Skip to main content

EDITORIAL article

Front. Ecol. Evol., 21 July 2023
Sec. Paleontology
This article is part of the Research Topic New Perspectives on Living Fossils View all 9 articles

Editorial: New perspectives on living fossils

  • 1Negaunee Integrative Research Center, Field Museum, Chicago, IL, United States
  • 2Department of Philosophy and Minnesota Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, MN, United States

Editorial on the Research Topic
New perspectives on living fossils

Hesitation: the controversy

What is it about “living fossils” that triggers dissatisfaction among scientists? The concept has been criticized for ill-defined definitional criteria, molecular genetic change despite apparent morphological stasis, faulty phylogenetic inference, or inadequate measurement of evolutionary rates (Schopf, 1984; Bennett et al., 2017) in groups as dissimilar as cycads (Nagalingum et al., 2011), tadpole shrimps (Mathers et al., 2013) and coelacanth and polypterid fishes (Casane and Laurenti, 2013; Near et al., 2014). Complaints generally concern whether to categorize a biological entity as a living fossil. The hesitation from these concerns does not tell the whole story and is not a reason to forsake analyses of living fossils. Instead, what matters is whether the living fossil concept can be used constructively. Our argument is that concepts have a role in science beyond categorization (Lidgard and Love, 2018; Lidgard and Love, 2021). Routine usage of a living fossil concept reflects a research agenda on evolutionary stasis, consisting in a set of interrelated questions contextualized to serve particular explanatory tasks (Lidgard and Kitchen). What we need is to use our concepts wisely. Here we summarize how papers in this Research Topic exemplify this pattern of wise use and consider the challenge of utilizing the concept moving forward.

Appreciation: the papers

The first thing to appreciate is just how routinely the living fossil concept is invoked. Lidgard and Kitchen capture the expansion of criteria from 1860 through the present, tracing the ongoing increase of over 800 entities named as living fossils across kingdoms and the biological hierarchy, from RNAs to taxonomic Classes. No single definition adequately describes all contexts and named entities. Rather, within a research agenda, distinctive living fossil criteria are most appropriate for a given question and particular entity (or entities). Turner and Han show that many proposed definitions appeal to a distinctive evolutionary history and this provides a foundation to ascribe conservation value to living fossil taxa. Vargas analyzes endangered monotypic genera, applying an “Endangered Living Fossil” concept pragmatically to prioritize specific taxa for conservation. Two papers address conflicts that arise when one set of traits seems to challenge living fossil status and a different set appears to support it. This requires thinking in terms of parts and wholes (Lidgard and Love, 2018): when should sets of traits like genes or morphological structures be considered proxies for historical entities like species or genera that bear them? Analyzing the Hox gene cluster in branchiopod crustaceans, Nicolini et al. show how morphological evolution is not tightly associated with genome dynamics. Rieppel elegantly traces systematists’ recognition of the mosaic evolution of characters in a lineage back into the late 19th century; its occurrence in living fossils does not differ from other taxa. Instead of part-whole conflicts disqualifying a living fossil concept, the contrasting signals can be scrutinized to understand how and why they occur, and why rates of change seem so disparate. Cavin and Alvarez provide evidence that suggests long generation and gestation times help to account for the slow rate of evolution in the coelacanth body plan. Sterner grapples with operationalizing criteria for living fossils by comparing two theoretical frameworks as a basis for improving evidential standards for classification. Finally, Hopkins et al. question whether there is anything special about the present time in pursuing living fossil questions—can “extinct living fossils” yield valuable new insights?

Utilization: the challenge

The primary challenge for any scientific concept is how it use it. “A concept is only as good as the research program it inspires … concepts should play the role of inspiring and guiding progressive empirical and theoretical investigation” (Wagner, 2015, 340). This challenge involves at least three tasks: explicit characterization, research question articulation, and the specification of evaluative standards. First, given different living fossil criteria, no researcher should assume their use of the concept is implicitly understood. If you intend “living fossils” to pick out prolonged geological duration relative to similar entities, then explicitly characterize what counts as prolonged duration and which entities are relevantly similar for comparison. If you intend “living fossils” to pick out very low taxonomic richness today compared to the past, then explicitly characterize what counts as high and low taxonomic richness and what past junctures should be used for comparison. Similar situations arise with scientific concepts such as “gene” or “species.”

