Skip to main content

HYPOTHESIS AND THEORY article

Front. Psychiatry, 27 July 2021
Sec. Schizophrenia
This article is part of the Research Topic Hallucinations from the Perspective of Altered Experiences of Self: A Multidisciplinary Approach View all 9 articles

Computational Mechanism for the Effect of Psychosis Community Treatment: A Conceptual Review From Neurobiology to Social Interaction

  • 1Department of Psychiatry, McGill University, Montreal, QC, Canada
  • 2Department of Psychiatry, Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, CT, United States

The computational underpinnings of positive psychotic symptoms have recently received significant attention. Candidate mechanisms include some combination of maladaptive priors and reduced updating of these priors during perception. A potential benefit of models with such mechanisms is their ability to link multiple levels of explanation, from the neurobiological to the social, allowing us to provide an information processing-based account of how specific alterations in self-self and self-environment interactions result in the experience of positive symptoms. This is key to improving how we understand the experience of psychosis. Moreover, it points us toward more comprehensive avenues for therapeutic research by providing a putative mechanism that could allow for the generation of new treatments from first principles. In order to demonstrate this, our conceptual paper will discuss the application of the insights from previous computational models to an important and complex set of evidence-based clinical interventions with strong social elements, such as coordinated specialty care clinics (CSC) in early psychosis and assertive community treatment (ACT). These interventions may include but also go beyond psychopharmacology, providing, we argue, structure and predictability for patients experiencing psychosis. We develop the argument that this structure and predictability directly counteract the relatively low precision afforded to sensory information in psychosis, while also providing the patient more access to external cognitive resources in the form of providers and the structure of the programs themselves. We discuss how computational models explain the resulting reduction in symptoms, as well as the predictions these models make about potential responses of patients to modifications or to different variations of these interventions. We also link, via the framework of computational models, the patient's experiences and response to interventions to putative neurobiology.

Introduction

While positive symptoms- such as hallucinations and delusions- have not been demonstrated to be the chief determinant of functional outcomes (1), their appropriate management, for many people on the psychotic spectrum, do appear to be of significant importance in terms of quality of life, vocational functioning, and safety (24). Hallucinations and delusions may cause fear and distress, occupy a significant portion of a patient's attention and time that could be spent on other tasks, or lead to unsafe behavior such as avoiding necessary medical treatment or attempting suicide in response to command hallucinations (3). Furthermore, positive symptoms, and lack of insight into these, can impact upon the therapeutic alliance between therapists and patients (5), which could stymie efforts to address cognitive symptoms, social function, and basic needs such as shelter or routine medical care. These symptoms can also have a significant effect on a patient's view of themselves in relation to the world. For example, patients with persecutory beliefs experience significant distress when entering crowded social environments (6), which might lead to an increase in self-isolating behavior. Delusions of control might result in the distressing sense that one is not in total control of their own thoughts or actions, or that their autonomy is under assault by some outside force (7).

Most existing pharmacological treatments are designed to help reduce positive symptoms, primarily via the blockade of dopamine in the mesolimbic pathway, though especially among the atypical antipsychotics a number of other neurotransmitter pathways are affected by these medications (8). Despite years of research and drug development, however, many patients remain resistant to antipsychotic treatment (9). A major focus of recent research has been better understanding the pathophysiology of psychotic syndromes in order to design new treatments (10).

In addition, for many patients there exist a number of barriers to adherence to medication which may include: positive symptoms (11) and positive patient attitudes toward positive symptoms (12), poor insight (13), negative symptoms (11), cognitive symptoms limiting ability to obtain medications or adherence to treatment (11), medication side effects (14), or inability to afford medications, medical care, housing, or services (14). Given these complexities, as well as the host of other social and medical challenges which face patients who live with psychosis [see (15, 16)], it is no surprise that for many patients the management of positive symptoms is not a simple matter of visiting a general practitioner, picking up a prescription, and taking their medications independently at home.

To address these difficulties, the delivery of treatment to patients living with psychosis has been marked in the last few decades by the growth in use and popularity of specialized, evidence-based clinical services, such as assertive community treatment (ACT) teams (17) and coordinated specialty care (CSC) clinics for early psychosis (18). Far more than just mechanisms for the improvement of medication adherence, these services usually provide a number of “wrap-around” therapeutic benefits such as supportive and other psychotherapies, social worker support, support with ensuring access to medication, transport, and housing, vocational and educational support, coordination of care with other services, and regular followup, often occurring, in the case of ACT, in the patient's home (17, 19).

The conventional view of these programs is that they work by providing the above services in an integrated manner, ensuring that patients get access to evidence-based treatments and services that support recovery and engagement in treatment. ACT teams have indeed been shown to reduce hospitalizations (17), suggesting the services they provide may modify disease course. Furthermore, CSCs may help get patients comprehensive services during a “window of opportunity” which exists in which services may help improve patient outcomes after first episode psychosis (20). However, despite the clear and demonstrated superior outcomes and feasibility of both types of service (17, 18), there does not seem to be a clear mechanistic account of how these services produce their effect–that is, while it is clear that providing integrated services improves outcomes, why delivering services in this manner for these particular patient populations produces this effect remains an open question. This may seem trivial, in the sense that it seems obvious that providing personalized, integrated services would clearly be superior to providing one-size-fits-all, difficult to access treatment. However, as we will argue below, examining how these services are provided, and how that might interact with a hypothesized computational model of the experience of psychosis, may reveal a number of interesting possibilities for improvement of services and novel mechanistic considerations.

ACT teams and CSCs have been shown to help reduce symptom severity more than standard treatment (21, 22). While these accounts certainly explain why a patient's quality of life would improve while receiving these services—for example, a patient receiving ACT support gains a team that can help them manage their household and gain access to needed medical care and social support—they do not directly explain why a patient would have reduced symptom intensity. One possibility is that these programs assist patients in managing their lives in a manner that reduces the occurrence or impact of stressful life events, which have been shown to be significantly associated with re-hospitalization or relapse of psychotic symptoms (23); if this is true, one can ask further how we might characterize the interactions between patient and team which lead to stress reduction. Another possibility is that patients are simply taking their medications more regularly. As noted above, medication may be a necessary but in many cases insufficient part of the control of positive symptoms. In addition, Guo et al. (24) found that medication plus psychosocial support outperformed medication alone in early schizophrenia, though this result is confounded by the fact that treatment discontinuation rates were higher in the medication-only group. Perhaps the key point to be made is that, despite ACT and CSC teams varying in composition and services provided (17, 20), none of them are limited to services that simply improve medication adherence. As such, considering all of the limited evidence available, one may hypothesize that other services in addition to the provision of medication, and potentially the experience of these services, may have an important impact on symptoms. Thus, we return to the question of mechanism: how do these external programs have an impact on the internal experience of a person, and of their experience of their self in the world and in relation to their symptoms?

Examining this question requires engaging in one of the most challenging exercises in behavioral science- integrating information across levels of explanation (25), or attempting to understand how a change in social or psychological situation might affect neurobiology or vice versa. In attempting to integrate across these different levels of interpretation and analysis, it is helpful to have one common language- a set of concepts which can serve as the benchmarks for use in comparing pieces of information from different levels of inquiry. A key requirement of this common language would be that it can assist in the understanding of how the patient's self-interacts with both the external world and with positive symptoms (like hallucinations) that are often experienced as being separate from them. One such language (or perhaps more accurately, set of languages) is that of computational psychiatry (26), a discipline that seeks to understand what, precisely, the brain is trying to compute, how it implements this computation (from both a psychological and neurobiological standpoint), how these processes influence and are influenced by the environment, and how psychiatric symptoms may arise from aberrations in any number of these processes. Once one has an idea of what the brain is trying to compute, one can explore the possible ways in which the brain might implement these computations neurobiologically; one can then observe how the quantity being computed changes with a change in the environment, and then deduce what changes at the level of neurobiological implementation would be necessary to allow these changes computation to obtain. Crucially, one must be able to use this model to gain an understanding of how to tie neurobiologically implemented computations to socially-oriented clinical interactions, which in turn may shed light on the way the patient's self efficacy of specialty intervent interacts with external actors and with their symptoms.

