Skip to main content

ORIGINAL RESEARCH article

Front. Behav. Neurosci., 20 November 2014
Sec. Emotion Regulation and Processing
This article is part of the Research Topic Prosocial and antisocial behavior in economic games View all 28 articles

Predictable and predictive emotions: explaining cheap signals and trust re-extension

  • 1Economic Science Institute, Chapman University, Orange, CA, USA
  • 2Department of Economics, Weatherhead School of Management, Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, OH, USA

Despite normative predictions from economics and biology, unrelated strangers will often develop the trust necessary to reap gains from one-shot economic exchange opportunities. This appears to be especially true when declared intentions and emotions can be cheaply communicated. Perhaps even more puzzling to economists and biologists is the observation that anonymous and unrelated individuals, known to have breached trust, often make effective use of cheap signals, such as promises and apologies, to encourage trust re-extension. We used a pair of trust games with one-way communication and an emotion survey to investigate the role of emotions in regulating the propensity to message, apologize, re-extend trust, and demonstrate trustworthiness. This design allowed us to observe the endogenous emergence and natural distribution of trust-relevant behaviors, remedial strategies used by promise-breakers, their effects on behavior, and subsequent outcomes. We found that emotions triggered by interaction outcomes are predictable and also predict subsequent apology and trust re-extension. The role of emotions in behavioral regulation helps explain why messages are produced, when they can be trusted, and when trust will be re-extended.

Introduction

In this paper, we explore the role of positive emotions (pride, believability, appreciation, contentment, cheerfulness, happiness) and negative emotions (guilt, shame, anger, disgust, aggravation, frustration) in regulating cheap signaling, trust re-extension, and trustworthy behavior in the wake of a veiled trust-based interaction between strangers with no explicit indication of certain expectation for repeated interaction1. Interactions with strangers have presented recurrent adaptive problems over the course of human evolutionary history (Fehr and Henrich, 2003) and are common in modern society, especially in global markets (Nowak and Sigmund, 2005; Seabright, 2010). Sometimes unexpected opportunities for repeated exchange with previously cooperative or uncooperative partners arise2. Once exchange histories establish, partners with mutually beneficial non-binding agreements often reap gains from iterated trust-based trade with one another (Cochard et al., 2004; Boero et al., 2009; Kaplan et al., 2012). However, investors ceding resources (in anticipation of desired returns) remain subject to various kinds of exploitation by previously trusted partners. Partners who demonstrated trustworthiness in the past might subsequently engage in Machiavellian manipulations (Humphrey, 1976; Byrne and Whiten, 1988) by sending false signals about intentions to engage in future trustworthy behavior. Upon being re-extended trust, these previously trusted partners can opportunistically exploit their positions3. Alternatively, if a partner was previously untrustworthy (e.g., breaking a promise and not returning profits on investment) but claims to have intentions and propensity for future trustworthiness, an investor must decide whether to forgo potential gains from future trust-based exchange (by not re-extending trust) or else pursue the available opportunity with that previously untrustworthy partner, at the risk of being repeatedly deceived or exploited4. While much attention has been given to the production and evaluation of cues and signals affecting novel trust extension, less attention has been given to the dilemma of trust re-extension and the role of emotions in regulating relevant behaviors.

The ability to integrate evaluations of reputation from cues and signal quality, infer a partner's propensity toward future trustworthiness, and accordingly regulate trust re-extension would have been a highly advantageous trait over the course of human evolutionary history and should continue to be in modern economies. Evolutionary theories of emotions (Nesse, 1990; Tooby and Cosmides, 1990; Haselton and Ketelaar, 2006; Tooby et al., 2008; Schniter and Shields, 2013) have proposed that key emotions have been selected to assist us in accomplishing these tasks. We test the propositions that new information about trust-based interaction outcomes triggers emotions, and that, when experienced, these emotions regulate re-affirmative and remedial behaviors, and the propensity to re-extend trust.

To study the predictors of emotions and the effects of emotions on spontaneous messaging and trust re-extension, we conducted a non-deceptive study wherein financially motivated participants used endogenously created and naturally distributed promises and messages. Our study is based on a version of the “investment game” by Berg et al. (1995). In our experiments trustees made non-binding promises of investment-contingent returns, then investors decided whether to invest, and finally trustees decided how much to return. Since investing money is risky, investments are usually interpreted as trust. Likewise, because voluntary returns are costly to trustees, the delivery of promised returns on investment (ROI) is interpreted as evidence of trustworthiness. We also administered a 20 item survey in which participants reported their emotional status as a consequence of the decisions and interaction outcomes that they just experienced5. After an unexpected second game was announced, but before it commenced, trustees could send a one-way message. This design allowed us to observe the endogenous emergence and natural distribution of trust-relevant behaviors, consequent emotions, and focus on these emotions' effects on trustees' naturally occurring communication strategies, investors' trust re-extension, and trustee's trustworthiness.

While results on the observed frequencies of game behaviors in both trust games of this study are reported in the Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization (Schniter et al., 2013), we did not previously examine the role of emotions. In this paper we evaluate reports of emotions and their role in regulating behaviors relevant to the dilemma of trust re-extension.

Background

Despite normative predictions, trust is often developed in experimental one-shot environments with unrelated strangers (Dawes and Thaler, 1988; Kiyonari et al., 2000; McCabe et al., 2003; Krasnow et al., 2013), especially when facilitated by cheap talk and emotions (Frank, 1988, 2004; McElreath et al., 2003; Schweitzer et al., 2006; Ben-Ner and Putterman, 2009; Ben-Ner et al., 2011; Gambetta and Székely, 2014; Sheremeta and Zhang, 2014). In this section we provide some background on three important literatures to which our research links: the first concerns trust-based exchange dilemmas and the evolution of cooperation, the second concerns cheap signaling and trust re-extension, and the third concerns the role of recalibrational emotions in cheap signaling and trust re-extension.

When taking into account the observation that people exist and have long existed under the uncertain but ever present shadow of possible future interactions with others, the propensity to trust (despite hazards for opportunism) may bring net exchange benefits6. Under such conditions natural selection may have favored those with the propensity to cooperate even when exposed to indicators that interactions were one-shot and interaction partners were unknown (Delton et al., 2011; Krasnow et al., 2013). Sayings like “you always meet twice in a lifetime,” “you haven't seen the last of me,” and “dangerous enemies will meet again in narrow streets” seem to provide justification for the human tendency to treat others as if they will be beneficial exchange partners or threats in the future, despite the absence of cues assuring there will be repeated interaction. The one-shot investment game (Berg et al., 1995) that models the opportunity to develop and allocate gains through exchange, has shown time and again that people exposed to one-shot sequential exchange opportunities with anonymous others tend to behave in a mutually beneficial way (for reviews see Ostrom and Walker, 2005; Balliet and Van Lange, 2012) despite the normative proscription from game theory: do not cooperate because your partner will not cooperate.

In the absence of information about past behavior, “cheap” messages (bearing little in the way of up-front costs for production) are often sent to receivers with the intention of communicating information about the sender (e.g., see Farrell and Rabin, 1996). For example, non-binding promises (of intended trustworthiness) have been shown to increase cooperation (Rubin and Brown, 1975; Kerr and Kaufman-Gilliland, 1994; Ellingsen and Johannesson, 2004; Charness and Dufwenberg, 2006; Sutter, 2009). Where demonstrated behavior has informed investors of a trustee's untrustworthiness, messages may be sent with the intention of persuading investors that the trustee is more trustworthy than inferred from cues alone. Many find it quite puzzling that so-called “cheap signals” can effectively be used to negotiate trust between individuals with conflicting interests (Lachmann et al., 2001) and that it is even possible for promise-breakers to rebuild damaged trust by issuing apologies (Schniter et al., 2013). Below we review why trust can be built with the help of cheap-to-produce messages and why those who re-extend trust to previously untrustworthy individuals (e.g., to promise breakers) may take their messages into consideration.

Cheap-to-produce messages can maintain their reliability because they often end up being “costly” after being used to deceive (Schniter et al., 2013). Through reputational sanctions or exclusion from future interactions, receivers of deceptively used cheap signals can impose ex post costs greater than the benefits initially derived from deceptively using those signals (Rohwer, 1977; Masclet et al., 2003; Schweitzer et al., 2006)—thereby maintaining signal reliability in the society in which it was used.

Though it has been studied little, it is reasonable to expect that the psychological machinery designed to produce and evaluate cheap signals is attuned to the experience and perception of emotions. Emotions are important components of message composition, speech production and perception, and face-to-face communication. Personal communication in various forms is known to improve cooperation (Orbell et al., 1988; Bohnet and Frey, 1999; Ridings et al., 2002; Zheng et al., 2002; Buchan et al., 2006; Cason et al., 2012) by facilitating coordination, decreasing social distance, raising solidarity, and providing the cues of familiarity that are normally associated with trustworthy relationships. Smith (1759) wrote of the “fellow feeling” that can be generated, for example as a consequence of sharing in another's emotional state, and being part of the process of improving it. According to Smith, the capacity to experience the pleasurable “fellow feeling” is based on our ability to model another's circumstances and emotional reaction to them, and to internally simulate (sympathize with) the emotional feelings that they might derive. When messages are produced7, they are often assembled with verbiage meant to demonstrate regard for the recipient, persuade a change in the recipient's perspectives, and provide information of the signaler's intentions and emotional experiences: things which may not be otherwise known (Pennebaker and Graybeal, 2001). Though the messages we consider guarantee no honest information, their length is a potential indication of the effort invested into an attempt to communicate these potentially unknown things. On the other hand, where messages are intended as re-affirmations of known things (e.g., recent cooperation), their length is not as necessary. Thus, to understand the human ecology of cheap signal production and evaluation, one should also understand the dynamic triggering of emotions and their targeted effects on the propensity to engage in communication.

