al. (2005) confirmed this hypothesis in two functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) experiments. They asked normal subjects to make judgments about actions and functions associated with manipulable and non-manipulable objects. Both studies showed that the left inferior frontal and parietal areas responded more strongly to actions (vs. functions) and to manipulable (vs. non-manipulable) objects. These results confirmed that brain regions specialized for sensory-motor functions play a critical role in the representation of tools and other manmade objects.
The “Embodied Cognition Hypothesis” and the Relationship Between Manipulation, Tool Knowledge and Left Ventral Fronto-Parietal Areas
Some theoretical models have been advanced to explain the relationship between manipulation, tool knowledge and left ventral fronto-parietal areas. One of these models is based on a strong version of the “embodied cognition hypothesis” (Barsalou, 1999, 2008; Gallese and Lakoff, 2005) and maintains that the conceptual processing of tools necessarily involves the retrieval or simulation of the movements associated with tool usage. According to this view, motor programs are run during object recognition and are necessary to ground the conceptual knowledge of objects. One prediction that can be made on the basis of this hypothesis is that loss or impairment of motor programs concerning the use of tools should be associated with disruption of the corresponding conceptual knowledge. But data obtained in brain-damaged patients have provided results that were inconsistent with this strong version of the “embodied cognition theory”. Thus, research conducted in patients with apraxia, whose performance is impaired when they imitate observed actions, by using objects or pantomiming their use from visual presentation, has shown that the ability to use objects may be much more impaired than naming them or knowing their function (Buxbaum et al., 2000; Buxbaum and Saffran, 2002; Rosci et al., 2003; Negri et al., 2007). Furthermore, results of two recent studies are at variance with the strong version of the “embodied cognition theory”. In one of these studies, Arévalo et al. (2012) presented left hemisphere stroke patients with pictures and words representing objects and actions typically associated with use of the hand, mouth and foot. They correlated results obtained on these tasks with data obtained from voxel-based lesion-symptom mapping analyses, but found no support for a correlation between body parts involved in the use of objects and somatotopically organized locus of damage. In another single case study, Garcea et al. (2013) reported the detailed investigation of a patient with a large left hemisphere lesion whose object knowledge was relatively spared in spite of a severe motor (action production) defect and impaired conceptual knowledge of actions. Taken together, the few studies that have used lesion data to test predictions deriving from a strong version of the “embodied cognition theory” provided data inconsistent with this theory.
The Innately Determined Connectivity Patterns Suggested by “the Distributed Domain-Specific Hypothesis”
Other theoretical models acknowledge that motor programs associated with tool use have an important role in the construction of tool representation, but deny that a necessary and sufficient relationship exists between the re-enactment of these sensory-motor processes and tool knowledge.
These models are the “domains of knowledge” hypothesis, (Caramazza, 1998; Caramazza and Shelton, 1998; Mahon and Caramazza, 2001, 2003; Caramazza and Mahon, 2006) and the “sensory-motor model of semantic knowledge”, (Gainotti et al., 1995; Chao et al., 1999; Gainotti, 2000, 2006; Martin and Chao, 2001; Martin, 2007), which have already been discussed in previous sections of the present review. The basic difference between these two models is that the domains of knowledge hypothesis is an innatist model and the sensory-motor model of conceptual knowledge maintains that categorical brain organization is experience-dependent. In fact, the domains of knowledge hypothesis’, which in its first formulation did not consider as relevant the anatomical correlates of brain categorical organization, after the publication of data obtained by Gainotti (2000, 2005) in patients with category-specific semantic disorders and by Kellenbach et al. (2003), Tyler et al. (2004), Bright et al. (2005) and Moss et al. (2005) in functional neuroimaging experiments, acknowledged that the neural substrate of each domain of knowledge consists of a network where the information most relevant for that category converges. However, this model, called “the distributed domain-specific hypothesis” by Mahon and Caramazza (2009, 2011), argues that innately determined connectivity patterns mediate the integration of information critical for the organization of each domain of knowledge; by contrast, the sensory-motor model of conceptual knowledge holds that each category results from the convergence of different sources of knowledge whose organization is experience-dependent. According to the distributed domain-specific hypothesis (Mahon and Caramazza, 2009, 2011), a domain-specific neural system is a network of brain structures in which each region processes a different type of sensory, motor, affective or conceptual information about the same category of objects. Furthermore, the computations that must be performed on items in the same category are sufficiently specific to merit a specialized process. For instance, there is a strong need to integrate motor-relevant information with visual information for tools and other artifacts; this need is less strong for animals and faces. Similarly, there is a strong need to integrate affective information, biological motion processing and visual form information for animals and conspecifics; this need is less strong for tools and other artifacts. Thus, supporters of the distributed domain-specific hypothesis propose that specialization for faces in the lateral fusiform area of the ventral visual stream occurs because this region of the brain is connected with the amygdale and the superior temporal sulcus, which are important for the extraction of socially relevant information. By contrast, specialization for tools and manipulable objects is driven by the connectivity between the inferior frontal and parietal cortex, which subserve object manipulation and regions of the medial fusiform gyrus, that are involved in the visual processing of tools.
Data Suggesting the Innate Nature of the Categorical Brain Organization and Objections Raised to the Hypothesis That Innate Connectivity Patterns may Underlie Categorical Organization
Strong empirical data supporting the innate nature of these patterns of connectivity come from work indicating that congenitally blind subjects show activation for words (presented in Braille) in the same regions of the ventral stream that are activated by visually presented words in sighted individuals (Buchel et al., 1998). Furthermore, Mahon et al. (2009) showed that the same medial-to-lateral bias in category preferences for artifacts vs. animals, which is present in the ventral surface of the temporo-occipital cortex in sighted individuals (Chao et al., 1999; Noppeney et al., 2006; Mahon et al., 2007), is also present in congenitally blind subjects. Mahon et al. (2009) suggested that, if visual experience is unnecessary for the emergence of category-specificity in the ventral stream, innate connectivity between regions of the ventral stream and other regions of the brain could drive category-specificity. Some objections have, however, been raised to this claim. First, several authors (e.g., Downing et al., 2006; Mechelli et al., 2006; Chouinard et al., 2008; Pourtois et al., 2009; Cate et al., 2011; Taylor and Downing, 2011) have challenged the specificity of the medial-to-lateral bias in category preferences. Second, according to Kiefer and Pulvermüller (2012) these data do not necessarily suggest that innate connections underlyie the organization of object knowledge, because the brain of congenitally blind patients is subject to many plastic changes in which visual areas are activated by tactile (Sadato et al., 1996; Röder et al., 1997) and auditory (Klinge et al., 2010; Collignon et al., 2011) information. It is, therefore, possible that tactile and auditory processing of biological and artifact stimuli recruits “visual” areas in the course of cortical reorganization and leads to the extraction of category-specific object properties, similarly to what occurs in visual exploration. Authors who argue that innately determined connectivity patterns mediate the integration of information critical for the organization of each domain of knowledge do not deny that the brains of blind subjects are different from the brains of sighted participants in important ways nor that “visual” regions in the blind process tactile information (e.g., Mahon et al., 2009; Amedi et al., 2010). In fact, they hold that the relevant finding for constraining models is not the format of the information that is represented but rather its organization. On the other hand, it can be objected that, to devise a task that could be performed by both sighted and blind individuals, Mahon et al. (2009) asked participants to make size judgments about stimuli that were presented as auditory words. These size-judgment tasks can be performed on the basis of both visual and somato-sensory kinesthetic information. Now, if we look at the original data of Mahon et al. (2009), we see that only activation concerning the artifacts, which emerged in the mesial parts of the ventral surface of the occipital-temporal cortex, was strong and spatially extensive; by contrast, activation concerning living beings (in the lateral parts of the same cortical areas) was weak and limited to small spots. This may have been because congenitally blind participants have disproportionately more somato-sensory experience, which is much more relevant for processing the shapes of nonliving (e.g., a fork, a car) than living things.