A number of computational theories of psychosis have been proposed (27, 28). In this conceptual paper, we will select one particular theory- the active inference account (29). As we will discuss, we have selected this theory because of its enactive nature, its existing physiological validation, and the manner in which it explicitly considers the role of an agent in the context of its environment. However, the choice of theory is not the main focus of the paper, and another theory could have been chosen. Rather, the focus of the paper is to demonstrate how, using a computational theory as a framework, we can conceptualize a mechanism of action for the specialized services described above and relate this directly to potential underlying neurobiology. We will then demonstrate how experiments could be designed to test the veracity of this hypothetical mechanism of action.

Background on Active Inference and Other Computational Accounts of ACT/CSC

In this concept paper, we have chosen to focus on the active inference theory of hallucinations in order to provide the computational language we will use to investigate the potential mechanism of action of services such as ACT teams and CSCs. We begin with a brief overview of active inference. Though more substantive reviews and descriptions of its mathematical underpinnings are available (30), we instead focus here on describing active inference in a manner that will be accessible to clinicians and clinical researchers.

Active inference is a Bayesian theory (30) which, at its core, asserts that all agents (organisms acting in the world) function in a manner that aims to minimize the uncertainty in their model of the world. This uncertainty can be quantified and is often referred to as surprise or free energy (31); decreases in free energy can be projected in an approximate form, and this in turn can guide the selection of action (i.e., agents take actions which help reduce their uncertainty). The theory is one of “inference” because agents do not have access to the processes in the outer (or inner) world that cause their sensations- they must infer these causes. It is “active” because agents must use actions in order to gain new information to test their models or update them. It is Bayesian because the agent has a set of prior beliefs about the world, takes in new observations (often after acting in order to acquire said observations), and then forms new beliefs (known in Bayesian theory as posteriors). Any action—or series of actions—that an agent can take is called a policy; the set of actions or series of actions that an agent can take is called a policy space.

As a simple example, imagine you are in a dark room. You do not know anything about the room or what may be contained in it. You are, however, armed with certain prior beliefs about yourself and the way rooms are generally constructed. For example, you believe that you have a pair of eyes that require an external light source in order to see and you also believe that most rooms are equipped with a light switch. You look around and notice a pair of eyes shining in the dark. You are now in possession of a sensory observation—a pair of shining eyes—but you do not know what process in the world has caused that sensory observation—that is, to whom or what the eyes in question belong. You have several policies available to you in your policy space—for example, you could walk toward the eyes; you could stay still; you could try and find the light. Of all of these actions, turning on the light—you project—has the highest chance of reducing your uncertainty the most, and as such you select this as your policy. You proceed to find the light switch and discover that the pair of eyes belonged to a tabby cat. You then update your model of the world- the sensory observation that was the eyes was likely caused by the cat (the presence of which you again infer from your sensory observation once the light is turned on). The belief that there is a cat in the world that can cause the sensation of shining eyes in the dark becomes a posterior belief; it can at a future time serve as a prior belief. For example, if you choose to turn the light off you might expect to see the shining eyes in the dark again- all due to your now-prior belief about the cat and the sensations it can produce. It is also key to understand that policies can engender expectations about what is to be experienced. For example, if you turn on the light you expect that, in the next time step, you will experience the light filling the room and rendering objects more easy to see. In this way, policies can act as models of how one might expect our perceptions (the causes of which we must infer) to evolve over time, in response to the actions- or inaction- that one might take. In other words, policies can serve as models of how we expect the world to evolve, and in turn a policy space defines the set of possible evolutions we may consider.

There is one more key concept to understand in our simplified description of active inference- that of precisions. In the real world, not all beliefs are held with equal certainty, and not all sources of information are equally reliable. For example, if you had poor eyesight in our example above, then when the light was turned on you might be only partially certain you are seeing a cat, which in turn might influence what you end up inferring to be the cause of the shining eyes in the dark. Equally, depending on your experience with usual room construction you may have more or less certainty in the different policies available to you while you are in the dark room (i.e., if you had been transplanted from a time just before electric light switches became commonplace, you may only be somewhat certain that searching the walls of the room might reveal a switch for an electric light). These varying levels of certainty in observations, beliefs or potential courses of action are called precisions under active inference and act as coefficients in active inference equations which can be manipulated in order to alter agent behavior.

Armed with an understanding of the basic aims and computational elements present in an active inference agent, let us now turn to a discussion of how one might cause such an agent to experience positive symptoms–for example, hallucinations. In (29) we describe several situations in which this can occur. Let us imagine an agent who must infer its current state- whether it is listening to someone speaking or whether there is silence. In terms of actions it is able to speak or to listen, and it must select between a set of policies which will have it listening or speaking at different points in time. It is paired with another agent that speaks every second time-step (an arbitrary choice in this case, chosen for simplicity), and which serves as its external “world” or environment. Finally, our agent has two different precisions to consider. The first is sensory precision. This is the confidence it places in information it observes- for example, auditory information. This confidence might be a result of the integrity of the information- dipping, for example, in the case of external noise or poor transmission over internal networks, such as the reduced integrity of the arcuate facilsulus seen in schizophrenia (32); it might also be a result of how much attention- which can be formulated under active inference in terms of sensory precision- is being placed on the information (a reflection of its perceived utility), which in turn has been linked to acetylcholine signaling (33). The second is prior precision over policies, or the strength of the agent's belief in the policies in its own policy space; this certainty about actions (or lack thereof) has been linked to dopamine signaling in previous work (34).

The first way to make this agent hallucinate is to drop its sensory precision. In this situation, where it cannot use information from the environment to correct its prior beliefs, then these priors become dominant: when the agent expects to be listening to the other agent in the world (as a result of the policies it has chosen to pursue, which involve listening), it can infer that sound is present because it expects it to be- in other words, it generates the percept of sound (a hallucination) in order satisfy its prior belief in the absence of information that could be used to correct this belief. If one were next to lower the sensory precision, but not to the same degree as previously, in an agent with an elevated prior precision over policies, the agent would similarly hallucinate. In this case, the increase in certainty about priors tips the balance, leading to hallucinations when observations in the world are not reliable enough to counteract these priors. Let us examine the policy space more closely. It is possible, as we have demonstrated (29), to construct policy spaces that never result in hallucinations- in this case, because they happen to match what happens in the world perfectly. These agents do not hallucinate even if sensory precision is reduced significantly, because their expectations and what the world produces match up. This is a very fragile state, however: when the policy that matched the world is “lesioned” and removed from play, the agent is once again vulnerable to hallucination. In other words: when an agent has a healthy and expansive policy space and a normal ability to use information in the world to correct faulty prior beliefs, then hallucinations do not result. As an example, imagine an agent playing a chess game and possessing a given moveset. The agent can use any of their moves to win the game and to keep up with the environment in the game changing (as a result of the moves of the other player). If we shrink the agent's moveset and allow it only one set of moves that is consistent with winning the game, the agent can still perform well but things are fragile- change the environment (i.e., increase the unpredictability of the opponent, for example), or further decrease the moveset, and the agent will no longer be able to produce moves consistent with a valid solution to the game. In our case, the “chess game” is perception and interaction with external reality, and incorrect solutions to that game driven by a limited moveset would be hallucinations or delusions. We should also note that, in addition to priors provided by policies, maladaptive perceptual priors can also be learned over time- perhaps as a result of continuous experience of maladaptive policies; these perceptual priors could then take the place of the main prior driving generation of hallucinations (35). Reduce the functional space of policies the agent can exploit- creating an agent maladapted to the world-, increase this agent's certainty about maladaptive priors, and, finally, reduce its ability to correct these prior beliefs by referring to external information and you create an agent that hallucinates because its prior beliefs have gained dominance over the evidence it gains from the world. A further elaboration of this model which expanded it to the content of hallucinations was described in (36). Here the agent is singing a song with another agent, and may believe the song order is standard or altered (i.e., the words of the song have been moved around). It will only have hallucinations of the song out of order when it believes that the song is disordered and its sensory precision is low, robbing it of the ability to use the other agent's singing to correct its faulty prior beliefs. Agents with abnormal prior beliefs about word order in the song who are still able to use external information—that is, whose sensory precision is intact—do not hallucinate.