Second, articulate the research question with precision. If you are considering why some but not all constellations of morphological characters exhibit apparent stasis over long periods of time in the same lineage, delineate which constellations of morphological characters are in view and how you would adequately measure their properties to test different hypotheses. Some research questions appear similar but require asking something distinct. The recurring problem of how suites of morphological versus molecular characters are related to slow rates of change (if at all) is not identical to the first question, because discrepancies in evolutionary rates between groups of morphological characters do not yield immediate answers to discrepancies in rates between a group of morphological characters and a group of molecular characters.

Finally, it is crucial to specify evaluative standards for a concept, especially when used across different disciplinary approaches. For example, if the aim is to draw a phylogenetic inference about specific characters being plesiomorphic, then the relevant evaluative standards derive at least in part from phylogenetic methodology. The ability to ascertain whether a living fossil entity represents a retention of ancestral character states cannot rely on presumptive inferences about the characters of unstudied species or use pruned trees for comparison (Jenner, 2022). The specification of evaluative standards means that one can incorrectly invoke the idea of a living fossil, whether for the purpose of categorization or evolutionary inference. A combination of explicit characterization, research question articulation, and specification of evaluative standards facilitates progressive empirical and theoretical inquiry.

Although more can be said about how to operationalize the living fossil concept within a research program about stasis—slow or negligible rates of evolutionary change—for diverse features in living systems, the contributions to this Research Topic display the productivity we should expect of a scientific concept and thereby offer exactly what was intended: new perspectives on living fossils.

Author contributions

SL and AL contributed equally to conception of the idea for this Research Project, working with authors and reviewers, and writing the editorial. All authors contributed to the article and approved the submitted version.

Funding

Partial financial support for this work came from a John Templeton Foundation grant (#62220) to AL. The opinions expressed in this article are those of the authors, and not those of the John Templeton Foundation.

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to all of the authors, reviewers, and associate editors who made this project possible.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

Bennett D. J., Sutton M. D., Turvey S. T. (2017). Evolutionarily distinct “living fossils” require both lower speciation and lower extinction rates. Paleobiology 43, 34–48. doi: 10.1017/pab.2016.36

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Casane D., Laurenti P. (2013). Why coelacanths are not ‘living fossils’. BioEssays 35, 332–338. doi: 10.1002/bies.201200145

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jenner R. (2022). Ancestors in evolutionary biology: linear thinking about branching trees (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

Google Scholar

Lidgard S., Love A. C. (2018). Rethinking living fossils. BioScience 68, 760–770. doi: 10.1093/biosci/biy084

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Lidgard S., Love A. C. (2021). The living fossil concept: reply to Turner. Biol. Philos. 36, 13. doi: 10.1007/s10539-021-09789-z

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mathers T. C., Hammond R. L., Jenner R. A., Hänfling B., Gómez A. (2013). Multiple global radiations in tadpole shrimps challenge the concept of ‘living fossils’. PeerJ 1, e62. doi: 10.7717/peerj.62

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nagalingum N. S., Marshall C. R., Quental T. B., Rai H. S., Little D. P., Mathews S. (2011). Recent synchronous radiation of a living fossil. Science 334, 796–799. doi: 10.2307/41351691

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Near T. J., Dornburg A., Tokita M., Suzuki D., Brandley M. C., Friedman M. (2014). Boom and bust: ancient and recent diversification in bichirs (Polypteridae: Actinopterygii), a relictual lineage of ray-finned fishes. Evolution 68, 1014–1026. doi: 10.1111/evo.12323

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schopf T. J. (1984). Rates of evolution and the notion of “living fossils”. Annu. Rev. Earth Planet. Sci. 12, 245–292d. doi: 10.1146/annurev.ea.12.050184.001333

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wagner G. P. (2015). “Reinventing the organism: evolvability and homology in post-Dahlem evolutionary biology,” in Conceptual change in biology: scientific and philosophical perspectives on evolution and development. Ed. Love A. C. (Berlin: Springer), 327–342.

Google Scholar

Keywords: character evolution, concepts, living fossils, part-whole relationships, research agenda

Citation: Lidgard S and Love AC (2023) Editorial: New perspectives on living fossils. Front. Ecol. Evol. 11:1250106. doi: 10.3389/fevo.2023.1250106

Received: 29 June 2023; Accepted: 03 July 2023;
Published: 21 July 2023.

Edited and Reviewed by:

Bruce S. Lieberman, University of Kansas, United States

Copyright © 2023 Lidgard and Love. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Scott Lidgard, slidgard@fieldmuseum.org

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.