Other objections to the innatist model of the distributed domain-specific hypothesis come from results, reported by Baker et al. (2007) in humans and by Srihasam et al. (2012) in monkeys. Baker et al. (2007) showed that category-specific regions in the ventral visual pathway, such as the “visual word form area” (VWFA), can be created through visual experience, without a strong genetic predisposition for that specific selectivity. These authors used high resolution fMRI to scan both Hebrew and non-Hebrew readers while they viewed English words, Hebrew words, Chinese characters and line drawings and found a small region in the left hemisphere fusiform gyrus, that selectively responded to letter strings. This region responded more strongly to Hebrew words in Hebrew readers than in non- Hebrew readers, indicating that the striking selectivity of this region for one class of stimuli originates from extensive experience with that stimulus class. Srihasam et al. (2012) conducted experimental studies in monkeys to evaluate whether the existence of dedicated cortical domains necessarily means that the corresponding abilities are innate, or whether these domains can be formed or refined by interactions between genetic programs and common early experience. They showed that intensive early, but not late, experience caused the formation of category-selective regions in the macaque temporal lobe for stimuli (i.e., letters and numbers) never encountered naturally by monkeys. Their explanation of these results was that thanks to a self-organizing activity-dependent Hebbian mechanism, intensive early experience drives the segregation of category-specific domains in the cortical areas of the IT cortex. It must be acknowledged, on the other hand, that the positions of Mahon and Caramazza (2009, 2011) were supported by a set of recent fMRI data from blind individuals obtained by Striem-Amit et al. (2012). These authors, taught congenitally blind adults to read and recognize complex images using sounds that topographically represented images (“soundscapes”). The blind subjects selectively activated the VWFA during the processing of letter soundscapes relative to textures or visually complex object categories. Therefore, similar to the blind subjects tested by Mahon and Caramazza, the VWFA of their blind participants showed category selectivity regardless of the input sensory modality, visual experience, and long-term familiarity or expertise with the script. Striem-Amit et al. (2012) thus concluded that, although the VWFA is located in classical “visual” regions of the brain, the sensory format of the stimulus might already be “abstracted away” when the information arrives in the fusiform gyrus, allowing the same information to be processed by that particular structure, even when it is channeled through other modalities.
In any case, the recruitment of occipital regions in the congenitally blind, the ability of the brain to reorganize itself due to experience and the observation of specialized cognitive modules in the occipital cortex of congenitally blind, similar to those observed in the sighted, are still the subject of intense debates (see Held et al., 2011; Ricciardi and Pietrini, 2011; Struiksma et al., 2011; Bedny et al., 2012; Collignon et al., 2013; Peelen et al., 2014 for different viewpoints on these subjects).
In conclusion, data indicating that the medial-to-lateral bias in category preferences for artifacts vs. animals, which is present in the visual “ventral stream” of sighted individuals, is also present in congenitally blind subjects certainly suggest that, if visual experience is not necessary for the emergence of this categorical neural organization, innate patterns of connectivity must mediate the integration of information critical for the organization of each category. These suggestions must, however, be taken with caution, because an interaction has been hypothesized in critical periods of development between an inborn general brain organization (allowing the connection between the main sensory-motor, cognitive, executive and affective brain structures) and an experience-dependent actualization or reshaping of this basic brain design. Furthermore, data obtained in humans and in monkeys suggest that, thanks to a self-organizing activity-dependent Hebbian mechanism, intensive early experience drives the segregation of category-specific domains within cortical areas in the IT cortex.
The Importance of Prior Experience in the Cortical Representation of Objects
Several recent investigations tried to assess the importance of prior perceptual and motor experience in the cortical representation of previously familiar or unknown objects, whose knowledge had been learned through intensive training. These lines of research will be analyzed in some detail. First, the results of investigations that studied the influence of experience with previously familiar objects or tasks will be reported and then the results of experimental studies that evaluated the influence of training on previously unfamiliar material.
The Influence of Experience with Previously Familiar Objects
The first line of research was pursued by Hoenig et al. (2011) in the auditory domain and by Yee et al. (2013) in the motor domain. Hoenig et al. (2011) started from the premise that professional musicians constitute a very good model for understanding experience-dependent plasticity in the human brain and investigated whether this neuroplasticity might extend beyond basic perceptual and motor functions and shape the semantic representation of musical instruments. Using fMRI, they showed that in musicians (but not in musical laypersons) conceptual processing of visually presented musical instruments activates the auditory association cortex encompassing the right posterior superior temporal gyrus, which is also recruited in the auditory perception of real sounds. Therefore, experience-driven neuroplasticity in musicians is not confined to alterations of perceptual and motor maps but also leads to the establishment of higher-level semantic representations for musical instruments. Yee et al. (2013) assessed the extent to which previous motor experience is part of an object’s representation. They showed: (a) that when the hands are engaged in a task involving movements that are incompatible with those used to interact with frequently manipulated objects, it is more difficult to make verbal judgements about those objects; and (b) that the amount of manual experience with the objects determines the amount of interference.
The Influence of Training on Previously Unfamiliar Material
The second research strategy, which started from the fact that the history of previous sensory-motor experience with familiar objects cannot be controlled, was based on the use of previously unfamiliar material and the administration of different types of extensive training with these objects. This line of research was followed by James and Gauthier (2003), Creem-Regehr et al. (2007), Kiefer et al. (2007), Weisberg et al. (2007) and Bellebaum et al. (2013).
James and Gauthier (2003) asked participants to learn associations between novel objects (“greebles”) and verbal labels of object features referring to a given modality (auditory and object motion). In a sequential matching task at test, the authors found stronger activity to objects associated with auditory words (“buzzes”) in the superior temporal gyrus, which responds to sounds in general, and stronger activity for objects associated with motion words (“hops”) in the superior posterior temporal sulcus, which is sensitive to motion processing. Similarly, Kiefer et al. (2007) assessed the plasticity of conceptual representations by training subjects with novel objects under different training conditions. In one class of stimuli object categorization was based on a detail feature, affording a particular action. During training, participants were asked either to make an action pantomime toward the detail feature or simply to pay attention to it by pointing to it with their index finger. In a categorization task at test, the neural correlates of the acquired conceptual representations were assessed. In the pantomime group, in which a meaningful action was performed towards the object during training, early activation was found in the frontal areas; but in the pointing training group, in which the action during training was not related to the object, these effects were absent. These results show that action information contributes to conceptual processing according to the specific learning experience, and suggest that conceptual representations are established by the learning-based formation of cell assemblies in different cortical areas. On the other hand, Creem-Regehr et al. (2007) used fMRI to investigate the influence of action knowledge associated with viewing, grasping, and using novel graspable objects. Participants were trained to perform complex actions associated with novel objects (“tools”) and had experience manipulating other visually similar novel objects (“shapes”). During scanning participants viewed, imagined grasping, and imagined using the objects. The greatest differences between “tools” and “shapes” were found in the “using” condition, in which greater effect sizes were observed for tools vs. shapes in the left inferior parietal lobule (IPL), pre-supplementary motor cortex (pre-SMA) and, marginally, in the left ventral premotor cortex (VPM). These results suggest that representations of tools are constructed on the basis of complex action schemata, which recruit processes related to graspability, action plans and use of objects. Similar conclusions were reached by Weisberg et al. (2007), who assessed the learning of tool-like functions for novel objects in an fMRI experiment in which subjects had to visually match pictures of novel objects before and after extensive training in the use of these objects to perform specific tool-like tasks. Compared with a pre-training baseline, activity increased after training in brain regions associated with motion (left middle temporal gyrus) and with manipulation (left intraparietal sulcus and premotor area) of tools and other manipulable objects. Furthermore, activations in the ventral temporo-occipital cortex became more focal after training. Specifically, although activity was widespread in the fusiform gyrus prior to training, activity, after training it was markedly increased in the medial portion of the fusiform gyrus, which is associated with identifying common tools, and was markedly reduced in the more lateral parts of the fusiform gyrus (i.e., in regions preferring animate objects like animals and faces).