To summarize, one can conceptualize hallucinations—and perhaps delusions—as arising from an imbalance between prior beliefs—for example, beliefs that one should be hearing someone speaking, and that the speech will include certain content—and sensory information, where priors have won out over sensory information. There has in fact been recent experimental evidence for this “strong priors” account of hallucinations [e.g., (3739)]; though as we discuss in (40), the dialectic between “strong” or “weak” priors is likely one that can be dissolved by turning instead to a discussion of hierarchy and timing within the disease course.

The key reason for using this computational framework is that it allows for agents to actively predict the world around them and to act in that world and interact with it. Active inference can be used to model social interactions- indeed the above models explicitly describe the generation of hallucinations in a social context, where another agent is present in the world and which the hallucinating agent can interact with and try to predict. This helps us understand how a patient may interact both with their generated hallucinations- which can be experienced as an external agent- and with external actors, who can provide information that may be of use to the patient in helping them understand- and predict- the world. In addition, and as noted above, it provides a framework that can link this social level to the neurobiological level. We will now turn to a discussion of how this conceptualization might assist us in probing the underlying neurobiology before then ascending the levels of interpretation and returning to the question of the mechanism of action of programs such as ACT or CSCs.

Generative Models and Mechanisms of Psychosis

Psychiatric treatment has long depended on models of symptom development: Freud's structural model proposed that psychiatric symptoms could result from unresolved conflicts between biological drives and internalized social limitations (41); behaviorist and cognitive models attempted to ground psychiatric nosology in emerging knowledge of learning, memory, and information processing theory (42). The advent of biological psychiatry brought with it (simplistic) brain-based explanations of the roles of different neurotransmitter systems in the generation of basic psychiatric symptoms, often arising as post-hoc justifications for the use of effective treatments discovered by serendipity [e.g., the monoamine hypothesis of depression (43), the dopaminergic hypothesis of schizophrenia (44)]. Each of these models drove significant advances in the recognition and treatment of psychiatric illness. However, these advances have fallen far short of the standards set by the rest of medical nosology, which uses knowledge of pathophysiology to inform objective tests to identify specific disease states and predict prognosis and response to treatment.

Computationally-informed generative models attempt to establish how latent information processing states give rise to symptoms. Using formal mathematical systems to describe how information is used to produce behavior provides several tangible benefits. First, formalized systems tie hypotheses to measurable quantities derived from behavior, eschewing vaguely-posited theories of symptom development in favor of quantitative variables. This means that formal generative models are inherently falsifiable. This also means that experimental work can be applied more quickly to the development of actionable tests and biomarkers, based as they are in measured, replicable quantities derived from behavior and other objective data. Additionally, because the most useful models are capable of identifying and then discriminating among different latent states that drive behavior and may differ across groups, they are in principle also capable of identifying meaningful subgroups of individuals exhibiting the same symptoms for different mechanistic reasons. This is the equivalent of identifying individuals with a symptom profile consistent with fluid overload [i.e., dropsy (45)] who have underlying heart failure, kidney failure, cirrhosis, or blood dyscrasias: by identifying differential causal pathways, clinicians might intervene differently to arrest or reverse the causes giving rise to clinically indistinguishable symptoms.

The ability to intervene depends on a generative model that is sufficiently rich and sufficiently tied to a plausible biological instantiation in the brain. The Bayesian family of generative models (including Active Inference models) is particularly well fleshed-out in this respect (46, 47). Similarly to the work above describing how computational parameters have been tied to neurotransmitter systems, recent data have brought evidence to some of these ideas and tied symptomatology to specific neurotransmitter and circuit abnormalities via computational parameters (35, 4850). For example, Powers et al. (35) directly correlated parameters from computational model fit to fMRI data demonstrating hyer-precise perceptual priors in hallucinators. Cassidy et al. (48), linked striatal dopamine release to the precision of predictions and resulting hallucinations.

Within this framework, perception may be thought of as the process of inferring the causes of one's sensory input given existing knowledge about those causes as well as the input itself, weighted by the reliability of these sources (28, 39, 51, 52). An extension of these ideas into the realm of active inference is outlined above. By couching the emergence of hallucinations within these formal terms and in the context of a hierarchical system of brain organization, we are able to make predictions as to how interventions as diverse as social support and brain stimulation may act in concert to correct or compensate for alterations leading to dysfunction in hallucinations. Here, we propose that the interventions shown to be effective in specialty care for psychosis may exert that efficacy in predictable and consistent ways within the AI framework.

In the following section, we examine the existing evidence for the mechanisms underlying effective components of specialty care for psychosis and then turn toward the integration of this evidence with other elements of the AI framework.

Proposed Mechanisms of Specialty Care

Before turning to a discussion of how an AI-based understanding of positive symptoms and its putative neurobiological correlates may be related to the efficacy of specialty interventions for psychosis (i.e. ACT/CSCs), it would be helpful to discuss how these interventions may exert their desired effects. It is worth noting that, while the efficacy of these programs is well-documented, there is a lack of research postulating the mechanisms that underlie the programs' success. Of the literature that does address mechanism, few papers propose a specific model or approach for investigation, much less a computational one. As discussed in (53), one limitation of existing research is that interventions are multifaceted, making it difficult to disentangle the elements within the intervention in order to create causal models. It should also be noted that most papers examining the effectiveness of ACT and CSCs show efficacy in terms of global symptomatology, hospital readmission, and social and occupational function, but not in terms of specific symptoms or symptom clusters (such as auditory hallucinations or positive symptoms distinct from negative symptoms) (54, 55).

In a recent study from (56), which analyzed semi-structured interviews from individuals enrolled in CSC programs across the United States, a majority of participants reported what they perceived as the mechanism through which change had occurred during their time in the program. Participants pointed to therapy, medication support, and instrumental support (case management, employment and education services, etc.). They also noted the importance of forming meaningful relationships with their providers (56). Some other frameworks that may be useful for interpreting these results include the Therapeutic Contracting Model (57) and the Health Belief Model (58), which view patient-centered treatment, perceived physician investment, treatment efficacy, and environmental interventions as important drivers of favorable health behavior. The focus on patient-centeredness and shared decision making may also be important in the improvement of medication adherence in this population (59). While these frameworks provide initial insight into the components of treatment that contribute to the success of CSCs and ACT, our paper offers a model for understanding at a deeper level why these reported cornerstones of care may be effective in reducing symptoms.