According to the recalibrational theory of emotions, when evolved psychological machinery has computationally identified adaptive problems (such as resulting from social dilemma outcomes), emotional responses are triggered that encourage recalibration of behavior regulation programs (Tooby et al., 2008; Schniter and Shields, 2013; Schniter et al., 2014). As such, emotions are hedonic components of a learning system that integrates relevant experiences to inform individual decisions and interaction behaviors. Emotions are often relatively “automatic,” difficult to control, and distinct from cogitative non-emotional learning8. When triggered, emotional responses typically produce sudden physiological changes (e.g., arousal) and affect facial expression, posture, subjective experience and perception, and action tendencies (Frijda, 1986; Tooby and Cosmides, 1990).

Consistent with recalibrational theories of emotions, we hypothesize that emotions integrate new information about trust-based interaction outcomes, providing hedonic feedback that people experience as either positively valenced (pleasantly motivating continuation of prior behaviors associated with its occurrence) or negatively valenced (unpleasantly motivating disengagement and pursuit of alternative strategies). It is hypothesized that this positive or negative emotional feedback is designed to motivate changes to behavioral propensities so as to enhance success in future relationships characterized by similar cooperation dilemmas. For example, when a trust-based relationship has been developed and assured, good feelings such as pride and appreciation are experienced (Schniter and Shields, 2013; Schniter et al., 2014). As a result, proud trustees may be more inclined to re-affirm the good relationship and demonstrate more trustworthiness (Nesse, 1990; Fessler, 1999, 2001), and appreciative or grateful investors may be more likely to trust the trustee's cheap signals and re-extend trust (Hirshleifer, 1987; McCullough et al., 2001; Dunn and Schweitzer, 2005; Algoe et al., 2008; Tooby and Cosmides, 2008). Alternatively, when a trustee has demonstrated untrustworthy behavior (breaking a promise or exploiting an investor) the investor may experience anger and frustration (e.g., see Ortony et al., 1988; Dunn and Schweitzer, 2005) while the trustee experiences guilt, and shame (e.g., see Baumeister et al., 1994; Smith et al., 2002; Ketelaar and Au, 2003; Sznycer, 2010; Sznycer et al., 2012). Angry and frustrated investor's may be more likely to distrust subsequent promises or offers from the untrustworthy trustee (e.g., see Pillutla and Murnighan, 1996; Dunn and Schweitzer, 2005), and more likely to impose costs or restrict benefits (e.g., see Sell et al., 2009). A guilty or shameful trustee may be motivated to make remedial efforts (e.g., issuing a persuasive message or apology) targeting the affected investor—especially when there is possibility of future trust-based exchange opportunity with this potentially angry investor (Fessler, 2001; Sznycer, 2010; de Hooge et al., 2011; Sznycer et al., 2012). Apology has been demonstrated to be a particularly effective remedial signal that encourages a victim to trust again by expressing responsibility for an offense and possibly the promise of forbearance, an offer of condolence, or repair (Scher and Darley, 1997; Ho, 2012; Fischbacher and Utikal, 2013; Schniter et al., 2013).

Emotionally affected speech and facial expression have long been believed to have some “honest signal” features revealing underlying emotional states (Darwin, 1872/1965). A century after Darwin, researchers began making a strong case that basic human emotions are not only universal in their distinct facial and vocal expressions, but also that the identification of these emotions exists and is consistent across humans. Evidently, humans can accurately recognize many basic emotions (e.g., happiness, surprise, sadness, fear, disgust, and anger) across quite different cultures in faces (Ekman et al., 1969), voices (Bryant and Barrett, 2008; Sauter et al., 2010), and written messages (Xiao and Houser, 2005) supporting the notion that these communicative forms provide fairly reliable indicators of the positive and negative affect, if not actual emotion, that the sender experiences (Keltner and Kring, 1998) and that a reduction in ambiguity has been selected for in human emotional signaling (Searcy and Nowicki, 2005). Hirshleifer (1987) and Frank (1988, 2004) proposed that emotions provide information about people's behavior propensities (e.g., as guarantors of promises) because they work as commitment devices. As veridical signals, emotions appear to be sufficiently reliable in this capacity; emotional displays are more often than not involuntary and high levels of emotional expressivity are difficult to imitate (Boone and Buck, 2003; Schug et al., 2010). Thus, the standard human ecology in which “cheap” signal production and evaluation was designed to operate is not entirely costless. Rather, because the signaling of emotional states is often veridical, language should be evaluated and trusted according to its correspondence with emotional propensities. Under these conditions, detection of deceptive language production would lead to the imposition of more costs than benefits on the signaler—effectively making cheaply produced language in the context of displayed emotions a “costly signal.”

We anticipated that, despite the anonymity we guaranteed participants in our laboratory implementation of the trust game (i.e., ensuring that their partners would not personally identify or watch them), experiences of emotions would be reliably produced and recognized by those experiencing them9. We evaluate the reported experience of several emotions (appreciation, contentment, cheerfulness, happiness, pride, believability, anger, disgust, aggravation, frustration, guilt, and shame) and whether these emotions predict the use of cheaply produced messages, trust re-extension, and trustworthy or opportunistic behavior. We hypothesize that these emotions serve the recalibrational functions outlined in Schniter and Shields (2013), and below detail specific predictions about the triggering of these emotions and how experienced emotions will correlate with subsequent behaviors. Previous studies have shown that the experience of emotions affects subsequent game behavior (Pillutla and Murnighan, 1996; Fehr and Gächter, 2002; Ketelaar and Au, 2003; Capra, 2004; Dunn and Schweitzer, 2005; Hopfensitz and Reuben, 2009; Kausel and Connolly, 2014). The current study contributes to this literature by examining how trust-relevant integral emotions are naturally triggered by interaction outcomes and how they inform trust repair and re-extension in subsequent interactions after trust is damaged10.

Experiment Details and Hypotheses

Experiment Details

Our research was approved by Chapman University's internal review board for research with human subjects and informed consent was obtained from all participants. The research was conducted at Chapman University's ESI laboratory. 458 participants (229 pairs) were recruited from a standard campus-wide subject pool for participation in a session that could last up to 45 min. There were 25 sessions. Each session had between 10 and 24 participants. The average earnings from experiments were $18, ranging from a $0 to $40, plus $7 for arriving to the session on time and participating. No participant participated more than once, and no participant had prior experience with a similar game environment. During a session, participants seated at visually isolated cubicles interacted with each other anonymously over a local computer network. Our procedure consisting of three parts, lasted an average of 35 min total, did not involve deception11, and proceeded as follows. Upon arrival, participants were told that they would receive $7 for participation, to be paid at the end of the session along with any additional money made during the session.

In the first part of the session, participants received instructions (see Supplementary Material) for and interacted in an “experiment”: a veiled trust game with (i) no indication of a subsequent game to follow and (ii) no statements that the session would end at conclusion of that game. The first trust game is denoted as “veiled” because participants are intentionally not informed of a subsequent “repetition of the experiment”: a trust game (repeated with same roles and partners as before) that would follow in part three12. Participants were assigned to one of two roles: “Participant A” (investor), or “Participant B” (trustee). First, the trustee completed the following standardized statement (which we will refer to below as a promise) by selecting an integer from 0 to 20: “I (Participant B) promise to transfer back $___of my income to you (Participant A) if you choose IN.” This statement was not binding, however. That is, the trustee was not obligated to transfer back the amount promised to the investor, and both trustee and investor knew this. The computer conveyed the trustee's statement to the investor and then the investor chose either OUT or IN. If the investor chose OUT, she received $5 and the trustee $0. If the investor chose IN (invest), then the trustee received $20 (the “income”), after which he selected a whole dollar amount from $0 to $20 to send back to the investor.

In the second part of the session, after the veiled trust game (game 1) finished, participants were given an emotional status survey (see Supplementary Material) that asked them to report how much they felt each of 20 emotional states (on a five point scale labeled (1) very slightly or not at all, (2) a little, (3) moderately, (4) quite a bit, (5) extremely) as a consequence of their recent game interactions and outcomes13. The computer software presented all emotional states on one screen and in random order.

In the third part of the session, after completing the survey, we gave our participants additional instructions (see Supplementary Material) indicating that they had opportunity to participate in a “repetition of the experiment.” These instructions unveiled that in game 2, participants would remain in the same roles and interact with the same partner as in game 1. The instructions also indicated that prior to game 2, the trustee would have an opportunity to use a “message” box to send a one-way message to the investor. Trustees were told that “in these messages, no one is allowed to identify him or herself by name, number, gender, or appearance,” but that other than these restrictions, trustees could “say anything in the message.” If trustees wished not to send a message they were instructed to “simply click on the send button without having typed anything in the message box.” The computer conveyed the trustee's message and subsequently the standardized promise to the investor, and then game 2 proceeded. We specified that game 2, which had the same rules as game 1, was the last experimental game in the session.