Finally, Bellebaum et al. (2013) used fMRI to study the impact of different types of object-related sensorimotor experiences on the neural representations of novel objects, by contrasting manipulation training (MTO) with visual training (VTO) and absence of training (NTO). The post-training activity in the left inferior/middle frontal gyrus and the left posterior IPL was higher for MTO than for VTO and NTO, suggesting that manipulation experience leads to greater activity specifically in regions of the fronto-parietal cortex.
In conclusion, these studies assessing the importance of perceptual and motor experience in the cortical representation of previously familiar or of previously unknown objects, confirm the importance of previous experience in the learning-based formation of cortical cell assemblies subsuming the cortical representation of concepts. The implication of these results is that, if it is shown that experience shapes brain organization then there is evidence against inborn models. The problem with this argument is that inborn models do not deny that experience shapes brain organization i.e., that all of the content that an individual represents comes from experience. The question is whether the basic organization by category is something that depends only on experience or also on endogenous constraints.
General Discussion and Tentative Concluding Remarks
If we try to summarize the data gathered in the present review, which are synthesized in Table 1 (by integrating the results of the different lines of research with some of the more important papers illustrating these lines) we can say that there are two main reasons why it is difficult to choose between the experience-dependent and the inborn models of conceptual representations.
Table 1. Overview of some of the most relevant papers that have supported either the innate or the experience-dependent models in the various lines of research surveyed in the present review.
The first reason is that both models acknowledge that experience shapes brain organization and that all of the content an individual represents comes from experience. The question is, therefore, whether the basic organization by category is something that depends only on experience or also on endogenous constraints. The second reason is that some of the empirical data gathered in this survey stress the importance of experience-related factors, other data suggest the existence of endogenous constraints and still other data do not clearly support either of these mechanisms. In the data stressing the importance of experience-related factors, I would mention: (a) the sizeable gender effects observed by Gainotti (2005) in reviewing case reports of category-specific semantic impairment; and (b) results of experimental studies which have shown that perceptual and motor experience play a critical role in the cortical representation of previously familiar or unknown objects.
Gender-related categorical effects were explained by Gainotti (2005) as due to men’s greater familiarity with tools and with certain kinds of animals (because they are more involved in manual and hunting activities) and women’s greater familiarity with fruits and vegetables (probably as a result of their cooking activities). An inborn account of these gender effects, proposed by Laws (2000, 2004) and by Laiacona et al. (2006) is at variance with the fact that these effects do not respect the boundaries between artifacts, animals and plant life categories. The observation that within the artifact categories men fare better with tools and women with “furniture” and “kitchen utensils” (Albanese et al., 2000; Moreno-Martinez et al., 2008; Gainotti et al., 2013b) is consistent with an “experience-dependent” interpretation of gender-related asymmetries, but not with the assumption that evolutionary pressures may have provided each gender with the most efficient cognitive representations for their main work and foraging targets.
As for the importance of perceptual and motor experience in the cortical representation of previously familiar or unknown objects, investigations which have studied the influence of experience with previously familiar objects (Hoenig et al., 2011; Yee et al., 2013) and results of experimental studies which have evaluated the influence of training on previously unfamiliar material (James and Gauthier, 2003; Creem-Regehr et al., 2007; Kiefer et al., 2007; Weisberg et al., 2007; Bellebaum et al., 2013) have consistently confirmed the importance of previous experience in the learning-based formation of the cortical cell assemblies that subsume the cortical representation of concepts.
In the data suggesting the existence of endogenous constraints, the most important come from work (Mahon et al., 2009) indicating that the medial-to-lateral bias in category preferences for artifacts vs. animals, which is present in the ventral surface of the temporo-occipital cortex in sighted individuals, is also present in congenitally blind subjects. According to Mahon and Caramazza (2011), this observation suggests that, if visual experience is not necessary for the emergence of a categorical neural organization, then innate patterns of connectivity must mediate the integration of information critical for the organization of each category.
More inconclusive, though mainly supporting the experience-dependent hypothesis, is the fact that the anatomical structures disrupted in a given type of category-specific semantic disorder correspond to the areas of convergences of the sensory-motor information which has a major role in the construction of that category. This observation which (as we have seen in a previous section of this survey) was predicted by the “sensory-motor model of semantic knowledge”, is not necessarily at variance with an innatistic model, if we assume that the convergence of critical sensory-motor information in well defined cortical areas may have taken place in the course of evolution.
Therefore, even if the rationalist approach did not explicitely acknowledge that the empiricist approach was correct, it made similar predictions, leading to the conclusion that at the present state of knowledge it is impossible to choose between experience-dependent and inborn models of conceptual representations.
This interlocutory conclusion may be necessary because the question about experience-dependent vs. inborn semantic categories cannot be an either/or issue and both inborn features and experience shape semantic categories. Nevertheless, the weight of these complementary determinants of conceptual representations has yet to be explored. For instance, a recent study of genetic and environmental influences on the VWFA and the fusiform face area (FFA) has shown that activation of the VWFA is partially under genetic control, whereas activation of the FFA is primarily influenced by individual experience (Pinel et al., 2014). These results are obviously at variance with those obtained by Striem-Amit et al. (2012), which are reported in Section “Data Suggesting the Innate Nature of the Categorical Brain Organization and Objections Raised to the Hypothesis that Innate Connectivity Patterns May Underlie Categorical Organization”, in a discussion of the data that support the innate nature of categorical brain organization.
In my opinion, it is likely that only some basic mechanisms, linked to the general architecture of the brain and to the connections between structures processing perceptual and action-related information are inborn and that more specific contents of knowledge is experience-dependent. On the other hand, since conceptual categories are constructed on the basis of cortical areas that process perceptual and action-related information and their interconnections, it is not easy to disentangle the innate processing systems from the experience-dependent contents of their joint action. It is only possible to highlight the results of studies that have consistently confirmed the importance of previous experience in the learning-based formation of cortical cell assemblies, which subsume the cortical representation of previously familiar or newly learned concepts.
In any case, even if both inborn features and experience shape semantic categories, the question of the relative contribution of novel information and of predefined structures (i.e., specific brain networks) remains unresolved. It also remains unclear whether any pre-quantitative model can determine the relative contribution of inborn and experience-dependent sources of influence (Hofmann and Jacobs, 2014).