Proposed Theoretical Framework

The main hypothesis of the Active Inference model proposed here with respect to psychosis is that the psychotic state arises from maladaptive prior beliefs going uncorrected by incoming sensory evidence and therefore driving the generation of delusions or hallucinations such that the experienced world comes to match the maladaptive prior. These priors may take a number of forms, may themselves be generated over time in a complex manner, and may operate at various levels of the neural hierarchy (29, 35, 36). The proposed dynamics of this system will be described below. In particular, we will explore the role of precisions- modifications of the weight of or confidence attributed priors or sensory evidence- and how ACT and CSC services may influence these. Given this “precise beliefs, imprecise evidence” approach, we now turn to our proposed theoretical framework for applying the computational language of active inference to ACT teams and CSC's in order to understand potential mechanisms of action for these services.

Let us begin with ACT teams. This particular service is often employed to support patients with more chronic forms of psychotic illness, especially when these patients are isolated from family or other social contacts (60). Under the above active inference account, these patients are in a state where the precision of their observations is reduced–that is, the confidence in, and therefore the attention afforded to, observations that may oppose their hallucination- and delusion- inducing priors is reduced. This is concordant with evidence that deficits in attention and other cognitive domains is a feature of schizophrenia that can impair social and occupational functioning (4, 61, 62). Two solutions to this situation seem plausible. One would be to reverse the tendency to afford low precision to external information—or in other words how external information is filtered—via some change within the patient, as might be produced via pharmacological treatment or after a course of cognitive training or CBT for psychosis (61, 63, 64) For example, a therapist might help a patient to re-evaluate their persecutory narratives and the trustworthiness of other people (e.g., family or members of their medical team), or cognitive training may help patients better attend to the environment around them in order to perform important tasks of daily living. Another approach would be to provide external information of greater perceived reliability which might encourage the patient to, over time, increase the precision afforded to information. These approaches are not mutually exclusive (and, in fact, may reinforce each other), and both seem to be present in the ACT team approach. The ACT team provides reliable, sometimes daily, social contact with professionals who provide consistent information about treatment as well as socioeconomic support. The fact that this support and information is delivered by other people in a consistent manner may be critical, given that patients with schizophrenia are less sensitive to social cues (65) and thus may require more consistent social engagement; the “assertive” nature of ACT also defeats the potential for patients to use social withdrawal to avoid this source of information. In addition, the provision of supportive psychotherapy—or even of CBT for psychosis interventions—as well as the structured nature of the ACT program itself may help to gradually re-train the patient's attention in order to improve the precision afforded to external sensory information. In this context it is interesting to consider the experience of someone experiencing ACT services: one might imagine the experience of psychosis when one is isolated to be similar to that of an echochamber- one in which one's own priors dominate experience, where the self effectively dominates external perception because of low sensory precision afforded to external cues. ACT services provide close social support, and regular contact with an external world that makes itself salient because of the assertive nature of ACT as described, and which provides a way out of the “echochamber” of priors run rampant. Indeed, in a study of patient experiences of ACT, some positive patient experiences were related to increased social contact and decreased isolation (66).

Furthermore, beyond increasing the salience of social information to compensate for reduced precision, it is also possible that the focus on social contact with the ACT team may serve as a form of social cognition training. As discussed by Green et al. (67), persons with schizophrenia tend to have reduced performance in a number of domains of social cognition, such as the accurate perception of the faces and voices of other people and inferring their emotional state. These limitations can be conceptualized as a reduction in the precision afforded to social information, and repeated interactions with the ACT team may help to re-train patients to attribute more attention to- and therefore raise the precision of- these social cues. Alternatively, should this reduction in precision be due to a deficit that cannot be remediated (i.e., due to a degradation in the integrity of relevant neural pathways), then the ACT team might help the patient understand the emotions and intentions of others in a continuous manner, acting in a sense as “emotional translators” for these patients in order to reduce stress or the need to resort to paranoid interpretations of others' intentions. Put another way, they may serve as external providers of a theory of mind for patients who are unable to develop or improve their own. This is critical, given that social cognition—and, in particular, theory of mind—is significantly associated with functional outcome in schizophrenia (68).

The repeatedly demonstrated effectiveness of ACT teams in preventing rehospitalization and relapse may have significance with respect to computational patterns as well. If the maladaptive priors that we argue underlie at least some psychotic experiences are reinforced when they are experienced in full (i.e., during relapse), then reducing the frequency these symptoms are experienced may, in some individuals, begin to shift patient priors away from the maladaptive set. The idea that psychotic symptoms are reinforced during relapse is supported by the literature demonstrating poorer outcomes correlating with greater relapse rates and rapid onset of symptoms during relapse [see (69), for a discussion]; this is the behavior one would expect if psychosis is in fact an attractor state (28) which is “deepened” and made easier to fall into with repeated exposure; in addition, one might expect the time required to recover from this state to lengthen after each subsequent relapse, which is true for some patients (69). Reducing the experience of psychotic symptoms may therefore interfere with this process or provide alternatives that can weaken the kinds of perceptual priors described in 30. In addition, the utility of ACT teams in improving medication adherence (70, 71) provides another mechanism for the reduction in positive symptoms.

It is interesting to consider, however, what happens when ACT team support is withdrawn, as this may help us understand to what extent ACT provides permanent vs. temporary change in patient capacities. While many ACT teams try to set rehabilitation goals for their patients, a number of patients require sustained services by ACT or, once they transition from ACT, continued community services, and in one study more than 10% of patients experienced psychiatric rehospitalization within 90 days of the end of ACT services (72). Why might this be? Thinking back again to our computational model, there are several possibilities. Firstly, the reduction in medication adherence in the absence of the ACT team's close follow-up may lead, via increase in dopaminergic activity, to a re-emergence of strong priors over a maladaptive policy space, making the mind of the patient more vulnerable to psychosis. Secondly, the lack of the ACT team's role in enriching the reliability of information in the world may result in a return to low sensory precision incapable of counterbalancing strong priors, the prerequisite combination for hallucinations. If patients have more severe illness, then it is also possible that the attractor state of psychosis has already become too deep, and the shifting of maladaptive priors toward more adaptive priors described in the previous paragraph may not be possible; this may explain why some patients require chronic ACT or similar-intensity services. Let us turn to the other key element of the computational model: the policy space.

The policy space represents the set of actions or sequences of actions a patient may take in the world, and represents the potential for the patient to adapt to changing circumstances. When their policy space is limited and does not accurately account for the environment, and the information from the environment has low precision, then hallucinations can occur. These are driven either by sensory priors formed over time, or by the prior expectations of sensory information driven by policies which affect state inferences. As above, if sound is expected (as a result of a sensory prior) or one expects to be listening to a sound (as a result of a maladaptive policy), and no high-precision information is available to sway perception toward the correct state (the inference of silence in the world) then sound will be generated in the form of a hallucination in order to satisfy the prior. How might an ACT team interface with the policy space? Two possibilities seem evident. The first is that the ACT team, through role modeling or the provision of therapy, help to expand a patient's policy space through learning. The second is that the team assists directly in problem solving- such that when the world is not explained by the set of policies the patient has at their disposal, the team can assist the patient by effectively “adding” their policy space to the patient's. The patient would still need to grow their policy space sufficiently to include the policy of “working with the ACT team,” but this may be a less taxing requirement than learning specific policies to deal with each of the other challenges life can generate. As such, when ACT team services are withdrawn, some patients—those for whom it is still possible to grow their policy space, potentially because of less advanced or severe illness—may still demonstrate improved function because of what they have learned while they were receiving services, whereas other patients—those who were relying on the ACT team as an external cognitive assistance mechanism—would be more likely to respond to new or stressful events, for which they lack the appropriate policies to respond, with a relapse of positive symptoms. This phenomenon is certainly observed clinically: many patients with chronic schizophrenia are re-hospitalized after stressors (such as altercations with landlords or interactions with government authorities) for which the response is recurrence or exacerbation of psychotic symptoms (23).