We classified whether messages from our study were apology (or not) using an incentivized laboratory coordination game (Houser and Xiao, 2011). Three coders recruited from the subject pool and blind to the hypotheses14 were asked to code each message based on whether or not it conformed to a broad definition of apology (“an explicit or implicit acknowledgment of offense”). All messages without content were coded by all coders as not conforming to the definition of apology and 93% of messages with content were coded by the majority of coders as conforming to the definition, a “substantial” inter-coder agreement (Kappa of 0.70)15.

Hypotheses

An earlier publication in the Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization (Schniter et al., 2013) detailed behavioral results from games 1 and 2 of this study, with particular attention to the effects of promises, transfers, messages, and apologies. This earlier publication did not examine the role of emotion experiences as a result of these games and gave less attention to the unanticipated dilemma of trust re-extension that we focus on here.

When deciding whether to re-extend trust, it is important for an investor to obtain accurate information about the propensity of trustees to behave in a trustworthy manner. The integrity of a trustee's previous promise (i.e., its signal value) and the actual returns made on investment (ROI) are indicators of trustworthy character demonstrated in past word and action or action alone, respectively. Previous studies suggest that these indicators of trustworthiness, with and without verbal components, may have separate effects on subsequent trust extension (Schweitzer et al., 2006; Schniter et al., 2013), so we examine their effects separately16. We hypothesize that these demonstrations of trustworthy character trigger emotional reactions in investors and trustees facing particular problems and that the emotions better calibrate them for repeated interaction with one another.

Specifically, we predict that when the signal value (= return − promise) of trustworthiness is negative (≥0), the trustee's psychology implicitly recognizes potential for a subsequent promise breaker's (promise keeper's) cooperation problem and triggers an emotional reaction: lower (higher) levels of pride and believability, higher (lower) levels of guilt and shame. When the non-verbal indicator of trustworthiness, ROI (= return/investment), is greater (not greater) than one, the trustee implicitly recognizes potential for a subsequent beneficent (opportunist) cooperation problem and an emotional reaction is triggered: feeling higher (lower) levels of pride and believability, lower (higher) levels of guilt and shame. We expect that together the trustee's beneficent (opportunist) and promise breaker (promise keeper) emotional reactions inform the trustee's propensity to produce spontaneous re-affirmative or remedial behaviors (constructing messages with content, constructing wordier messages with higher word count, and issuing spontaneous apologies) in preparation for a subsequent interaction problems.

We predict that when the signal value (= return − promise) is negative (positive), the investor implicitly recognizes potential for a subsequent damaged trust (assured trust) cooperation problem and an emotional reaction is triggered, characterized by higher (lower) levels of anger, disgust, aggravation, frustration, and lower (higher) levels of appreciation, contentment, cheerfulness, and happiness. When ROI is greater than one (one or less), the investor experiences a benefited (exploited) emotional reaction: feeling lower (higher) levels of anger, disgust, aggravation, frustration, and higher (lower) levels of appreciation, contentment, cheerfulness, and happiness.

We expect that the propensity to re-extend trust in game 2 is informed by the investor's emotional reactions to demonstrated trustworthiness, and some assessment of re-affirmative and remedial messaging (e.g., whether or not there is a message with content, what the word count of message is, whether or not an apology was issued) by the trustee after the investor's initial emotional reactions to game 1 interaction outcomes17. In Figure 1 we provide a path model visually representing the above predicted relationships between indicators of trustworthiness, emotional reactions to cooperation problems resulting from game 1 interaction outcomes, messaging behaviors, and the trust of re-extension decision. We suspect that investor emotional reactions to trustee re-affirmative and remedial behaviors would also affect our model, however we did not survey emotional reactions to either received messages or game 2 promises and are therefore unable to account for their partial effects.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. Path model of predicted relationship between variables.

In addition to the predicted emotional effects on messaging and trust re-extension summarized above and in Figure 1, we predict emotional effects on trustee behavior in game 2. Specifically, we predict a greater propensity to generate trustworthy indicators (e.g., with higher signal value and higher ROI) in game 2 among trustees who reported higher levels of emotional reaction to game 1—regardless of reaction valence (i.e., higher levels of feeling proud, believable, guilty, and ashamed). Conversely, we expect those reporting less emotional reaction to demonstrate less trustworthy behaviors.

Results

Trust and reciprocity decisions from this game are reported in detail in Schniter et al. (2013); however, the role of game outcomes in triggering emotional experiences, and the role of emotional experiences in affecting subsequent behavior propensity was not reported.

General Overview

We found no significant differences between the 25 sessions and report the joint results of all 458 participants where appropriate. As seen with similar games, we observed a high initial rate of promised cooperation: 95.2% (218/229) of trustees promised investors ROI > 1, 3.9% (9/229) promised ROI = 1, and 0.8% (2/229) promised ROI < 1. In game 1, there was also a high rate of trust in response to the promises: investors trusted 86.7% (189/218) of trustees promising ROI > 1 and 22.2% (2/9) promising ROI = 1, but none of those promising ROI < 1. Trusting investors from the first game (83.4% of all investors) faced a new set of challenges when they interacted with the same trustees again in a second unexpected game. Some of these investors decided whether to re-extend trust to trustees who cooperated in the first game by delivering a ROI > 1 (which 88.5% did), delivering the returns they promised (which 81.2% did), or both. Other investors decided whether to re-extend trust to trustees that did not deliver the returns they promised (18.8% of all trusted trustees), or did not deliver a profitable ROI (11.5% of all trusted trustees), or both. A subset of those who decided whether to re-extend trust to non-cooperators, appear to have also been influenced by their emotional reactions to game 1 and subsequent message and apology that were sometimes received.

We examined emotional state reports from the 382 participants who had game 1 interactions where trust was extended. We found moderately high reliability of internal consistency in their emotion reports: the Cronbach alpha coefficient is 0.889 for the 10 item Positive Affect Scale and 0.888 for the 10 item Negative Affect Scale of our 20 item survey, a version of the PANAS (Watson et al., 1988)18. There was substantial variability in individual reports of the 12 emotional states investigated below19. The average reported emotional state had a mean of 2.21 (median = 1, SD = 1.04), near 2 (“a little”). Ratings on every emotional state ranged from 1 (“very slightly or not at all”) to 5 (“extremely”). While the modal report for most (7/12) emotional states was 1 (“very slightly or not at all”) modes were also seen at 3 for believable and 4 for appreciative, content, cheerful, and happy. Reports of 1 were more frequent for emotional states in the negative set than for the positive set (1968/2292 vs. 400/2292, respectively), contributing to significantly lower intensity of reported negative states (M = 1.27, SD = 0.75) than positive states (M = 3.15, SD = 1.34) according to Wilcoxon matched-pairs tests (Z = −15.167, p < 0.001). This pattern of significantly lower reported negative states was observed in both investors (Z = −9.446, p < 0.001) and trustees (Z = −11.798, p < 0.001).

In this paper, we focus on the explanatory power of the emotional reactions we predict based on recalibrational theory. Below we report results indicating the predictable and predictive nature of emotional reactions in this unexpectedly repeated interaction. Emotions help explain whether participants attempted to use cheap signaling reassuringly or remedially, whether investors decided to re-extend trust, and whether individuals were more likely to break promises or benefit their exchange partners.

Predicted Emotions

Trustees: emotions predicted by behavior

In this section we evaluate whether the positive and negative emotional reactions to game 1, reported by naturally occurring groups of trustees and investors, were predicted by demonstrations of trustworthiness (signal value, ROI) after being trusted (i.e., invested in). As predicted, after game 1, promise breakers reported significantly higher levels of guilt and shame than promise keepers, and promise keepers reported significantly higher levels of pride and feeling believable than promise breakers. We provide bar charts of promise breaker's and promise keeper's emotions and report the details of Welch's t-test comparisons for equal means in Supplementary Material.

Also, consistent with our prediction of a beneficent (opportunist) emotional reaction in trustees, beneficent trustees delivering ROI > 1 in game 1 reported significantly higher levels of pride and feeling believable. Opportunist trustees reported significantly higher levels of guilt and shame. We provide bar charts of beneficent and opportunist trustees' emotions and report the details of Welch's t-test comparisons in Supplementary Material.

Figure 2 displays bubble plots of trustee emotion intensity (on a five point scale) and signal value (the difference between game 1 return and promise). Observations are plotted with bubbles, where the relative size indicates the proportion of observations at a given point. Table 1 reports results of linear regression models where the dependent variable is intensity of a specific emotion (proud, believable, guilty, ashamed) and the independent variable is signal value. We find that trustee emotions are predicted by signal value of the promise.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. Bubble plots of trustees' emotions and Signal value.

TABLE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Table 1. Regression of trustees' emotions on signal value.

Similarly, Figure 3 displays bubble plots of trustee emotion intensity and ROI. Table 2 reports results of estimating linear regression models where the dependent variable is intensity of a specific emotion (proud, believable, guilty, ashamed) and the independent variable is ROI. We find that trustee emotions are predicted by ROI. This leads us to our first result:

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. Bubble plots of trustees' emotions and ROI.

TABLE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Table 2. Regression of trustees' emotions on ROI.

Result 1: Trustees' demonstrations of trustworthiness in game 1, by signal value of promise and ROI, predict their subsequent emotions.