Future Research Directions
Since I indicated in the foregoing tentative concluding remarks that the question about experience-dependent vs. inborn semantic categories cannot be an either/or issue and that both inborn features and experience shape semantic categories, I feel it is necessary to indicate some research directions in the fields of Artificial Intelligence and genomic imaging, which might provide ways to address these issues in the future. As to the first direction, a pioneering study by Mitchell et al. (2008) has shown that brain activation in response to a line drawing of a concrete concept and the corresponding name can be predicted if semantic feature values for that concept and the patterns of brain activation for other concepts are given. Since then, multivariate pattern analysis (MVPA) has become an inductive method for determining brain sites that selectively respond to particular semantic features and these analyses are becoming more and more category-specific. Pereira et al. (2013), for instance, used a corpus of a few thousand Wikipedia articles about concrete high-imageability concepts to produce a low-dimensional semantic feature representation of those concepts. They showed that these features can be used to uncover similarity relations in brain activation for different concepts, which parallel relations in behavioral data from human subjects. If strong similarities could be uncovered between sighted and congenitally blind individuals in the patterns of brain activation for different abstract and concrete, high-imageability and low-imageability words, this could strengthen the inborn models of conceptual representation. As for the second direction, it can be argued that if genes determine functional imaging (e.g., Muñoz et al., 2009), this might help to illuminate the degree to which semantic category development is genetically pre-determined. For example, to further explore the finding that higher-order semantic impairments are implicated in formal thought disorders (FTD) in schizophrenia (e.g., Dwyer et al., 2014), Nicodemus et al. (2014) combined a computational linguistic approach with a candidate gene approach to examine the genetic architecture of a category fluency task in patients with schizophrenia. It is, therefore, possible that the weight of inborn and experience-dependent factors in the construction of conceptual categories will be clarified by these and other, similar research directions.
Conflict of Interest Statement
The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
References
Albanese, E., Capitani, E., Barbarotto, R., and Laiacona, M. (2000). Semantic category dissociations, familiarity and gender. Cortex 36, 733–746. doi: 10.1016/s0010-9452(08)70549-5
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Allport, D. A. (1985). “Distributed memory, modular systems and dysphasia,” in Current Perspectives in Dysphasia, eds S. K. Newman and R. Epstein (Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone), 32–60.
Amedi, A., Raz, N., Azulay, H., Malach, R., and Zohary, E. (2010). Cortical activity during tactile exploration of objects in blind and sighted humans. Restor. Neurol. Neurosci. 28, 143–156. doi: 10.3233/RNN-2010-0503
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Arévalo, A. L., Baldo, J. V., and Dronkers, N. F. (2012). What do brain lesions tell us about theories of embodied semantics and the human mirror neuron system? Cortex 48, 242–254. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2010.06.001
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Baker, C. I., Liu, J., Wald, L. L., Kwong, K. K., Benner, T., and Kanwisher, N. (2007). Visual word processing and experiential origins of functional selectivity in human extrastriate cortex. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U S A 104, 9087–9092. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0703300104
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Barbarotto, R., Capitani, E., and Laiacona, M. (2001). Living musical instruments and inanimate body parts? Neuropsychologia 39, 406–414. doi: 10.1016/s0028-3932(00)00128-7
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Barbarotto, R., Laiacona, M., and Capitani, E. (2008). Does sex influence the age of acquisition of common names? A contrast of different semantic categories. Cortex 44, 1161–1170. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2007.08.016
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Barbarotto, R., Laiacona, M., Macchi, V., and Capitani, E. (2002). Picture reality decision, semantic categories and gender. A new set of pictures, with norms and an experimental study. Neuropsychologia 40, 1637–1653. doi: 10.1016/s0028-3932(02)00029-5
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behav. Brain Sci. 22, 577–660. doi: 10.1017/s0140525x99002149
Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 59, 617–645. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093639
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Basso, A., Capitani, E., and Laiacona, M. (1988). Progressive language impairment without dementia: a case with isolated category specific semantic defect. J. Neurol. Neurosurg. Psychiatry 51, 1201–1207. doi: 10.1136/jnnp.51.9.1201
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Bedny, M., Caramazza, A., Pascual-Leone, A., and Saxe, R. (2012). Typical neural representations of action verbs develop without vision. Cereb. Cortex 22, 286–293. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhr081
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Bellebaum, C., Tettamanti, M., Marchetta, E., Della Rosa, P., Rizzo, G., Daum, I., et al. (2013). Neural representations of unfamiliar objects are modulated by sensorimotor experience. Cortex 49, 1110–1125. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2012.03.023
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Blundo, C., Ricci, M., and Miller, L. (2006). Category-specific knowledge deficit for animals in a patient with herpes simplex encephalitis. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 23, 1248–1268. doi: 10.1080/02643290600896449
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Boronat, C. B., Buxbaum, L. J., Coslett, H. B., Tang, K., Saffran, E. M., Kimberg, D. Y., et al. (2005). Distinctions between manipulation and function knowledge of objects: evidence from functional magnetic resonance imaging. Brain Res. Cogn. Brain Res. 23, 361–373. doi: 10.1016/j.cogbrainres.2004.11.001
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Breedin, S. D., Saffran, E. M., and Coslett, B. H. (1994). Reversal of the concreteness effect in a patient with semantic dementia. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 11, 617–660. doi: 10.1080/02643299408251987
Bright, P., Moss, H. E., Longe, O., Stamatakis, E. A., and Tyler, L. K. (2007). Conceptual structure modulates anteromedial temporal involvement in processing verbally presented object properties. Cereb. Cortex 17, 1066–1073. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhl016
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Bright, P., Moss, H. E., Stamatakis, E. A., and Tyler, L. K. (2005). The anatomy of object processing: the role of anteromedial temporal cortex. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. B 58, 361–377. doi: 10.1080/02724990544000013
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Buchel, C., Price, C., Frackowiak, R. S., and Friston, K. (1998). Different activation patterns in the visual cortex of late and congenitally blind subjects. Brain 121, 409–419. doi: 10.1093/brain/121.3.409
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Buxbaum, L. J., and Kalénine, S. (2010). Action knowledge, visuomotor activation and embodiment in the two action systems. Ann. N Y Acad. Sci. 1191, 201–218. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2010.05447.x
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Buxbaum, L. J., and Saffran, E. M. (2002). Knowledge of object manipulation and object function: dissociations in apraxic and nonapraxic subjects. Brain Lang. 82, 179–199. doi: 10.1016/s0093-934x(02)00014-7
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Buxbaum, L. J., Veramonti, T., and Schwartz, M. F. (2000). Function and manipulation tool knowledge in apraxia: knowing “what for” but not “how”. Neurocase 6, 83–97. doi: 10.1093/neucas/6.2.83
Cameron, R. M., Wambaugh, J. L., and Mauszycki, S. (2008). Effects of age, gender and education on semantic fluency for living and artefact categories. Aphasiology 22, 790–801. doi: 10.1080/02687030701818018
Campanella, F., D’Agostini, S., Skrap, M., and Shallice, T. (2010). Naming manipulable objects: anatomy of a category specific effect in left temporal tumours. Neuropsychologia 48, 1583–1597. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2010.02.002
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Capitani, E., Laiacona, M., and Barbarotto, R. (1999). Gender affects word retrieval of certain categories in semantic fluency tasks. Cortex 35, 273–278. doi: 10.1016/s0010-9452(08)70800-1