In considering the descriptions in preceding sections, it becomes clear that ACT teams provide external computational resources for patients in two cognitive domains, social and neuro cognition, that have been shown to be predictive of functional outcome [see (68), for a review]. When ACT teams help patients overcome their challenges with problem-solving—for example, helping them to find a new place to live, or helping them set up a phone line—by helping them overcome attentional difficulties (potentially related to low sensory precision) or challenges in sequencing their actions in an appropriate manner (because of their maladaptive policy space), ACT teams are supplementing patient neurocognitive resources. When ACT teams support patients in understanding social cues or interpreting the intentions of others, they are helping to increase the sensory precision afforded to social stimuli in order to support their social cognition. Acting as “external brains” in these key domains, ACT teams are supporting key cognitive functions in a manner which could have significant positive impacts on functional outcome.

Thus far, we have discussed how ACT teams might improve the functioning of patients with chronic psychosis in three main ways, using the language of active inference and computational psychiatry. Firstly, ACT teams provide a stable and reliable source of information and social contact, which may enrich the information in the outside world available to a patient or which might help them learn to better use the information already available (increasing sensory precision). Secondly, the teams ensure access to and often adherence to medication, which acts by reducing dopaminergic signaling (reducing prior precision over policies). Finally, the teams may help patients learn how to approach life challenges more effectively (growing the policy space) or at least to problem solve (by acting as a “supplemental” policy space). We have also reflected on how, in providing support to patients in the manner described, ACT teams can supplement patient computational resources and help improve social and neuro cognition in a manner that should help improve functional outcomes. These mechanisms may be difficult to separate out, and likely work in concert with each other, but which particular mechanism is more crucial for a given patient, based on their individual capacities, may be relevant in determining the type, level, and longevity of services required, and the response of the patient to the withdrawal or interruption of these services. This latter point about service interruption is relevant because services are commonly interrupted- staff may go on vacation, maternity leave, or a holiday may reduce the number of available staff. Having a better idea of which patients are at highest risk for relapse in the event of temporarily limited services may assist in the assigning of temporary or replacement services to patients in greatest need.

We turn now to a discussion of CSCs, which primarily serve first-episode patients and serve as the basis for approaches meant to treat those at Clinical High Risk for psychosis (CHR-P). In addition to symptomatic relief and assisting in ensuring function, many of these clinics also have as a mandate the early detection and treatment of psychosis in order to improve symptomatic and functional outcomes (73). While research is still ongoing to determine long-term outcomes in patients treated in CSC clinics (74), it may still be of some utility to consider their possible mechanisms of action for the fulfillment of these two mandates from a computational perspective. As discussed in (36), the prodromal or high-risk state can be conceptualized as one in which there has been some change in the priors a patient may hold- beliefs may have begun to grow more anxious or fearful (for example, a person may develop beliefs of being persecuted or of being watched), prior to and then alongside the development of attenuated psychotic symptoms [consistent with the description reviewed in (75)]. However, there seems to still be enough ability for patients to be able to use the context present in the environment to counteract these maladaptive beliefs and to avoid frank psychotic symptoms. The reasons for this preserved ability are relevant.

One possibility is that these patients retain at least moderate sensory precision. One reason may be because the neural pathways that encode this precision have not yet lost their integrity. Previous work has demonstrated interval deterioration in gray matter and white matter tracts between the high-risk state and first-episode psychosis (76, 77), suggesting that ongoing neural deterioration may be leading to changes in the quality of information carried over time. Another possibility is that increasingly maladaptive and rigid priors over the course of the progression of the prodrome lead patients to actively reduce their sensory precision. Normally, a prior shown to be incorrect based on gathered data would be updated. If this prior is rigidly fixed—for example, because of a reduced or over-confident policy space which does not allow for other alternatives—then a dilemma occurs: should the agent trust its priors or its observations? If the prior cannot be changed, then a reasonable course of action would be to begin to doubt incoming sensory information- to reduce its precision. This may occur, as noted in the previous section, via a modulation of ACh. Early intervention while there is still some flexibility in priors or before sensory information has been fully down-weighted may delay or even prevent the onset of psychosis, although the type of intervention chosen would depend crucially on the pathophysiological processes at play in hallucinogenesis. Importantly, careful identification of potential computational subgroups within these early-stage patients may be crucial for the development and personalization of interventions. For example, for some patients with low sensory precision because of reduced ACh but intact neural pathways, increasing sensory precision may be beneficial; in other patients with less preserved neural pathways, increasing the precision of incoming information may be less effective as it might result in the amplification of inherently noisy signals. What remains to be determined, however, is the relative importance of neuro-degenerative processes vs. altered neural signaling in the mechanisms underlying the transition to psychosis. The former may be less amenable than the latter to purely socio-environmental interventions, though we hypothesize that the manner in which neurodegeneration proceeds (i.e., those policies which are pruned vs. those which are preserved) may depend on the prevailing emotions and beliefs held more or less strongly by the patient during the process. These in turn may be amenable to psychotherapy and social interventions.

Another possibility is that FEP or high-risk clinics can help patients navigate the very challenging situations which can occur during the FEP or high-risk period- such as difficulties in scholastic or professional life caused by symptoms, and the transition from a state of wellness to one of relative disability. This is consistent with the focus of CSCs on case management and an individualized approach that adapts to the needs- and specific stressors- experienced by each patient. They may also help patients recognize, explore and understand emerging psychotic beliefs and experiences while maintaining and reinforcing links to consensual reality, preventing them from developing the crystallized set of delusional beliefs that in commonly used scales such as the PANSS characterize more severe illness (78). This rigid set of beliefs may inform the maladaptive policy space that we hypothesize is present in more chronic illness, and any efforts that could be made to retain flexibility or include more adaptive policies may help to prevent or reduce the severity of further illness. Additionally, early intervention may prevent or mitigate the formation of maladaptive perceptual priors—the deepening of attractor states described above—which coheres with the philosophy of CSCs that early intervention and decrease in the duration of untreated psychosis is key for improving long-term outcomes. Overall, concurrent with the high-risk and FEP literature, there appears to be a computational argument for concerted attempts at prevention, treatment, and mitigation of psychotic symptoms at this phase of illness. From an experiential perspective, the thesis here is that less experience of psychotic symptoms would prevent the need to develop the crystalized, internally consistent psychotic narrative which characterizes more severe illness- keeping the person more grounded in consensual reality from the start, rather than needing to bring them back to that baseline from the thoroughly different experience of repeated psychotic episodes.

We note a number of limitations to the Active Inference model described in Benrimoh et al. (29, 36). The first is that this model was focused on hallucinations in a dyadic context—that is, hallucinations when an agent was interacting with an external world containing another agent. As such, it is not clear if the model's results would hold true in other contexts—for example, in a situation where the agent being examined could choose to change its environment or in which it had policies available to it that were not focused on the dyadic interaction. This model was also not a learning model: while policies were selected over a number of time-steps, changes in computational parameters were not conserved between trials, which means that while the model could reflect states in time- which could reflect, via the choice of initial computational parameters, specific stages of illness—it cannot model in a continuous manner the onset, establishment, and transition to chronicity of psychotic illness. Future work will aim to provide models that can change in this manner over time. Finally, this model provides a demonstration of one possible route to psychosis—the generation of hallucinations in order to match priors that are strongly held and uncorrected by the weakening of sensory precision. There are other possible computational “recipes” for the generation of hallucinations, and this model does not purport to be the only possible one. Figures 14 provide a visual depiction of the proposed theoretical framework.