Investors: emotions predicted by behavior

As predicted, investors with damaged trust (where game 1 return < promise) reported significantly higher levels of anger, disgust, aggravation, and frustration while investors who had been assured with a return ≥ promise reported significantly higher levels of appreciation, contentment, cheerfulness, and happiness. We provide bar charts of emotions reported by investors with damaged trust and assured trust and report the details of Welch's t-test comparisons in Supplementary Material.

Also, consistent with our prediction, significantly lower levels of anger, disgust, aggravation, frustration, and significantly higher levels of appreciation, contentment, cheerfulness, and happiness were reported after game 1 by investors who had benefited from a ROI > 1, as opposed to those exploited by lower ROI. We provide bar charts of emotions reported by investors who had benefited and been exploited and report the details of Welch's t-test comparisons in Supplementary Material.

Figure 4 display bubble plots of investor emotion intensity and signal value of promise. Observations are plotted with bubbles, where the relative size indicates the proportion of observations at a given point. Table 3 reports results of estimating linear regression models where the dependent variable is intensity of a specific emotion (angry, disgusted, aggravated, frustrated, appreciative, content, cheerful, happy) and the independent variable is signal value. We find that investor emotions are predicted by signal value of promise.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. Bubble plots of investors' emotions and Signal value.

TABLE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Table 3. Regression of investors' emotions on signal value.

Similarly, Figure 5 displays bubble plots of investor emotion intensity and ROI. Table 4 reports results of estimating linear regression models where the dependent variable is intensity of a specific emotion (angry, disgusted, aggravated, frustrated, appreciative, content, cheerful, happy) and the independent variable is ROI. We find that investor emotions are predicted by ROI. This leads us to our second result:

FIGURE 5
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 5. Bubble plots of investors' emotions and ROI.

TABLE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Table 4. Regression of investors' emotions on ROI.

Result 2: Trustees' demonstrations of trustworthiness in game 1, by signal value of promise and ROI, predict investors' subsequent emotions.

Predictive Emotions

Trustees: spontaneous messaging behaviors predicted by emotions

Using regression analysis, we evaluated the effects of trustees' emotional reactions to game 1 on measures of their spontaneous re-affirmative and remedial behaviors (sending a message with content, the word count sent, and inclusion of a spontaneous apology). Table 5 reports how the likelihood of message (i.e., whether or not they sent a message with content) depends on different emotions. We also controlled for the trustee signal value, as a broken promise may have been a prime motivator for sending messages with content. Nevertheless, trustees' feelings of pride showed a significant positive relationship predicting message (p = 0.027), explaining 2.7% of variance in message. Trustees feeling believable, guilt, or ashamed were not predictive of message.

TABLE 5
www.frontiersin.org

Table 5. Regression of message on trustees' emotions.

Table 6 reports how the message word count depends on different emotions, as well as the trustee signal value. We used a hurdle model, described by Cameron and Trivedi (1998), since the process of generating zero values (i.e., no words) is likely to be different from the process of generating positive values. Trustees' pride showed a significant negative relationship (p < 0.001), while feeling believable as well as feelings of guilt and shame showed a significant positive relationship (p = 0.010, p < 0.001 and p < 0.001), with word count. Next, we estimated a regression to evaluate the combined effects of the above four emotional reactions on message word count. We can reject the hypothesis that all four emotions (specification 5 in Table 6) have no effect on word count (X2 = 62.20, p < 0.001, df = 4). As a set, the four emotions predicted 5.5% of the variance in message word count.

TABLE 6
www.frontiersin.org

Table 6. Regression of word count on trustees' emotions.

Next, Table 7 reports logistic regression analyses evaluating the effects of trustee emotional reactions to game 1 on spontaneous apology. Trustees' feelings of pride did not show a significant relationship predicting apology. On the other hand, trustees feeling believable showed a significant negative relationship (p = 0.019) while feelings of guilt and shame showed a significant positive relationship (p = 0.000 and p = 0.005) predicting apology. Next, we estimated a logit model to evaluate the combined effects of the above four emotional reactions on likelihood of apology. We can reject the hypothesis that all four emotions (specification 5 in Table 7) have no effect on the likelihood of apology (X2 = 19.56, p < 0.001, df = 4). The Cox and Snell R2 indicates that together the four emotions explain 41.8% of the apology variance.

TABLE 7
www.frontiersin.org

Table 7. Regression of apology on trustees' emotions.

Result 3: Trustees' emotions' predict their subsequent messaging behavior such as issuing messages with content, with longer word count, and with apology.

Investors: trust re-extension predicted by emotions

In this section we evaluate whether investors' trust re-extension in game 2 was predicted by their emotional reactions to game 1 and by measures of spontaneous re-affirmative or remedial messaging behavior demonstrated after game 1.

Table 8 reports logistic regression analyses evaluating the effects of trustee emotional reactions to game 1 on trust re-extension in game 2. We also include one of several measures of messaging behaviors (i.e., message, word count, or apology) that investors were targeted by, as well as the trustee signal value from game 1 and new promises (specifically, the returned amount promised) in game 2. In estimating these models, we do not consider a model with multiple measures of messaging behaviors because it would introduce multicollinearity20.

TABLE 8
www.frontiersin.org

Table 8. Regression of trust re-extension on investors' emotions.

We can reject the hypothesis that all eight emotions in specification (1) of Table 8 have no effect on the likelihood of trust re-extension (X2 = 21.54, p = 0.005, df = 8, Cox Snell R2 = 0.178). Overall, it appears that the most important emotion predicting trust re-extension is the experience of frustration. Specification (2) of Table 8 considers these emotions, as well as the trustee game 1 signal value and new promises in game 2 to predict trust re-extension (X2 = 24.06, p = 0.007, df = 10, Cox Snell R2 = 0.203). The change in R2 between specification (2) and specification (1) indicates that signal value and new promises explain an additional 2.5% of the variance. Specification (3) of Table 8 additionally considers message to predict trust re-extension (X2 = 27.43, p = 0.004, df = 11, Cox Snell R2 = 0.288). The change in R2 between specification (3) and specification (2) indicates that message explains an additional 8.5% of the variance. Similar conclusions can be drawn for specification (4) and specification (5).

Result 4: Investors' emotions, trustees' messaging targeting investors, and the signal value of game 1 promise predict subsequent game 2 trust re-extension.

Trustees: signal value and ROI in game 2 predicted by emotions

In this section we evaluate whether trustees' emotional reactions to game 1 are predictive of game 2 demonstrations of trustworthiness (signal value and ROI in game 2).

For previously trusted trustees who were re-extended trust again in game 2, we estimated linear regression models, reported in Tables 9A,B, where the dependent variable is the signal value of game 2 promise (the difference between game 2 return and promise) and the independent variables are the trustee emotional reactions to game 1 (pride, believability, guilt, shame), as well as the signal value in game 1 (to control for individual effects). Table 9A uses a sub-sample of game 1 promise keepers and Table 9B uses a sub-sample of game 1 promise breakers. There are two interesting results that emerge from comparing these two tables. First, the signal value in game 1 and the signal value in game 2 are positively correlated for promise breakers (Table 9A) and negatively correlated for promise keepers (Table 9B). Second, it appears that emotions play a more important role in regulating the subsequent behavior of promise keepers than promise breakers. Table 9B shows that trustees feelings of pride in game 1 is positively correlated with signal value in game 2, trustees feelings of shame is negatively correlated with signal value in game 2.

TABLE 9A
www.frontiersin.org

Table 9A. Regression of game 2 Signal Value on promise breaking trustees' emotions.

TABLE 9B
www.frontiersin.org

Table 9B. Regression of game 2 Signal Value on promise keeping trustees' emotions.

Next, we estimated linear regression models, reported in Tables 10A,B, where the dependent variable is game 2 ROI (game 2 return divided by investment) and the independent variables are the trustee emotional reactions to game 1, as well as game 1 ROI (to control for individual effects). Table 10A uses a sub-sample of game 1 promise keepers and Table 10B uses a sub-sample of game 1 promise breakers. The only significant emotion predicting ROI is shame experienced by promise keepers (Table 10B).

TABLE 10A
www.frontiersin.org

Table 10A. Regression of game 2 ROI on promise breaking trustees' emotions.

TABLE 10B
www.frontiersin.org

Table 10B. Regression of game 2 ROI on promise keeping trustees' emotions.

Result 5: Trustees' emotions predict their subsequent demonstrations of trustworthiness such as signal value and ROI in game 2.

Discussion

Emotional experiences reported by our participants explain as much as 30.1% of their subsequent behavior. That the studied emotions did not predict more of the observed variance in messaging or trust re-extension may be a consequence of the unexplained variance in reported experiences of emotions. Our model based on game 1 antecedents explained between 20 and 47% of the variance in reports of each of the 12 emotional states studied, with more variance explained for the negative emotion states that were generally experienced with lower intensity. Below we consider whether some of the variance in emotional reports might be explained by differing interpretations of the emotion labels, design limitations of the survey instrument, or deliberately compromised reporting fidelity.

People who are asked to rate single emotions may not be able to accurately describe their emotional states (Ellsworth and Tong, 2006) if emotion experiences are more often and accurately described with multiple words (Izard, 1977), or with different words among different people. While we acknowledge that language could present problems for this research and have no controls, the success of previous research on self-reported emotions in conjunction with experimental games (Ketelaar and Au, 2003; Hopfensitz and Reuben, 2009) gave us encouragement in using our instrument to pursue measures of self-reported emotions following an economic game.