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Capitani, E., Laiacona, M., Mahon, B., and Caramazza, A. (2003). What are the facts of semantic category-specific deficits? A critical review of the clinical evidence. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 20, 213–261. doi: 10.1080/02643290244000266
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Capitani, E., Laiacona, M., Pagani, R., Capasso, R., Zampetti, P., and Miceli, G. (2009). Posterior cerebral artery infarcts and semantic category dissociations: a study of 28 patients. Brain 132, 965–981. doi: 10.1093/brain/awp013
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Caramazza, A. (1998). The interpretation of semantic category-specific deficits: what do they reveal about the organization of conceptual knowledge in the brain? Neurocase 4, 265–272. doi: 10.1093/neucas/4.4.265
Caramazza, A., Hillis, A., Rapp, B. C., and Romani, C. (1990). The multiple semantic hypothesis: multiple confusions? Cogn. Neuropsychol. 7, 161–189. doi: 10.1080/02643299008253441
Caramazza, A., and Mahon, B. Z. (2006). The organization of conceptual knowledge in the brain: the future’s past and some future directions. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 23, 13–38. doi: 10.1080/02643290542000021
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Caramazza, A., and Shelton, J. R. (1998). Domain-specific knowledge systems in the brain: the animate-inanimate distinction. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 10, 1–34. doi: 10.1093/neucas/4.4.399-k
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Cate, A. D., Goodale, M. A., and Köhler, S. (2011). The role of apparent size in building- and object-specific regions of ventral visual cortex. Brain Res. 1388, 109–122. doi: 10.1016/j.brainres.2011.02.022
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Chao, L. L., Haxby, J. V., and Martin, A. (1999). Attribute-based neural substrates in temporal cortex for perceiving and knowing about objects. Nat. Neurosci. 2, 913–919. doi: 10.1038/13217
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Chouinard, P. A., Morrissey, B. F., Köhler, S., and Goodale, M. A. (2008). Repetition suppression in occipital-temporal visual areas is modulated by physical rather than semantic features of objects. Neuroimage 41, 130–144. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2008.02.011
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Collignon, O., Dormal, G., Albouy, G., Vandewalle, G., Voss, P., Phillips, C., et al. (2013). Impact of blindness onset on the functional organization and the connectivity of the occipital cortex. Brain 136, 2769–2783. doi: 10.1093/brain/awt176
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Collignon, O., Vandewalle, G., Voss, P., Albouy, G., Charbonneau, G., Lassonde, M., et al. (2011). Functional specialization for auditory-spatial processing in the occipital cortex of congenitally blind humans. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U S A 108, 4435–4440. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1013928108
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Cree, G. S., and McRae, K. (2003). Analyzing the factors underlying the structure and computation of the meaning of chipmunk, cherry, chisel, cheese and cello (and many other such concrete nouns). J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 32, 163–201. doi: 10.1037/0096-3445.132.2.163
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Creem-Regehr, S. H., Dilda, V., Vicchrilli, A. E., Federer, F., and Lee, J. N. (2007). The influence of complex action knowledge on representations of novel graspable objects: evidence from functional magnetic resonance imaging. J. Int. Neuropsychol. Soc. 13, 1009–1020. doi: 10.1017/s1355617707071093
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. (1989). Time-locked multiregional retroactivation: a systems level proposal for the neural substrates of recall and recognition.Cognition 33, 25–62. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(89)90005-x
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. (1990). Category-related recognition defects as a clue to the neural substrates of knowledge. Trends Neurosci. 13, 95–98. doi: 10.1016/0166-2236(90)90184-c
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., and Brandt, J. P. (1990). Neural regionalization of knowledge access: preliminary evidence. Cold Spring Harb. Symp. Quant. Biol. 55, 1039–1047. doi: 10.1101/sqb.1990.055.01.098
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Damasio, H., Grabowski, T. J., Tranel, D., Hichwa, R. D., and Damasio, A. R. (1996). A neural basis for lexical retrieval. Nature 380, 499–505. doi: 10.1038/381810b0
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
De Renzi, E., and Lucchelli, F. (1994). Are semantic systems separately represented in the brain? The case of living category impairment. Cortex 30, 3–25. doi: 10.1016/s0010-9452(13)80322-x
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Devlin, J. T., Moore, C. J., Mummery, C. J., Gorno-Tempini, M. L., Phillips, J. A., Noppeney, U., et al. (2002). Anatomic constraints on cognitive theories of category specificity. Neuroimage 15, 675–685. doi: 10.1006/nimg.2001.1002
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Dixon, M. J., Piskopos, M., and Schweizer, T. A. (2000). Musical instrument naming impairments: the crucial exception to the living/nonliving dichotomy in category-specific agnosia. Brain Cogn. 43, 158–164.
Downing, P. E., Chan, A. W., Peelen, M. V., Dodds, C. M., and Kanwisher, N. (2006). Domain specificity in visual cortex. Cereb. Cortex 16, 1453–1461. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhj086
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Dwyer, K., David, A., McCarthy, R., McKenna, P., and Peters, E. (2014). Higher-order semantic processing in formal thought disorder in schizophrenia. Psychiatry Res. 216, 168–176. doi: 10.1016/j.psychres.2014.02.011
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Farah, M. J., and McClelland, J. L. (1991). A computational model of semantic memory impairment: modality specificity and emergent category-specificity. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 120, 339–357. doi: 10.1037/0096-3445.120.4.339
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Farah, M. J., Meyer, M. M., and McMullen, P. A. (1996). The living: non-living dissociation is not an artifact: giving an a priori implausible hypothesis a strong test. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 13, 137–154. doi: 10.1080/026432996382097
Farah, M. J., and Wallace, M. A. (1992). Semantically-bounded anomia: implications for the neural implementation of naming. Neuropsychologia 30, 609–621. doi: 10.1016/0028-3932(92)90066-u
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Forde, E. M. E., Francis, D., Riddoch, M. J., Rumiati, M. I., and Humphreys, G. W. (1997). On the links between visual knowledge and naming: a single case study of a patient with a category-specific impairment for living things. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 14, 403–458. doi: 10.1080/026432997381538
Funnell, E., Hughes, D., and Woodcock, J. (2006). Age of acquisition for naming and knowing: a new hypothesis. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. (Hove) 59, 268–295. doi: 10.1080/02724980443000674
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G. (2000). What the locus of brain lesion tells us about the nature of the cognitive defect underlying category-specific disorders: a review. Cortex 36, 539–559. doi: 10.1016/s0010-9452(08)70537-9
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G. (2005). The influence of gender and lesion location on naming disorders for animals, plants and artefacts. Neuropsychologia 43, 1633–1644. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2005.01.016
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G. (2006). Anatomical, functional and cognitive determinants of semantic memory disorders. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 30, 577–594. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2005.11.001
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G. (2010). The influence of anatomical locus of lesion and of gender-related familiarity factors in category-specific semantic disorders for animals, fruits and vegetables: a review of single-case studies. Cortex 46, 1072–1087. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2010.04.002
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G. (2013). Controversies over the mechanisms underlying the crucial role of the left fronto-parietal areas in the representation of tools. Front. Psychol. 4:727. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00727
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G., Ciaraffa, F., Silveri, M. C., and Marra, C. (2009). Mental representation of normal subjects about the sources of knowledge in different semantic categories and unique entities. Neuropsychology 23, 803–812. doi: 10.1037/a0016352