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1. The perception of an agent that does not hallucinate is shown on the left. The incoming sensory evidence about the environment has a normal confidence ascribed to it and the agent has an expansive policy space without bias toward a specific string of actions. The agent does, however, have a strong prior belief that it will perceive a singing bird. On the right, when precision of incoming sensory evidence is reduced and the forest scene looks blurry, the agent is unable to use the environment to correct for their strong prior belief and hallucinates the singing bird.

FIGURE 2
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 2. On the left, the agent experiences reduced precision of incoming sensory evidence, but it has an expansive policy space without bias toward any string of actions and has equally weighted priors. On the right, the agent experiences an increase in prior precision over policies, and their policy space is such that this results in having a bias toward actions that heavily involve listening and therefore the expectation of sound. This results in the hallucinated songbird because the agent is over-confident in these policies and less certain about other policies which may have implied other possible states of the world.

FIGURE 3
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 3. On the left, the agent experiences incoming sensory evidence to which it ascribes low confidence, and it has equally weighted priors and policies in an expansive policy space. The result is an agent that does not hallucinate. On the right, the agent experiences degraded precision of incoming sensory evidence and a decreased policy space. The decreased policy space now only includes a couple of policies that rely heavily on listening. The result is an agent that does not have a full range of policies adaptable to the world it finds itself in and which imply that a singing bird is present and thus the agent hallucinates the songbird.

FIGURE 4
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 4. On the left, the agent experiences degraded precision of incoming sensory evidence, a strong prior belief, a decreased policy space, and strong confidence in policy that relies exclusively on listening. This agent hallucinates the songbird as it would in the cases presented in Figures 13. On the right are four panels, each with a single change from the hallucinatory perception on the left. Each change represents an effect that treatment could have on a hallucinating agent (note that in almost all cases multiple parameters change with treatment, but for simplicity we demonstrate the possible changes independently). The first is improved sensory precision: with clearer incoming sensory evidence, the agent can use its perception of the environment to correct for an over-weighted prior/policy or a maladapted policy space. We hypothesize that the approach of CSCs and ACT teams may help to increase the quality of and confidence in the external environment and as such improve the sensory precision. The second is expanded policy space: with additional actions that the agent could take, it can make further observations about its environment and potentially choose a policy that less heavily implies the presence of the songbird, allowing it to correct for an over-weighted prior/policy and degraded sensory information. We hypothesize that this could occur as a result of cognitive training or therapy and social interactions and external support provided through ACT teams, or that policy space could be preserved via the early intervention provided by CSCs. The third is reduced prior precision over policies: the agent now has equal confidence in the listening action as well as the listening, looking closely, and walking closer action, and as such a weaker prior favoring the presence of the bird. This is the effect hypothesized to be produced by dopamine blockade and helps the agent disengage. The fourth is reduced influence of sensory priors: when the prior beliefs are weighted equally, the agent is not biased toward perceiving the songbird despite the limited policy space and strong prior precision over policies. We hypothesize that this could occur as a result of cognitive training or therapy and social interactions and external support provided through ACT teams, or that the formation of fixed maladaptive priors could be prevented via the early intervention provided by CSCs.

Proposed Steps for Validation

In order for these models to be of use in assisting with the improvement or innovation of treatment strategies, there must be the possibility to test the hypothetical mechanisms provided and to either support the proposed mechanisms, to falsify them, or to suggest alterations that may improve them. Given the complexity of the cognitive and emotional processes at play and the multiple processes which may give rise to observed behavior, designing experiments to test specific cognitive mechanisms can be challenging, though recent work has demonstrated that it is possible (35, 37, 38, 40). We will discuss some options here.

One possibility is to conduct an imaging study of patients in ACT follow-up and to relate white or gray matter integrity to the length of required ACT follow-up. This would support the conceptual model if patients who have a greater burden of neural degeneration- which might relate to inflexibility of priors or policy spaces- require prolonged care from ACT services as these services help provide the external computational resources described above. However, this would not provide very specific support to the model, as lower neural integrity may simply reflect more severe disease overall. To provide more specific support, we could also try to determine if this relationship between reduced neural integrity and need for ACT support is moderated by measures relating to our computational parameters. These could include tasks that measure strength of perceptual priors [e.g., (35, 37, 38)] or new tasks, currently in development, which measure policy space size and flexibility. These may take the form of open-ended games which patients may be able to solve in a number of ways, with the number of solutions utilized being a proxy for the size of the policy space. The advent and increasing use of virtual reality (VR) in the assessment and treatment of psychosis (79), as well as emerging evidence of its feasibility and utility (80), presents a unique opportunity in this respect. VR simulations could be used to generate more ecologically valid tasks to assess the size and flexibility of a policy space by giving the participant access to an array of abilities and options—from saccades to looking around to motion and interaction with objects in the virtual world—more closely related to their real-life repertoire of actions. In addition, games could be made that match contexts of interest to both participants and researchers—for example, navigating crowded shopping environments while accomplishing a list of tasks and dealing with stressful stimuli. In addition, as these tasks become more adept at assessing and tracking the policy space over time, they may also become useful for training and treatment, supplementing the work of ACT teams or CSCs by providing an engaging training modality that could be personalized with scenarios based on the needs of and challenges faced by individual patients (79). Indeed, the simulated environment would allow for the modulation of the salience or precision of stimuli (i.e., by including highly important objects or adding noise to signals) and the importance of actions could also be modulated (i.e., by altering the consequences of actions or the effects they produce). These manipulations could more effectively investigate or target the various computational parameters discussed. It would also be important to correlate these tests with measures of the cognitive deficits often seen in schizophrenia (1) in order to understand how they may be related and whether more general cognitive training strategies may improve this measure. These psychophysical tasks could be further correlated with need for specific ACT services, such as problem solving support. A lack of correlation between performance in these tasks and need for ACT services would serve—importantly—as strong evidence against the conceptual view presented here. An expansion or maintenance of policy space after ACT or CSC services compared to treatment as usual would also provide evidence in favor of this model, as would a reduction in the strength of perceptual priors after ACT or CSC services. It should be noted that the possibility for the expansion of policy space or reduction of the strength of perceptual priors may depend on disease severity; as such, maintenance of existing policy space with ACT compared to further contraction with relapse in treatment as usual may be expected for more severe patients, and the lack of strengthening of perceptual priors with CSC compared to treatment as usual over the course of disease progression may be expected for patients with more severe first episode psychosis.

With respect to testing the neurobiological implementation of this conceptual model, one can imagine a number of experiments. For example, to test the role of ACh in encoding sensory precision, tracer studies could look at changes in ACh signaling before and after initiation of ACT services, in order to determine if ACh increases with the onset and maintenance of ACT services. Similarly, to test the role of decreased sensory precision in the onset of psychotic symptoms, CHR-P patients could have ACh signaling serially tested before and after a first episode psychosis, to determine if a reduction of ACh correlates with psychosis onset and if treatment at a CSC is correlated with ACh increase alongside reduction in psychotic symptoms; a comparison group treated outside of a CSC could also be included to determine if CSC services have an effect beyond treatment as usual, which mostly centers on dopamine-blocking medication without the extensive services provide by CSCs (an important caveat to strict interpretation of these experiments, however, will be the interactions between the dopaminergic and cholinergic systems). In addition, given recent positive preliminary studies of ACh-agonist agents in reducing symptoms in schizophrenia (81), one might also consider testing if these agents might help to arrest symptom development in at least some sub-groups of patients in prodromal or early phases of psychosis. Once again, psychophysical measurements of perceptual priors, sensory precision, and policy space could also be administered at different time points in order to determine how they correlate with service use, symptoms, and neurobiological measures. These psychophysical and neurobiological measures, administered in high-risk groups served by CSCs, may also have value in predicting transition to psychosis, as has been the case for related measures, such as the repetition positivity (82) or mismatch negativity (83) measured by EEG.