Data quality could also have been affected if our stimulus primed participants to experience specific emotions (e.g., as a consequence of experimenter demand) or if they were incentivized to make untruthful reports. Demand effects to provide inflated reports of the emotional states specifically studied in this report is unlikely because we surveyed a larger set of 20 emotional states and did not reveal the subset of emotional states that we were particularly interested in analyzing. Another concern is that if participants did not view the emotion survey as “incentive compatible,” they may have been motivated to answer untruthfully. A meta-review by Camerer and Hogarth (1999) concludes that there is no clear evidence that additional financial incentives would improve the quality of responses in a simple survey task like ours. In fact, for short tasks like these surveys that people are known to voluntarily complete without problem (because they have sufficient intrinsic motivation to do so), an attempt at increasing participation via financial incentives often “backfires” with counter-intentional effects (e.g., Mellstrom and Johannesson, 2008). Nevertheless, wary of the possibility that participants may have been incentivized to use efficiency tactics to expediently complete the survey (such as by quickly marking all responses the same), we reviewed our data and found no cases of such behavior.

Conclusion

In this study we examined how participants who were given no indication of opportunity for subsequent interactions, experienced emotions after participating in a trust game, and how such emotions influenced subsequent behaviors when another opportunity for trust-based exchange unexpectedly arose. We found that emotions triggered by trust-based interaction outcomes are predictable and also predict subsequent messaging, apology, trust re-extension, and demonstrated trustworthiness. These findings advance our understanding of human behavior and they contribute to several areas of research.

First, our study provides support for the recalibrational theory of emotions. According to this theory, new information about outcomes triggers emotions, and, when experienced, these emotions recalibrate the system regulating one's propensity for subsequent behavior. In support of this theory, we find that positive emotions experienced after successful trust-based interaction motivate the investor to trust the trustee's cheap signals and re-extend trust, and motivate the beneficent, promise keeper trustees to issue shorter re-affirmative messages (word count M = 6.33, SD = 10.970)21 and demonstrate more trustworthiness. Alternatively, a trustee's negative emotional reaction to acting untrustworthy (breaking a promise and exploiting the investor), motivates remedial efforts like longer messages (word count M = 19.06, SD = 19.031) and apology targeting the affected investor.

Second, our study provides an explanation for why “cheap-talk” (i.e., communication not necessarily affecting incentives, Farrell and Rabin, 1996) is produced despite normative prediction, and why these kinds of messages are often effective. Though cheap-to-produce signals are not guaranteed to be reliable on their own and thus unexpected to persuade receivers (Grafen, 1990; Zahavi, 1993), they are frequently used by humans in the form of spoken or written words to negotiate trust between individuals with conflicting interests (Lachmann et al., 2001). Our study suggests that cheap-to-produce messages are reliable because they are influence by predictable emotions in reliable ways. For example, we find that the predicted positive emotional responses by trustees decrease the likelihood of apology and the length of message. On the other hand, predicted negative emotional responses increase the likelihood of apology and the length of message. Not only do emotions predict the use of cheap-to-produce re-affirmative and remedial messages, but they also predict the subsequent behavior of trustees. In principal, investors who anticipate or have access to the dynamics of these emotional responses and communicative intentions should be able to reliably predict the behavior of trustees based on their messages.

Finally, our study shows that remedial behaviors (spontaneous messaging with apology) can facilitate the rebuilding of damaged trust, with emotions guiding behavioral propensities. This is an important finding, given that breaches of trust are a common problem in social and economic relationships, and corporate life (Robinson and Rousseau, 1994; Barnett, 2003).

For the past couple millennia scholars have recognized that emotions indeed matter in our everyday lives, but have argued over issues of whether and how emotions guide behavior. Much progress has been made toward understanding how emotions are triggered, and what their effects are on behavior. Our study contributes to this discussion by providing evidence that trust-based interaction outcomes trigger emotions in predictable ways that, in turn, influence our propensity toward subsequent behaviors. One drawback of our study is that we elicited emotions using self-reports. Future research can overcome this limitation by focusing on objective neurological, physiological, and behavioral measures of emotional states.

Author Contributions

For inspiration to pursue this study, we thank John Dickhaut. For helpful comments, we thank the associate editor, three anonymous referees, Hilly Kaplan, Greg Bryant, and participants at the Workshop on Communication in Games (at the University of Zurich), the Human Behavior and Evolution Society annual meeting (in Montpellier, France), the Center for Evolutionary Psychology (at UC Santa Barbara), the John Dickhaut Memorial Conference (at Chapman University), and the Association for Religion, Economics and Culture annual meeting (at Chapman University). We would also like to thank the Economic Science Institute at Chapman University for funding this research.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Supplementary Material

The Supplementary Material for this article can be found online at: http://www.frontiersin.org/Journal/10.3389/fnbeh.2014.00401/abstract

Footnotes

1. ^A number of other behavioral economic studies have also used veiled designs where interacting participants are unaware of opportunity for repeated interaction(s) that will later be made available (e.g., see Binmore et al., 1985; Burnham et al., 2000; Ellingsen et al., 2010; Gambetta and Székely, 2014). Ellingsen et al. (2010, p. 96) discuss why the veiled design avoiding deception by commission does not violate the non-deception norm in behavioral economic experiments and why withholding procedural information may serve to limit undesirable experimenter demand. Nevertheless, because there is no clear agreement among economists as to what kinds of deception are taboo (see survey results by Krawczyk, 2013 and discussion by Wilson, 2014), deception by omission remains a potential concern with our design. Veiled designs may create negative externality in that the next time participants return to the laboratory to participate in other studies, they may question whether they should anticipate unannounced tasks or interactions, unless the instructions explicitly exclude such a possibility (see also Davis and Holt, 1993, pp. 23–24; Wilson, 2014). It is unlikely that our design produced these externalities, however, as we followed the procedural norm for conducting research with our participant pool by specifying the expected session duration, making a clear statement about the experimental game which was the final one in the session, and indicating when payments would be issued. We discuss in the design section how future studies using veiled designs can make improvements over ours to avoid omitting important details—namely, whether subsequent tasks are scheduled as part of the session.

2. ^While transactions with strangers may have been full of danger, mistrust, and exploitation for much of human evolutionary history (Diamond, 1997; Bowles, 1998), at least more recently, since the 19th century, as modern market society and per capita income have grown (Clark, 2008), the norm of exchange has moved from more exclusively personal to more anonymous (North, 1990). Market proliferation, in turn, has reinforced learning of the notion that trust in strangers brings benefits, resulting in greater trustworthiness (Henrich et al., 2001, 2010; Zak and Knack, 2001; Al-Ubaydli et al., 2013).

3. ^McNally and Tanner (2011) speculated that under conditions of “an unforgiving Machiavellian society,” one-shot cooperation is most likely to evolve.

4. ^As suggested by the phrase “… fool me twice, shame on me,” there may be stronger hedonic costs to being a targeted victim of repeated deception, than are experienced after being a first-time victim.

5. ^In this study we focus on 12 emotions that had previously been shown to be affected by trust-based exchange outcomes (Schniter and Shields, 2013; Schniter et al., 2014). However, to avoid demand effects that might result by focusing participants only on the 12 emotions of interest to our study, and to limit post-rationalization that might result from inducing a more limited focus, we presented subjects with a larger number of 20 emotions. This set of 20 emotions is frequently used in versions of the one-dimensional Positive and Negative Affect Scale (PANAS), a self-report measure of positively and negatively valenced affect state activations developed by Watson et al. (1988) that has been demonstrated across large non-clinical samples to be a reliable and valid measure of these states (Crawford and Henry, 2004).

6. ^Human psychological adaptations for sociality likely evolved under a selective regime characterized by repeated interactions among known others (Kelly, 1995).

7. ^Messaging is often an option (i.e., not compulsory). When optional, we expect people to tradeoff costs and benefits. Messaging may not be chosen for a variety of reasons including: to minimize cognitive effort, in an attempt to manage impressions, to save time, to pursue alternative opportunities that otherwise might be forgone.

8. ^Despite being difficult to control, people regularly make efforts to control their experience of emotions and the effects of those emotions on decision making processes (Gross, 2002). Indeed, it has been shown that an individual's ability to effectively control their emotions has implications for their decision making processes under uncertain conditions (Heilman et al., 2010). While individual differences in degree of emotional regulation likely explain some variance in the behaviors that we explore with this study, our recalibrational model is not a model of individual differences. Rather, we study the different kinds of emotional adaptations that should have reliably predictable directional effects among all people.

9. ^ Schniter et al. (2014) also collected data on emotional reactions to trust-based interaction outcomes using an emotional status survey with multiple emotion items. They reported floor effects with some of their items: where participants indicated experiencing the emotion very little or not at all. However, other emotions in their study showed strong responsiveness to trust-game outcomes, and based on those results they suggested that future researchers consider investigating appreciation, happiness, pride, frustration, anger, and guilt: a selected set with balanced valance that is representative of the varieties of functions described by their recalibration model of emotions in trust-based interaction. We chose to study those six emotions in addition to another six which we expected to be roughly synonymous and therefore similarly activated: cheerfulness (often concomitant with appreciation), contentment (often concomitant with happiness), believability (often concomitant with pride), aggravation (often concomitant with frustration), disgust (often concomitant with anger), and shame (concomitant with guilt when the offender's culpability is known).