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G., Ciaraffa, F., Silveri, M. C., and Marra, C. (2010). Different views about the nature of gender-related asymmetries in tasks based on biological or artefact categories. Behav. Neurol. 22, 81–90. doi: 10.1155/2010/410858
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G., and Silveri, M. C. (1996). Cognitive and anatomical locus of lesion in a patient with category specific semantic impairment for living beings. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 13, 357–390. doi: 10.1080/026432996381944
Gainotti, G., Silveri, M. C., Daniele, A., and Giustolisi, L. (1995). Neuroanatomical correlates of category-specific semantic disorders: a critical survey. Memory 3, 247–264. doi: 10.1080/09658219508253153
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G., Spinelli, P., Scaricamazza, E., and Marra, C. (2013a). The evaluation of sources of knowledge underlying different semantic categories. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7:40. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2013.00040
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gainotti, G., Spinelli, P., Scaricamazza, E., and Marra, C. (2013b). Asymmetries in gender-related familiarity with different semantic categories. Data from normal adults. Behav. Neurol. 27, 175–181. doi: 10.3233/BEN-120277
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gales, T. M., Done, D. J., and Frank, R. J. (2001). Visual crowding and category specific deficits for pictorial stimuli: a neural network model. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 18, 509–550. doi: 10.1080/02643290125912
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Gallese, V., and Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: the role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 22, 455–479. doi: 10.1080/02643290442000310
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Garcea, F. E., Dombovy, M., and McMahon, B. Z. (2013). Preserved tool knowledge in the context of impaired action knowledge: implications for models of semantic memory. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7:120. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2013.00120
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Goldenberg, G. (1992). Loss of visual imagery and loss of visual knowledge–a case study. Neuropsychologia 30, 1081–1099. doi: 10.1016/0028-3932(92)90100-z
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Grabowski, T. J., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., Ponto, L. L., Hichwa, R. D., and Damasio, A. R. (2001). A role for left temporal pole in the retrieval of words for unique entities. Hum. Brain Mapp. 13, 199–212. doi: 10.1002/hbm.1033.abs
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Hanley, J. R., Young, A. W., and Pearson, N. A. (1989). Defective recognition of familiar people. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 6, 179–210. doi: 10.1080/02643298908253418
Hart, J., Berndt, R. S., and Caramazza, A. (1985). Category-specific naming deficit following cerebral infarction. Nature 316, 439–440. doi: 10.1038/316439a0
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Hart, J. Jr., and Gordon, B. (1992). Neural subsystems for object knowledge. Nature 359, 60–64. doi: 10.1038/359060a0
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Held, R., Ostrovsky, Y., de Gelder, B., Gandhi, T., Ganesh, S., Mathur, U., et al. (2011). The newly sighted fail to match seen with felt. Nat. Neurosci. 14, 551–553. doi: 10.1038/nn.2795
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Hillis, A. E., and Caramazza, A. (1991). Category-specific naming and comprehension impairment: a double dissociation. Brain 114, 2081–2094. doi: 10.1093/brain/114.5.2081
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Hoenig, K., Müller, C., Herrnberger, B., Sim, E. J., Spitzer, M., Ehret, G., et al. (2011). Neuroplasticity of semantic representations for musical instruments in professional musicians. Neuroimage 56, 1714–1725. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.02.065
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Hoffman, P., and Lambon Ralph, M. A. (2013). Shapes, scents and sounds: quantifying the full multi-sensory basis of conceptual knowledge. Neuropsychologia 51, 14–25. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2012.11.009
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Hofmann, M. J., and Jacobs, A. M. (2014). Interactive activation and competition models and semantic context: from behavioral to brain data. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 46, 85–104. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2014.06.011
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Humphreys, G. W., Riddoch, M. J., and Price, C. J. (1997). Top-down processes in object identification: evidence from experimental psychology, neuropsychology and functional anatomy. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci. 352, 1275–1282. doi: 10.1098/rstb.1997.0110
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Jackendoff, R. (1987). On beyond zebra: the relation of linguistic and visual information. Cognition 26, 89–114. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(87)90026-6
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
James, T. W., and Gauthier, I. (2003). Auditory and action semantic features activate sensory-specific perceptual brain regions. Curr. Biol. 13, 1792–1796. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2003.09.039
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Kellenbach, M. L., Brett, M., and Patterson, K. (2003). Actions speak louder than functions: the importance of manipulability and action in tool representation. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 15, 30–46. doi: 10.1162/089892903321107800
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Kensinger, E. A., Siri, S., Cappa, S. F., and Corkin, S. (2003). Role of the anterior temporal lobe in repetition and semantic priming: evidence from a patient with a category-specific deficit. Neuropsychologia 41, 71–84. doi: 10.1016/s0028-3932(02)00131-8
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Kiefer, M., and Pulvermüller, F. (2012). Conceptual representations in mind and brain: theoretical developments, current evidence and future directions. Cortex 48, 805–825. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2011.04.006
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Kiefer, M., Sim, E. J., Liebich, S., Hauk, O., and Tanaka, J. (2007). Experience-dependent plasticity of conceptual representations in human sensory-motor areas. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 19, 525–542. doi: 10.1162/jocn.2007.19.3.525
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Klinge, C., Eippert, F., Röder, B., and Büchel, C. (2010). Corticocortical connections mediate primary visual cortex responses to auditory stimulation in the blind. J. Neurosci. 30, 12798–12805. doi: 10.1523/jneurosci.2384-10.2010
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Kolinsky, J., Fery, P., Messina, D., Peretz, I., Evinck, S., Ventura, P., et al. (2002). The fur of the crocodile and the mooing sheep: a study of a patient with a category-specific impairment for biological things. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 19, 301–342. doi: 10.1080/02643290143000196
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Laiacona, M., Barbarotto, R., and Capitani, E. (2006). Human evolution and the brain representation of semantic knowledge: is there a role for sex differences? Evol. Hum. Behav. 27, 158–168. doi: 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2005.08.002
Laiacona, M., Barbarotto, R., Trivelli, C., and Capitani, E. (1993). Dissociazioni semantiche intercategoriali: descrizione di una batteria standardizzata e dati normativi. Arch. Psicol. Neurol. Psichiat. 2, 209–248.
Laws, K. R. (1999). Gender affects naming latencies for living and nonliving things: implications for familiarity. Cortex 35, 729–733. doi: 10.1016/s0010-9452(08)70831-1
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Laws, K. R. (2000). Category-specific naming errors in normal subjects: the influence of evolution and experience. Brain Lang. 75, 123–133. doi: 10.1006/brln.2000.2348
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Laws, K. R. (2004). Sex differences in lexical size across semantic categories. Pers. Individ. Dif. 36, 23–32. doi: 10.1016/s0191-8869(03)00048-5
Luckhurst, L., and Lloyd-Jones, T. J. (2001). A selective deficit for living things after temporal lobectomy for relief of epileptic seizures. Brain Lang. 79, 266–296. doi: 10.1006/brln.2001.2485
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Mahon, B. Z., Anzellotti, S., Schwarzbach, J., Zampini, M., and Caramazza, A. (2009). Category-specific organization in the human brain does not require visual experience. Neuron 63, 397–405. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2009.07.012
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2001). The sensory/functional assumption or the data: which do we keep? Behav. Brain Sci. 24, 488–489.
Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2003). Constraining questions about the organization and representation of conceptual knowledge. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 20, 433–450. doi: 10.1080/02643290342000014
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2004). Heterogeneity is a fact of category- specific semantic deficits. So? Comments on Rosazza, Imbornone, Zorzi, Farina, Chiavari, and Cappa (2003). Neurocase 10, 78–83. doi: 10.1080/13554790490960530
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2009). Concepts and categories: a cognitive neuropsychological perspective. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 60, 27–51. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.60.110707.163532
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2011). What drives the organization of object knowledge in the brain? Trends Cogn. Sci. 15, 97–103. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2011.01.004
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Mahon, B. Z., Milleville, S. C., Negri, G. A., Rumiati, R. I., Caramazza, A., and Martin, A. (2007). Action-related properties shape object representations in the ventral stream. Neuron 55, 507–520. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2007.07.011
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Markie, P. (2013). “Rationalism vs. Empiricism,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed E. N. Zalta (Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab).
Marra, C., Ferraccioli, M., and Gainotti, G. (2007). Gender-related dissociations of categorical fluency in normal subjects and in subjects with Alzheimer’s disease. Neuropsychology 21, 207–211. doi: 10.1037/0894-4105.21.2.207
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Martin, A. (2007). The representation of object concepts in the brain. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 58, 25–45. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.57.102904.190143
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Martin, A., and Chao, L. L. (2001). Semantic memory and the brain: structure and processes. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 11, 194–201. doi: 10.1016/s0959-4388(00)00196-3
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Martin, A., Ungerleider, L. G., and Haxby, J. V. (2000). “Category-specificity and the brain: the sensory-motor model of semantic representations of objects,” in The New Cognitive Neurosciences, ed M. S. Gazzaniga (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 1023–1036.
Martin, A., Wiggs, C. L., Ungerleider, L. G., and Haxby, J. V. (1996). Neural correlates of category-specific knowledge. Nature 379, 649–652. doi: 10.1038/379649a0
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Masullo, C., Piccininni, C., Quaranta, D., Vita, M. G., Gaudino, S., and Gainotti, G. (2012). Selective impairment of living things and musical instruments on a verbal ‘Semantic Knowledge Questionnaire’ in a case of apperceptive visual agnosia. Brain Cogn. 80, 155–159. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2012.06.002
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
McKenna, P., and Parry, R. (1994). Category-specificity in the naming of natural and manmade objects: normative data from adults and children. Neuropsychol. Rehabil. 4, 225–281. doi: 10.1080/09602019408401461
McRae, K., and Cree, G. S. (2002). “Factors underlying category-specific impairments,” in Category Specificity in Brain and Mind, eds E. M. E. Forde and G. W. Humphreys (Hove: Psychology Press), 211–249.
Mechelli, A., Sartori, G., Orlandi, P., and Price, C. J. (2006). Semantic relevance explains category effects in medial fusiform gyri. Neuroimage 30, 992–1002. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2005.10.017
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Mitchell, T. M., Shinkareva, S. V., Carlson, A., Chang, K. M., Malave, V. L., Mason, R. A., et al. (2008). Predicting human brain activity associated with the meaning of nouns. Science 320, 1191–1195. doi: 10.1126/science.1152876
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Moreno-Martinez, F. J., Laws, K. R., and Schulz, J. (2008). The impact of dementia, age and sex on category fluency: greater deficits in women with Alzheimer’s disease. Cortex 44, 1256–1264. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2007.11.008
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Moss, H. E., Rodd, J. M., Stamatakis, E. A., Bright, P., and Tyler, L. K. (2005). Anteromedial temporal cortex supports fine-grained differentiation among objects. Cereb. Cortex 15, 616–627. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhh163
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Muñoz, K. E., Hyde, L. W., and Hariri, A. R. (2009). Imaging genetics. J. Am. Acad. Child Adolesc. Psychiatry 48, 356–361. doi: 10.1097/CHI.0b013e31819aad07
Negri, G. A., Rumiati, R. I., Zadini, A., Ukmar, M., Mahon, B. Z., and Caramazza, A. (2007). What is the role of motor simulation in action and object recognition? Evidence from apraxia. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 24, 795–816. doi: 10.1080/02643290701707412
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Nicodemus, K. K., Elvevåg, B., Foltz, P. W., Rosenstein, M., Diaz-Asper, C., and Weinberger, D. R. (2014). Category fluency, latent semantic analysis and schizophrenia: a candidate gene approach. Cortex 55, 182–191. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2013.12.004
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Noppeney, U., Price, C. J., Penny, W. D., and Friston, K. J. (2006). Two distinct neural mechanisms for category-selective responses. Cereb. Cortex 16, 437–445. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhi123
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Patterson, K., and Hodges, J. R. (2000). “Semantic dementia: one window on the structure and organisation of semantic memory,” in Handbook of Neuropsychology (Vol. 2), 2nd Edn. eds F. Boller and J. Grafman (North-Holland: Elsevier), 313–333.
Peelen, M. V., He, C., Han, Z., Caramazza, A., and Bi, Y. (2014). Nonvisual and visual object shape representations in occipitotemporal cortex: evidence from congenitally blind and sighted adults. J. Neurosci. 34, 163–170. doi: 10.1523/jneurosci.1114-13.2014
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Pereira, F., Botvinick, M., and Detre, G. (2013). Using Wikipedia to learn semantic feature representations of concrete concepts in neuroimaging experiments. Artif. Intell. 194, 240–252. doi: 10.1016/j.artint.2012.06.005
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Pinel, P., Lalanne, C., Bourgeron, T., Fauchereau, F., Poupon, C., Artiges, E., et al. (2014). Genetic and environmental influences on the visual word form and fusiform face areas. Cereb. Cortex doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhu048. [Epub ahead of print].
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Pourtois, G., Schwartz, S., Spiridon, M., Martuzzi, R., and Vuilleumier, P. (2009). Object representations for multiple visual categories overlap in lateral occipital and medial fusiform cortex. Cereb. Cortex 19, 1806–1819. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhn210
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1973). What the mind’s eye tells to the mind’s brain: a critique of mental imagery. Psychol. Bull. 80, 1–24. doi: 10.1037/h0034650
Randall, B., Moss, H. E., Rodd, J. M., Greer, M., and Tyler, L. K. (2004). Distinctiveness and correlation in conceptual structure: behavioral and computational studies. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 30, 393–406. doi: 10.1037/0278-7393.30.2.393
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Ricciardi, E., and Pietrini, P. (2011). New light from the dark: what blindness can teach us about brain function. Curr. Opin. Neurol. 24, 357–363. doi: 10.1097/wco.0b013e328348bdbf
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Röder, B., Rösler, F., and Hennighausen, E. (1997). Different cortical activation patterns in blind and sighted humans during encoding and transformation of haptic images. Psychophysiology 34, 292–307. doi: 10.1111/j.1469-8986.1997.tb02400.x
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Rosazza, C., Imbornone, E., Zorzi, M., Farina, E., Chiavari, L., and Cappa, S. F. (2003). The heterogeneity of category-specific semantic disorders: evidence from a new case. Neurocase 9, 189–202. doi: 10.1076/neur.9.3.189.15557
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Rosci, C., Chiesa, V., Laiacona, M., and Capitani, E. (2003). Apraxia is not associated to a disproportionate naming impairment for manipulable objects. Brain Cogn. 53, 412–415. doi: 10.1016/s0278-2626(03)00156-8
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Sadato, N., Pascual-Leone, A., Grafman, J., Ibañez, V., Deiber, M. P., Dold, G., et al. (1996). Activation of the primary visual cortex by Braille reading in blind subjects. Nature 380, 526–528. doi: 10.1038/380526a0
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Saffran, E. M., and Schwartz, M. F. (1994). Of cabbages and things: semantic memory from a neuropsychological perspective—a tutorial review.Atten. Perform. 25, 507–536.