Finally, qualitative research should be a significant component of the above experiments, as this would help to “close the loop,” so to speak, and to these measures, measured symptoms, and the experience and views of people with respect to their hallucinations and their relationships with caregiving services like ACT teams and CSCs.

Conclusions

At first glance, one might argue that adding the computational lens does not add very much to the account of mechanisms of action of ACT teams and CSCs. Using this language has perhaps provided a sophisticated theory for why social or problem-solving support may benefit patients, but it has not changed the fact that these well-established interventions are effective. Indeed, the components of the interventions identified as being crucial here do not differ greatly from more traditional accounts relating to the reduction of stress or the provision of housing or social support discussed above. In addition, the computational mechanisms proposed are not easily separable, as several of them are affected by the same interventions, which seems to limit explanatory power. However, this computational language does provide us with two key advantages. The first is that it can be used to generate specific and testable hypotheses that can be used to improve existing interventions or potentially design new ones from first principles. The second is that it provides a bridge from a macro-level clinical intervention with multiple components, to potential psychological processes which could be measured with psychophysics experiments, all the way down to the potential neural implementation of these processes which can be interrogated using tracer studies and neuroimaging. This in turn allows for the synergistic design of interventional combinations, pairing psychosocial interventions with pharmacological interventions meant to optimize combined efficacy. At more social and experiential levels of interpretation, it also allows us to better understand the experience of patients in their interaction with services provided by CSCs and ACT teams. This paper serves as a case study for how thinking about mental disorders from the lens of computation allows us to integrate information across all levels of abstraction, and to use this information at different levels in order to design experiments or improve interventions.

We have laid out a number of possible experiments which might be used to establish (or falsify) some of the proposed computational mechanisms described here. These experiments, should they yield new metrics, may have clinical value. For example, should we successfully create tests that measure policy space or sensory precision, and demonstrate that they in fact behave as expected in this conceptualization, these could be used as tests for staging patients, determining progress, and attributing new resources as needed. Patients may also have care personalized to them based on their specific computational profile. For example, a patient with a limited policy space as a result of degeneration of cortical structures may be recognized as needing long-term problem-solving services, while another patient with a relatively preserved policy space may be enrolled in a program with a greater focus on rehabilitation- instead of subjecting both patients to the same rehabilitation-focused program and considering the first patient to have “failed” treatment. New treatments- either pharmacological or environmental in nature- might also be designed with this computational language- and its neurobiological correlates- in mind, and with the use of tests derived from computational theory to act as biomarkers for treatment effects. Finally, researchers investigating other psychiatric conditions for which fewer treatments exist- for example, antisocial personality disorder- may use this case study as an example of how an understanding of underlying computations may drive our understanding of both neurobiology and potential interventions.

Data Availability Statement

The original contributions generated for the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author/s.

Author Contributions

DB, ES, AS, and AP collaborated in the conceptualization and writing and review of the manuscript. ES produced the figures. DB, AS, and AP provided comments on the figures. DB led the writing of the manuscript. AP provided supervision. All authors contributed to the article and approved the submitted version.

Conflict of Interest

DB is a shareholder, officer, and employee of Aifred Health, a digital mental health company the work of which is unrelated to this article.

The remaining authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher's Note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

1. Bowie CR, Harvey PD. Cognitive deficits and functional outcome in schizophrenia. Neuropsychiatr Dis Treat. (2006) 2:531–6. doi: 10.2147/nedt.2006.2.4.531

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

2. Wiersma D, Jenner JA, Nienhuis FJ, van de Willige G. Hallucination focused integrative treatment improves quality of life in schizophrenia patients. Acta Psychiatr Scand. (2004) 109:194–201. doi: 10.1046/j.0001-690X.2003.00237.x

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

3. Shawyer F, Mackinnon A, Farhall J, Trauer T, Copolov D. Command hallucinations and violence: implications for detention and treatment. Psychiatry Psychol Law. (2003) 10:97–107. doi: 10.1375/pplt.2003.10.1.97

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

4. Mucci A, Galderisi S, Gibertoni D, Rossi A, Rocca P, Bertolino A, et al. Factors associated with real-life functioning in persons with schizophrenia in a 4-year follow-up study of the italian network for research on psychoses. JAMA Psychiatry. (2021) 78:550–9. doi: 10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2020.4614

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Wittorf A, Jakobi U, Bechdolf A, Müller B, Sartory G, Wagner M, et al. The influence of baseline symptoms and insight on the therapeutic alliance early in the treatment of schizophrenia. Eur Psychiatry. (2009) 24:259–67. doi: 10.1016/j.eurpsy.2008.12.015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

6. Freeman D, Emsley R, Dunn G, Fowler D, Bebbington P, Kuipers E, et al. The stress of the street for patients with persecutory delusions: a test of the symptomatic and psychological effects of going outside into a busy urban area. Schizophr Bull. (2015) 41:971–9. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbu173

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

7. Fierro M, Hernández AM, Malcolm J. The psychopathology of delusion of control according to subjective experience. Rev Colomb Psiquiatr. (2018) 47:221–8. doi: 10.1016/j.rcp.2017.02.004

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Brisch R, Saniotis A, Wolf R, Bielau H, Bernstein H.-G., et al. The role of dopamine in schizophrenia from a neurobiological and evolutionary perspective: old fashioned, but still in vogue. Front Psychiatry. (2014) 5:110. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2014.00110

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

9. Potkin SG, Kane JM, Correll CU, Lindenmayer J.-P., Agid O, et al. The neurobiology of treatment-resistant schizophrenia: paths to antipsychotic resistance and a roadmap for future research. Npj Schizophrenia. (2020) 6:1–10. doi: 10.1038/s41537-019-0090-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

10. Stepnicki P, Kondej M, Kaczor AA. Current concepts and treatments of schizophrenia. Molecules. (2018) 23:2087. doi: 10.3390/molecules23082087

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Haddad PM, Brain C, Scott J. Nonadherence with antipsychotic medication in schizophrenia: challenges and management strategies. Patient Relat Outcome Meas. (2014) 5:43–62. doi: 10.2147/PROM.S42735

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

12. Moritz S, Favrod J, Andreou C, Morrison AP, Bohn F, Veckenstedt R, et al. Beyond the usual suspects: positive attitudes towards positive symptoms is associated with medication noncompliance in psychosis. Schizophrenia Bull. (2013) 39:917–22. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbs005

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

13. Higashi K, Medic G, Littlewood KJ, Diez T, Granström O, De Hert M. Medication adherence in schizophrenia: Factors influencing adherence and consequences of nonadherence, a systematic literature review. Ther Adv Psychopharmacol. (2013) 3:200–18. doi: 10.1177/2045125312474019

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

14. El-Mallakh P, Findlay J. Strategies to improve medication adherence in patients with schizophrenia: the role of support services. Neuropsychiatr Dis Treat. (2015) 11:1077–90. doi: 10.2147/NDT.S56107

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

15. Lambert TJR, Velakoulis D, Pantelis C. (2003) Medical comorbidity in schizophrenia. Med J Aust. 178 (S9):S67–S70. doi: 10.5694/j.1326-5377.2003.tb05311.x

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

16. Cohen CI. Poverty and the course of schizophrenia: implications for research and policy. Hosp Commun Psychiatry. (1993) 44:951–8. doi: 10.1176/ps.44.10.951

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Phillips SD, Burns BJ, Edgar ER, Mueser KT, Linkins KW, Rosenheck RA, et al. Moving assertive community treatment into standard practice. Psychiatr Serv. (2001) 52:771–9. doi: 10.1176/appi.ps.52.6.771