10. ^A few neuroeconomic studies have shown evidence of neural correlates of interaction behaviors in ultimatum games (Sanfey et al., 2003) and trust games (Aimone et al., 2014) that may correspond to emotional experiences (e.g., see Takahashi et al., 2004) but have not provided direct measures of whether emotions were actually experienced. Because physiological measures are often incapable of detecting social emotions (Adolphs, 2002), self-reports may provide the best, if not only, direct measures of social emotions (Hopfensitz and Reuben, 2009).

11. ^Though we failed to provide information at the outset of our session indicating our intent to provide a repeated trust game opportunity, we provided participants a reasonable indication of expected total duration for the session to which they were recruited, and we made no misleading or counterfactual statements. As such, our procedure does not qualify as the more typical form of experimental deception (i.e., by commission of lies or exaggerations). Nevertheless, future studies using similar veiled approaches can improve on our design by more explicitly clarifying from the outset that a multi-stage approach is planned. As suggested by the editor, a veiled design could avoid use of the word “experiment” in describing a single stage and more transparently explain to participants something like, “The session consists of three stages. Now you will receive the instructions of stage 1. After completion of stage 1, there will be a stage 2 for which you will receive a new set of instructions. Finally, following completion of stage 2 there will be a final stage 3 for which you will receive a new set of instructions.”

12. ^We were motivated to see how people deal with trust re-extension dilemmas that were not explicitly anticipated as a consequence of certain expectations (for repeated interaction) but arise through a surprise unveiling. This required us to first examine trust-based interaction behaviors carried out by procedurally naïve individuals from behind the veil of ignorance.

13. ^Of the 20 emotions surveyed, we later focus predictions and analyses on a positive subset (appreciation, contentment, cheerfulness, happiness) and a negative subset (anger, disgust, aggravation, frustration) among investors (who might have been benefited or exploited and had their trust assured or damaged), and a positive subset (pride, believability) and a negative subset (guilt, shame) among trustees (who might have been beneficent or opportunist and kept or broken their promises).

14. ^The instructions for coders, details about how they were paid, and their earning from the incentivized task are reported in Schniter et al. (2013).

15. ^We use a standard approach from content analysis methodology to calculate Cohen's Kappa inter-rater agreement coefficient (Cohen, 1960; Krippendorff, 2004). Kappa values between 0.41 and 0.60 are considered “Moderate” agreement, and those above 0.60 indicate “Substantial” agreement (Landis and Koch, 1977).

16. ^These separate effects might come about as a result of reactions to two distinct phenomena: one being the abuse of language (e.g., issuing a deceptive promise), and the second being the imposition of economic harm (returning less than invested). These two phenomenon are not necessarily related: deceptive promises can be made by trustees providing positive ROIs (observed in our sample), just as it is possible for promise keeping trustees to provide negative ROIs (unobserved in our sample).

17. ^We suspect that investor emotional reactions to trustee re-affirmative and remedial behaviors would also affect our model, however we did not survey emotional reactions to either received messages or game 2 promises and are therefore unable to account for their partial effects. Our model characterizes cooperation problems resulting from certain game interaction outcomes as discrete and binary (e.g., a promise is either kept or broken), and expects the set of recalibrational emotions they trigger to be distinct (promoting either re-assuring or remedial messaging, respectively). As such, we evaluate reports of emotional states and behavioral differences between naturally-formed groups (e.g., promise keeper vs. promise breaker trustees, beneficent vs. opportunist trustees, etc.) using two-sample (Welch's) t-tests for equal means where appropriate.

18. ^Moderately high reliability of internal consistency in PANAS similar to ours has been reported by Watson et al. (1988) and others (e.g., Mehrabian, 1998; Roesch, 1998; Kausel and Connolly, 2014).

19. ^ We refer to reports of proud, believable, guilty, ashamed, angry, disgusted, aggravated, frustrated, appreciative, content, cheerful, and happy emotional states.

20. ^Message, word count, and apology are inter-related: whether or not there is a message (with content) is related to word count; whether or not there is apology is related to word count and to message.

21. ^Space precludes a full content analysis, but cursory inspection reveals that these messages tend to be re-affirmative—calling attention to the successful exchange and intention to repeat it. Examples include “teamwork!,” “same deal.,” “same as last time:),” “we're a good pair. I don't know what else to say haha.,” “same thing?,” “lets do this!,” “Pleasure doing business with you,” “I will keep it equal like last time,” “Let's just do the same transfer again,” “Let's do the same… It worked and we both made some money!!!,” “Same deal as before sounds about right, in my opinion,” “Let's do the same thing, that way we both get the max amount of money,” “Same thing again. We both benefit.,” “I like the way we did it last time, it works out nicely for both of us and it's fair:) Thanks for being great!,” “Heyo- happy to work with you again ¶ and do the same thing.,” “well we worked together so far- want to do it again? at least we'll both make more than $5.” Interested readers are encouraged to further examine the message content in Supplementary Material.

References

Adolphs, R. (2002). Recognizing emotion from facial expressions: psychological and neurological mechanisms. Behav. Cogn. Neurosci. Rev. 1, 21–61. doi: 10.1177/1534582302001001003

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Aimone, J. A., Houser, D., and Weber, B. (2014). Neural signatures of betrayal aversion: an fMRI study of trust. Proc. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 281, 20132127. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2013.2127

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Algoe, S., Haidt, J., and Gable, S. (2008). Beyond reciprocity: gratitude and relationships in everyday life. Emotion 8, 425–429. doi: 10.1037/1528-3542.8.3.425

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Al-Ubaydli, O., Houser, D., Nye, J., Paganelli, M. P., and Pan, X. S. (2013). The causal effect of market priming on trust: an experimental investigation using randomized control. PLoS ONE 8:e55968. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0055968

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Balliet, D., and Van Lange, P. A. (2012). Trust, conflict, and cooperation: a meta-analysis. Psychol. Bull. 139, 2013, 1090–1112. doi: 10.1037/a0030939

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Barnett, M. (2003). “Unringing the bell: can industries reverse unfavorable institutional shifts triggered by their own mistakes?” in Southern Management Association Conference Proceedings, 800–806.

Google Scholar

Baumeister, R. F., Stillwell, A. M., and Heatherton, T. F. (1994). Guilt: an interpersonal approach. Psychol. Bull. 115, 243–267. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.115.2.243

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ben-Ner, A., and Putterman, L. (2009). Trust, communication and contracts: an experiment. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 70, 106–121. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2009.01.011

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ben-Ner, A., Putterman, L., and Ren, T. (2011). Lavish Returns on cheap talk: non-binding communication in a trust experiment. J. Soc. Econ. 40, 1–13. doi: 10.1016/j.socec.2010.09.009

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Berg, J., Dickhaut, J., and McCabe, K. (1995). Trust, reciprocity, and social history. Games Econ. Behav. 10, 122–142. doi: 10.1006/game.1995.1027

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Binmore, K., Shaked, A., and Sutton, J. (1985). Testing noncooperative bargaining theory: a preliminary study. Am. Econ. Rev. 75, 1178–1180.

Google Scholar

Boero, R., Bravo, G., Castellani, M., and Squazzoni, F. (2009). Reputational cues in repeated trust games. J. Soc. Econ. 38, 871–877 doi: 10.1016/j.socec.2009.05.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bohnet, I., and Frey, B. S. (1999). The sound of silence in prisoner's dilemma and dictator games. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 38, 43–57. doi: 10.1016/S0167-2681(98)00121-8

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Boone, R. T., and Buck, R. (2003). Emotional expressivity and trustworthiness: the role of nonverbal behavior in the evolution of cooperation. J. Nonverbal Behav. 27, 163–182. doi: 10.1023/A:1025341931128

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Bowles, S. (1998). Endogenous preferences: the cultural consequences of markets and other economic institutions. J. Econ. Lit. 36, 75–111.

Google Scholar

Bryant, G. A., and Barrett, H. C. (2008). Vocal emotion recognition across disparate cultures. J. Cogn. Cult. 8, 135–148. doi: 10.1163/156770908X289242

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Buchan, N. R., Croson, R., and Johnson, E. J. (2006). Let's get personal: an international examination of the influence of communication, culture, and social distance on other regarding preferences. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 60, 373–398. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2004.03.017

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Burnham, T., McCabe, K., and Smith, V. L. (2000). Friend-or-foe intentionality priming in an extensive form trust game. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 43, 57–73. doi: 10.1016/S0167-2681(00)00108-6

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Byrne, R., and Whiten, A. (eds.). (1988). Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect in Monkeys, Apes, and Humans. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Camerer, C., and Hogarth, R. (1999). The effects of financial incentives in experiments: a review and capital-labor production framework. J. Risk Uncertain. 19, 7–42. doi: 10.1023/A:1007850605129

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cameron, A. C., and Trivedi, P. K. (1998). Regression Analysis of Count Data. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511814365

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Capra, C. M. (2004). Mood-driven behavior in strategic interactions. Am. Econ. Rev. 94, 367–372. doi: 10.1257/0002828041301885