Samson, D., and Pillon, A. (2003). A case of impaired knowledge for fruit and vegetables. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 20, 373–400. doi: 10.1080/02643290244000329
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Sartori, G., and Job, R. (1988). The oyster with four legs: a neuropsycholigical study on the interaction of visual and semantic information. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 5, 105–132. doi: 10.1080/02643298808252928
Saygin, A. P., Wilson, S. M., Dronkers, N. F., and Bates, E. (2004). Action comprehension in aphasia: linguistic and non-linguistic deficits and their lesion correlates. Neuropsychologia 42, 1788–1804. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2004.04.016
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Scotti, S., Laiacona, M., and Capitani, E. (2010). Brain damage and semantic category dissociations: is the animals category easier for males? Neurol. Sci. 31, 483–489. doi: 10.1007/s10072-010-0328-z
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Silveri, M. C., and Gainotti, G. (1988). Interaction between vision and language in category-specific semantic impairment. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 5, 677–709. doi: 10.1080/02643298808253278
Simmons, W. K., and Barsalou, L. W. (2003). The similarity-in-topography principle: reconciling theories of conceptual deficits. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 20, 451–486. doi: 10.1080/02643290342000032
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Siri, S., Kensinger, E. A., Cappa, S. F., Hood, K. L., and Corkin, S. (2003). Questioning the living/nonliving dichotomy: evidence from a patient with an unusual semantic dissociation. Neuropsychology 17, 630–645. doi: 10.1037/0894-4105.17.4.630
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Srihasam, K., Mandeville, J. B., Morocz, I. A., Sullivan, K. J., and Livingstone, M. S. (2012). Behavioral and anatomical consequences of early versus late symbol training in macaques. Neuron 73, 608–619. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2011.12.022
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Strauss, E., Semenza, C., Hunter, M., Hermann, B., Barr, W., Chelune, G., et al. (2000). Left anterior lobectomy and category-specific naming. Brain Cogn. 43, 403–406.
Striem-Amit, E., Dakwar, O., Reich, L., and Amedi, A. (2012). The large-scale organization of “visual” streams emerges without visual experience. Cereb. Cortex 22, 1698–1709. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhr253
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Struiksma, M. E., Noordzij, M. L., Neggers, S. F., Bosker, W. M., and Postma, A. (2011). Spatial language processing in the blind: evidence for a supramodal representation and cortical reorganization. PLoS One 6:e24253. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0024253
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Taylor, J. C., Devereux, B. J., and Tyler, L. K. (2011). Conceptual structure: towards an integrated neuro-cognitive account. Lang. Cogn. Proc. 26, 1368–1401. doi: 10.1080/01690965.2011.568227
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Taylor, J. C., and Downing, P. E. (2011). Division of labor between lateral and ventral extrastriate representations of faces, bodies and objects. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 23, 4122–4137. doi: 10.1162/jocn_a_00091
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Taylor, J. C., Stamatakis, E. A., and Tyler, L. K. (2009). Crossmodal integration of object features: voxel-based correlations in brain-damaged patients. Brain 132, 671–683. doi: 10.1093/brain/awn361
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Tranel, D., Damasio, H., and Damasio, A. R. (1997a). A neural basis for the retrieval of conceptual knowledge. Neuropsychologia 35, 1319–1327. doi: 10.1016/s0028-3932(97)00085-7
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Tranel, D., Logan, C. G., Frank, R. J., and Damasio, A. R. (1997b). Explaining category-related effects in the retrieval of conceptual and lexical knowledge for concrete entities: operationalization and analysis of factors. Neuropsychologia 35, 1329–1339. doi: 10.1016/s0028-3932(97)00086-9
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Tyler, L. K., and Moss, H. E. (2001). Towards a distributed account of conceptual knowledge. Trends Cogn. Sci. 5, 244–252. doi: 10.1016/s1364-6613(00)01651-x
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Tyler, L. K., Moss, H. E., Durrant-Peatfield, M., and Levy, J. P. (2000). Conceptual structure and the structure of categories: a distributed account of category-specific deficits. Brain Lang. 75, 195–231. doi: 10.1006/brln.2000.2353
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Tyler, L. K., Stamatakis, E. A., Bright, P., Acres, K., Abdallah, S., Rodd, J. M., et al. (2004). Processing objects at different levels of specificity. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 16, 351–362. doi: 10.1162/089892904322926692
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Vanoverberghe, V., and Storms, G. (2003). Feature importance in feature generation and typicality rating. Eur. J. Cogn. Psychol. 15, 1–18. doi: 10.1080/09541440303600
Ventura, P., Morais, J., Brito-Mendes, C., and Kolinsky, R. (2005). The mental representation of living and nonliving things: differential weighting and interactivity of sensorial and non-sensorial features. Memory 13, 124–147. doi: 10.1080/09658210344000639
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Vigliocco, G., Vinson, D. P., Lewis, W., and Garrett, M. F. (2004). Representing the meanings of objects and action words: the feature and unitary semantic space hypothesis. Cogn. Psychol. 48, 422–488. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2003.09.001
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Warrington, E. K., and McCarthy, R. (1983). Category-specific access dysphasia. Brain 106, 859–878. doi: 10.1093/neucas/8.3.192
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Warrington, E. K., and McCarthy, R. (1987). Categories of knowledge: further fractionations and an attempted integration. Brain 110, 1273–1296. doi: 10.1093/brain/110.5.1273
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Warrington, E. K., and Shallice, T. (1984). Category-specific semantic impairments. Brain 107, 829–854. doi: 10.1093/brain/107.3.829
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Weisberg, J., van Turennout, M., and Martin, A. (2007). A neural system for learning about object function. Cereb. Cortex 17, 513–521. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhj176
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Yee, E., Chrysikou, E. G., Hoffman, E., and Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2013). Manual experience shapes object representations. Psychol. Sci. 24, 909–919. doi: 10.1177/0956797612464658
Zannino, G. D., Perri, R., Pasqualetti, P., Caltagirone, C., and Carlesimo, G. A. (2006). Analysis of the semantic representations of living and nonliving concepts: a normative study. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 23, 515–540. doi: 10.1080/02643290542000067
Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar
Keywords: category-specific semantic disorders, sensory-motor model of semantic knowledge, domains of knowledge hypothesis, role of experience in the representation of objects, inborn models of conceptual representations
Citation: Gainotti G (2015) Inborn and experience-dependent models of categorical brain organization. A position paper. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 9:2. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2015.00002
Received: 21 August 2014; Accepted: 02 January 2015;
Published online: 23 January 2015.
Edited by:
Arthur M. Jacobs, Freie Universität Berlin, GermanyReviewed by:
Markus J. Hofmann, University of Wuppertal, GermanyAlexander Gerald Huth, University of California, Berkeley, USA
Copyright © 2015 Gainotti. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution and reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Guido Gainotti, Center for Neuropsychological Research and Department of Neurosciences, Institute of Neurology Policlinico Gemelli, Catholic University of Rome, Largo A. Gemelli, 8 00168 Rome, Italy e-mail: gainotti@ rm.unicatt.it