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cason, T. N., Sheremeta, R. M., and Zhang, J. (2012). Communication and efficiency in competitive coordination games. Games Econ. Behav. 76, 26–43. doi: 10.1016/j.geb.2012.05.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Charness, G., and Dufwenberg, M. (2006). Promises and partnership. Econometrica 74, 1579–1601. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0262.2006.00719.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Clark, G. (2008). A Farewell to Alms: a Brief Economic History of the World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Google Scholar

Cochard, F., Nguyen Van, P., and Willinger, M. (2004). Trusting behavior in a repeated investment game. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 55, 31–44. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2003.07.004

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cohen, J. (1960). A coefficient of agreement for nominal scales. Educ. Psychol. Meas. 20, 37–46. doi: 10.1177/001316446002000104

CrossRef Full Text

Crawford, J. R., and Henry, J. D. (2004). The Positive and Negative Affect Schedule (PANAS): construct validity, measurement properties and normative data in a large non-clinical sample. Br. J. Clin. Psychol. 43, 243–265. doi: 10.1348/0144665031752934

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Darwin, C. (1872/1965). Expression of Emotions in Man and Animals. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Google Scholar

Davis, D. D., and Holt, C. A. (1993). Experimental Economics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Google Scholar

Dawes, R. M., and Thaler, R. H. (1988). Anomalies: cooperation. J. Econ. Perspect. 2, 187–197. doi: 10.1257/jep.2.3.187

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

de Hooge, I. E., Zeelenberg, M., and Breugelmans, S. M. (2011). A functionalist account of shame-induced behaviour. Cogn. Emot. 25, 939–946. doi: 10.1080/02699931.2010.516909

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Delton, A. W., Krasnow, M. M., Tooby, J., and Cosmides, L. (2011). The evolution of direct reciprocity under uncertainty can explain human generosity in one-shot encounters. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 108, 13335–13340. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1102131108

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Diamond, J. (1997). Guns, Germs, and Steel: the Fates of Human Societies. New York, NY: Norton

Google Scholar

Dunn, J., and Schweitzer, M. (2005). Feeling and believing: the influence of emotion on trust. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 88, 736–748. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.88.5.736

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ekman, P., Sorenson, E. R., and Friesen, W. V. (1969). Pan-cultural elements in facial displays of emotions. Science 164, 86–88. doi: 10.1126/science.164.3875.86

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ellingsen, T., and Johannesson, M. (2004). Promises, threats, and fairness. Econ. J. 114, 397–420. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2004.00214.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ellingsen, T., Johannesson, M., Tjøtta, S., and Torsvik, G. (2010). Testing guilt aversion. Games Econ. Behav. 68, 95–107. doi: 10.1016/j.geb.2009.04.021

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ellsworth, P. C., and Tong, M. W. (2006). What does it mean to be angry at yourself? Categories, appraisals, and the problem of language. Emotion 6, 572–586. doi: 10.1037/1528-3542.6.4.572

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Farrell, J., and Rabin, M. (1996). Cheap talk. J. Econ. Perspect. 10, 103–118. doi: 10.1257/jep.10.3.103

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text

Fehr, E., and Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature 415, 137–140. doi: 10.1038/415137a

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Fehr, E., and Henrich, J. (2003). “Is strong reciprocity a maladaptation? On the evolutionary foundations of human altruism,” in Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation, ed P. Hammerstein (Cambridge, MA: MIT press), 55–82.

Google Scholar

Fessler, D. M. (1999). “Toward an understanding of the universality of second order emotions,” in Beyond Nature or Nurture: Biocultural Approaches to the Emotions, ed A. Hinton (New York, NY: Cambridge University Press), 75–116.

Google Scholar

Fessler, D. M. (2001). “Emotions and cost-benefit assessment: the role of shame and self-esteem in risk taking,” in Bounded Rationality: the Adaptive Toolbox, eds G. Gigerenzer and R. Selten (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 191–214.

Google Scholar

Fischbacher, U., and Utikal, V. (2013). On the acceptance of apologies. Games Econ. Behav. 82, 592–608. doi: 10.1016/j.geb.2013.09.003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Frank, R. H. (2004). “Introducing moral emotions into models of rational choice,” in Feelings and Emotions. The Amsterdam Symposium, eds A. S. R. Manstead, N. H. Frijda, and A. Fischer (Cambridge: University Press), 422–440. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511806582.024

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Frank, R. L. (1988). Passions Within Reason: the Strategic Role of the Emotions. New York, NY: Norton.

Google Scholar

Frijda, N. H. (1986). The Emotions. Cambridge: University Press.

Google Scholar

Gambetta, D., and Székely, A. (2014). Signs and (counter) signals of trustworthiness. J. Econ. Behav. Org. 106, 281–297. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2014.07.009

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Grafen, A. (1990). Biological signals as handicaps. J. Theor. Biol. 144, 517–546. doi: 10.1016/S0022-5193(05)80088-8

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Gross, J. J. (2002). Emotion regulation: affective, cognitive, and social consequences. Psychophysiology 39, 281–291. doi: 10.1017/S0048577201393198

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Haselton, M. G., and Ketelaar, T. (2006). “Irrational emotions or emotional wisdom? The evolutionary psychology of emotions and behavior,” in Hearts and Minds: Affective Influences on Social Cognition and Behavior, ed J. P. Forgas (New York, NY: Psychology Press), 21–40.

Google Scholar

Heilman, R. M., Crişan, L. G., Houser, D., Miclea, M., and Miu, A. C. (2010). Emotion regulation and decision making under risk and uncertainty. Emotion 10, 257. doi: 10.1037/a0018489

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., Gintis, H., et al. (2001). In search of homo economicus: behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies. Am. Econ. Rev. 91, 73–78. doi: 10.1257/aer.91.2.73

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Henrich, J., Ensminger, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, A., et al. (2010). Markets, religion, community size, and the evolution of fairness and punishment. Science 327, 1480–1484. doi: 10.1126/science.1182238

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hirshleifer, J. (1987). On the Emotions as Guarantors of Threats and Promises. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Ho, B. (2012). Apologies as signals: with evidence from a trust game. Manage. Sci. 58, 141–158. doi: 10.1287/mnsc.1110.1410

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Hopfensitz, A., and Reuben, E. (2009). The importance of emotions for the effectiveness of social punishment. Econ. J. 119, 1534–1559. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2009.02288.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Houser, D., and Xiao, E. (2011). Classification of natural language messages using a coordination game. Exp. Econ. 14, 1–14. doi: 10.1007/s10683-010-9254-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Humphrey, N. (1976). “The social function of intellect,” in Machiavellian Intelligence, eds R. Byrne and A. Whiten, Reprinted in (1988) (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 13–26.

Izard, C. E. (1977). Human Emotions. New York, NY: Plenum. doi: 10.1007/978-1-4899-2209-0

CrossRef Full Text

Kaplan, H., Schniter, E., Smith, V., and Wilson, B. (2012). Risk and the evolution of human exchange. Proc. R. Soc. Biol. Sci. 279, 2930–2935. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2011.2614

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kausel, E. E., and Connolly, T. (2014). Do people have accurate beliefs about the behavioral consequences of incidental emotions? Evidence from trust games. J. Econ. Psychol. 42, 96–111. doi: 10.1016/j.joep.2014.02.002

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kelly, R. L. (1995). The Foraging Spectrum. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press.

Keltner, D., and Kring, A. M. (1998). Emotion, social function, and psychopathology. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 2, 320–342. doi: 10.1037/1089-2680.2.3.320

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kerr, N., and Kaufman-Gilliland, C. (1994). Communication, commitment, and cooperation in social dilemmas. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 66, 513–529. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.66.3.513

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ketelaar, T., and Au, W. T. (2003). The effects of guilty feelings on the behavior of uncooperative individuals in repeated social bargaining games: an Affect-as-information interpretation of the role of emotion in social interaction. Cogn. Emot. 17, 429–453. doi: 10.1080/02699930143000662

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Kiyonari, T., Tanida, S., and Yamagishi, T. (2000). Social exchange and reciprocity: confusion or a heuristic? Evol. Hum. Behav. 21, 411–427. doi: 10.1016/S1090-5138(00)00055-6

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Krasnow, M. M., Delton, A. W., Tooby, J., and Cosmides, L. (2013). Meeting now suggests we will meet again: implications for debates on the evolution of cooperation. Sci. Rep. 3:1747. doi: 10.1038/srep01747

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Krawczyk, M. (2013). Delineating Deception in Experimental Economics: Researchers' and Subjects' Views, Faculty of Economic Sciences Working Paper. Warsaw: University of Warsaw.

Google Scholar

Krippendorff, K. (2004). Content Analysis: an Introduction to its Methodology. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.

Lachmann, M., Számadó, S., and Bergstrom, C. T. (2001). Cost and conflict in animal signals and human language. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 98, 13189–13194. doi: 10.1073/pnas.231216498

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Landis, J. R., and Koch, G. (1977). An application of hierarchical kappa-type statistics in the assessment of majority agreeement among multiple observers. Biometrics 33, 363–374. doi: 10.2307/2529786

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Masclet, D., Noussair, C., Tucker, S., and Villeval, M. (2003). Monetary and non-monetary punishment in the voluntary contributions mechanism. Am. Econ. Rev. 93, 366–380. doi: 10.1257/000282803321455359

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McCabe, K. A., Rigdon, M. L., and Smith, V. L. (2003). Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 52, 267–275. doi: 10.1016/S0167-2681(03)00003-9

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McCullough, M. E., Kilpatrick, S. D., Emmons, R. A., and Larson, D. B. (2001). Is gratitude a moral affect? Psychol. Bul. 127, 249–266. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.127.2.249

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

McElreath, R., Clutton-Brock, T. H., Fehr, E., Fessler, D. M. T., Hagen, E. H., Hammerstein, et al. (2003). “Group report: the role of cognition and emotion in cooperation,” in Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation, ed P. Hammerstein (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 125–152.

Google Scholar

McNally, L., and Tanner, C. J. (2011). Flexible strategies, forgiveness, and the evolution of generosity in one-shot encounters. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 108, 971–971. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1115225108

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mehrabian, A. (1998). Comparison of the PAD and PANAS as models for describing emotions and for differentiating anxiety from depression. J. Psychopathol. Behav. Assess. 19, 331–357. doi: 10.1007/BF02229025

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Mellstrom, C., and Johannesson, M. (2008). Crowding out in blood donation: was Titmuss right? J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 6, 845–863. doi: 10.1162/JEEA.2008.6.4.845

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nesse, R. M. (1990). Evolutionary explanations of emotions. Hum. Nat. 1, 261–289. doi: 10.1007/BF02733986

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

North, D. (1990). Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511808678

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Nowak, M. A., and Sigmund, K. (2005). Evolution of indirect reciprocity. Nature 437, 1291–1298. doi: 10.1038/nature04131

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Orbell, J., Dawes, R., and Kragt van de, A. (1988). Explaining discussion induced cooperation. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 54, 811–819. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.54.5.811

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., and Collins, A. (1988). The Cognitive Structure of Emotions. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511571299

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ostrom, E., and Walker, J. (2005). Trust and Reciprocity: Interdisciplinary Lessons from Experimental Research. New York, NY: Russell Sage Foundation Publications.

Google Scholar

Pennebaker, J. W., and Graybeal, A. (2001). Patterns of natural language use: disclosure, personality, and social integration. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci. 10, 90–93. doi: 10.1111/1467-8721.00123

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pillutla, M. M., and Murnighan, J. K. (1996). Unfairness, anger, and spite: emotional rejections of ultimatum offers. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 68, 208–224. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1996.0100

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Ridings, C. M., Gefen, D., and Arinze, B. (2002). Some antecedents and effects of trust in virtual communities. J. Strat. Inform. Syst. 11, 271–295. doi: 10.1016/S0963-8687(02)00021-5

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Robinson, S. L., and Rousseau, D. M. (1994). Violating the psychological contract: not the exception but the norm. J. Organ. Behav. 15, 245–259. doi: 10.1002/job.4030150306

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Roesch, S. C. (1998). Validity studies the factorial validity of trait positive affect scores: confirmatory factor analyses of unidimensional and multidimensional models. Educ. Psychol. Meas. 58, 451–466. doi: 10.1177/0013164498058003006

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rohwer, S. (1977). Status signaling in Harris sparrows: some experiments in deception. Behaviour 61, 107–129. doi: 10.1163/156853977X00504

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Rubin, J., and Brown, B. (1975). The Social Psychology of Bargaining and Negotiation. New York, NY: Academic Press.

Google Scholar

Sanfey, A. G., Rilling, J. K., Aronson, J. A., Nystrom, L. E., and Cohen, J. D. (2003). The neural basis of economic decision-making in the ultimatum game. Science 300, 1755–1758. doi: 10.1126/science.1082976

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sauter, D. A., Eisner, F., Ekman, P., and Scott, S. K. (2010). Cross-cultural recognition of basic emotions through nonverbal emotional vocalizations. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 107, 2408–2412. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0908239106

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Scher, S. J., and Darley, J. M. (1997). How effective are the things people say to apologize? Effects of the realization of the apology speech act. J. Psychol. Res. 26, 127–140. doi: 10.1023/A:1025068306386

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schniter, E., Sheremeta, R., and Shields, T. (2014). Conflicted Emotions Following Trust-based Interaction. Working Paper. Orange, CA: Chapman University, Economic Science Institute.

Google Scholar

Schniter, E., Sheremeta, R., and Sznycer, D. (2013). Building and rebuilding trust with promises and apologies. J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 94, 242–256. doi: 10.1016/j.jebo.2012.09.011

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schniter, E., and Shields, T. (2013). “Recalibrational emotions and the regulation of trust-based behaviors,” in Psychology of Trust: New Research, ed D. Gefen (New York, NY: Nova Science Publishers), 1–58.

Google Scholar

Schug, J., Matsumoto, D., Horita, Y., Yamagishi, T., and Bonnet, K. (2010). Emotional expressivity as a signal of cooperation. Evol. Hum. Behav. 31, 87–94 doi: 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2009.09.006

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Schweitzer, M., Hershey, J. C., and Bradlow, E. (2006). Promises and lies: restoring violated trust. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 101, 1–19. doi: 10.1016/j.obhdp.2006.05.005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Seabright, P. (2010). The Company of Strangers: a Natural History of Economic Life (Revised Edition). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Google Scholar

Searcy, W. A., and Nowicki, S. (2005). The Evolution of Animal Communication: Reliability and Deception in Signaling Systems. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Google Scholar

Sell, A., Tooby, J., and Cosmides, L. (2009). Formidability and the logic of human anger. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106, 15073–15078. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0904312106

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sheremeta, R. M., and Zhang, J. (2014). Three-player trust game with insider communication. Econ. Inq. 52, 576–591. doi: 10.1111/ecin.12018

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Smith, A. (1759). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Adam Smith Institute. Available online at: http://www.adamsmith.org/smith/tms/tms-index.htm

Smith, R. H., Webster, J. M., and Eyre, H. L. (2002). The role of public exposure in moral and nonmoral shame and guilt. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 83, 138–159. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.83.1.138

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sutter, M. (2009). Deception through telling the truth?! Experimental evidence from individuals and teams. Econ. J. 119, 47–60. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2008.02205.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Sznycer, D. (2010). Cognitive Adaptations for Calibrating Welfare Tradeoff Motivations, with Special Reference to the Emotion of Shame. Doctoral dissertation, University of California, Santa Barbara.

Google Scholar

Sznycer, D., Takemura, K., Delton, A. W., Sato, K., Robertson, T., Cosmides, L., et al. (2012). Cross-cultural differences and similarities in proneness to shame: an adaptationist and ecological approach. Evol. Psychol. 10, 352–370.

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | Google Scholar

Takahashi, H., Yahata, N., Koeda, M., Matsuda, T., Asai, K., and Okuboc, Y. (2004). Brain activation associated with evaluative processes of guilt and embarrassment: an fMRI study. Neuroimage 23, 967–974. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2004.07.054

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tooby, J., and Cosmides, L. (1990). The past explains the present: emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments. Ethol. Sociobiol. 11, 375–424. doi: 10.1016/0162-3095(90)90017-Z

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Tooby, J., and Cosmides, L. (2008). “The evolutionary psychology of the emotions and their relationship to internal regulatory variables,” in Handbook of Emotions, 3rd Edn., eds M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones, and L. F. Barrett (New York, NY: Guilford), 114–137.

Google Scholar

Tooby, J., Cosmides, L., Sell, A., Lieberman, D., and Sznycer, D. (2008). “Internal regulatory variables and the design of human motivation: a computational and evolutionary approach,” in Handbook of Approach and Avoidance Motivation, ed A. J. Elliot (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates), 251–271.

Google Scholar

Watson, D., Clark, L. A., and Tellegen, A. (1988). Development and validation of brief measures of positive and negative affect: the PANAS scales. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 54, 1063–1070. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.54.6.1063

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Wilson, B. J. (2014). “The meaning of deceive in experimental economic science,” in The Oxford Handbook of Professional Economic Ethics, eds G. DeMartino and D. McCloskey (New York, NY: Oxford University Press). doi: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199766635.013.013

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Xiao, E., and Houser, D. (2005). Emotion expression in human punishment behavior. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 102, 7398–7401. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0502399102

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zahavi, A. (1993). The fallacy of conventional signalling. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 340, 227–230. doi: 10.1098/rstb.1993.0061

Pubmed Abstract | Pubmed Full Text | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zak, P. J., and Knack, S. (2001). Trust and growth. Econ. J. 111, 295–321. doi: 10.1111/1468-0297.00609

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Zheng, J., Veinott, E., Bos, N., Olson, J. S., and Olson, G. M. (2002). “Trust without touch: jumpstarting long-distance trust with initial social activities,” in Proceedings of CHI (New York, NY: ACM Press), 141–146.

Google Scholar

Keywords: emotion, cheap signal, promise, apology, trust game, reciprocity, experiment

Citation: Schniter E and Sheremeta RM (2014) Predictable and predictive emotions: explaining cheap signals and trust re-extension. Front. Behav. Neurosci. 8:401. doi: 10.3389/fnbeh.2014.00401

Received: 04 July 2014; Accepted: 02 November 2014;
Published online: 20 November 2014.

Edited by:

Rosemarie Nagel, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Spain

Reviewed by:

Daniel Houser, George Mason University, USA
Verena Utikal, University of Erlangen-Nuremberg, Germany
Erte Xiao, Carnegie Mellon University, USA

Copyright © 2014 Schniter and Sheremeta. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Eric Schniter, Economic Science Institute, Chapman University, One University Drive, Orange, CA 92866, USA e-mail: eschniter@gmail.com

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.