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

18. Kane JM, Robinson DG, Schooler NR, Mueser KT, Penn DL, Rosenheck RA, et al. Comprehensive versus usual community care for first-episode psychosis: 2-year outcomes from the NIMH RAISE early treatment program. Am J Psychiatry. (2016) 173:362–72. doi: 10.1176/appi.ajp.2015.15050632

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Mueser KT, Penn DL, Addington J, Brunette MF, Gingerich S, Glynn SM, et al. The NAVIGATE program for first-episode psychosis: rationale, overview, and description of psychosocial components. Psychiatr Serv. (2015) 66:680–90. doi: 10.1176/appi.ps.201400413

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

20. Srihari VH, Tek C, Pollard J, Zimmet S, Keat J, Cahill JD, et al. (2014). Reducing the duration of untreated psychosis and its impact in the U.S.: The STEP-ED study. BMC Psychiatry 14:335. doi: 10.1186/s12888-014-0335-3

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

21. Coldwell CM, Bender WS. The effectiveness of assertive community treatment for homeless populations with severe mental illness: a meta-analysis. Am J Psychiatry. (2007) 164:393–9. doi: 10.1176/ajp.2007.164.3.393

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Nossel I, Wall MM, Scodes J, Marino LA, Zilkha S, Bello I, et al. Results of a coordinated specialty care program for early psychosis and predictors of outcomes. Psychiatr Serv. (2018) 69:863–70. doi: 10.1176/appi.ps.201700436

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

23. Martland N, Martland R, Cullen AE, Bhattacharyya S. Are adult stressful life events associated with psychotic relapse? A systematic review of 23 studies. Psychol Med. (2020) 50:2302–16. doi: 10.1017/S0033291720003554

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

24. Guo X, Zhai J, Liu Z, Fang M, Wang B, Wang C, et al. Effect of antipsychotic medication alone vs combined with psychosocial intervention on outcomes of early-stage schizophrenia: a randomized, 1-year study. Arch Gen Psychiatry. (2010) 67:895–904. doi: 10.1001/archgenpsychiatry.2010.105

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

25. Boccignone G, Cordeschi R. Coping with levels of explanation in the behavioral sciences. Front Psychol. (2015) 6:213. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00213

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

26. Huys QJM, Maia TV, Frank MJ. Computational psychiatry as a bridge from neuroscience to clinical applications. Nat Neurosci. (2016) 19:404–13. doi: 10.1038/nn.4238

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

27. Sterzer P, Adams RA, Fletcher P, Frith C, Lawrie SM, Muckli L, et al. The predictive coding account of psychosis. Biol Psychiatry. (2018) 84:634–43. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2018.05.015

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

28. Adams RA, Stephan KE, Brown HR, Frith CD, Friston KJ. The computational anatomy of psychosis. Front Psychiatry. (2013) 4:47. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2013.00047

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

29. Benrimoh D, Parr T, Vincent P, Adams RA, Friston K. Active inference and auditory hallucinations. Comput Psychiatry. (2018) 2:183–204. doi: 10.1162/CPSY_a_00022

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

30. Friston K, FitzGerald T, Rigoli F, Schwartenbeck P, Pezzulo G. Active inference: a process theory. Neural Comput. (2017) 29:1–49. doi: 10.1162/NECO_a_00912

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

31. Friston K, Kilner J, Harrison L. A free energy principle for the brain. J Physiol. (2006) 100:70–87.

Google Scholar

32. Catani M, Craig MC, Forkel SJ, Kanaan R, Picchioni M, Toulopoulou T, et al. Altered integrity of perisylvian language pathways in schizophrenia: relationship to auditory hallucinations. Biol Psychiatry. (2011) 70:1143–50. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2011.06.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

33. Moran RJ, Campo P, Symmonds M, Stephan KE, Dolan RJ, Friston KJ. Free energy, precision and learning: the role of cholinergic neuromodulation. J Neurosci. (2013) 33:8227–36. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4255-12.2013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

34. Schwartenbeck P, FitzGerald THB, Mathys C, Dolan R, Friston K. The Dopaminergic Midbrain Encodes the Expected Certainty about Desired Outcomes. Cerebral Cortex (New York, NY). (2015) 25:3434–45. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhu159

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

35. Powers AR, Mathys C, Corlett PR. Pavlovian conditioning–induced hallucinations result from overweighting of perceptual priors. Science. (2017) 357:596–600. doi: 10.1126/science.aan3458

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

36. Benrimoh D, Parr T, Adams RA, Friston K. Hallucinations both in and out of context: An active inference account. PLoS ONE. (2019) 14:e0212379. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0212379

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

37. Vercammen A, Aleman A. Semantic expectations can induce false perceptions in hallucination-prone individuals. Schizophrenia Bull. (2010) 36:151–6. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbn063

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

38. Teufel C, Subramaniam N, Dobler V, Perez J, Finnemann J, Mehta, et al. Shift toward prior knowledge confers a perceptual advantage in early psychosis and psychosis-prone healthy individuals. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. (2015) 112:13401–6. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1503916112

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

39. Corlett PR, Horga G, Fletcher PC, Alderson-Day B, Schmack K, Powers AR. Hallucinations and strong priors. Trends Cogn Sci. (2019) 23:114–27. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2018.12.001

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

40. Benrimoh DA, Friston KJ. All grown up: computational theories of psychosis, complexity, and progress. Journal of Abnormal Psychology. (2020) 129:624–8. doi: 10.1037/abn0000543

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

41. Freud S. The ego and the id (1923). TACD J. (1989) 17:5–22. doi: 10.1080/1046171X.1989.12034344

CrossRef Full Text

42. Neisser U. Cognitive Psychology: Classic Edition. Routledge and CRC Press (1967).

Google Scholar

43. Delgado PL. Depression: the case for a monoamine deficiency. J Clin Psychiatry. (2000) 61 (Suppl 6) 7–11.

Google Scholar

44. Meltzer HY, Stahl SM. The dopamine hypothesis of schizophrenia: a review*. Schizophr Bull. (1976) 2:19–76. doi: 10.1093/schbul/2.1.19

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

45. Clementz BA, Sweeney J, Keshavan MS, Pearlson G, Tamminga CA. Using biomarker batteries. Biol Psychiatry. (2015) 77:90–2. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2014.10.012

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

46. Friston KJ, Stephan KE, Montague R, Dolan RJ. Computational psychiatry: the brain as a phantastic organ. Lancet. Psychiatry. (2014) 1:148–58. doi: 10.1016/S2215-0366(14)70275-5

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

47. Friston K. The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nat Rev Neurosci. (2010) 11:127–38. doi: 10.1038/nrn2787

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

48. Cassidy CM, Balsam PD, Weinstein JJ, Rosengard RJ, Slifstein M, Daw ND, et al. A perceptual inference mechanism for hallucinations linked to striatal dopamine. Curr Biol. (2018) 28:503–14. e4. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2017.12.059

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

49. Alderson-Day B, Lima CF, Evans S, Krishnan S, Shanmugalingam P, Fernyhough C, et al. Distinct processing of ambiguous speech in people with non-clinical auditory verbal hallucinations. Brain. (2017) 140:2475–89. doi: 10.1093/brain/awx206

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

50. Howes OD, Hird EJ, Adams RA, Corlett PR, McGuire P. Aberrant salience, information processing, and dopaminergic signaling in people at clinical high risk for psychosis. Biol Psychiatry. (2020) 88:304–14. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2020.03.012

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

51. Friston K. A theory of cortical responses. Philos Trans R Soc B Biol Sci. (2005) 360:815–36. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2005.1622

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

52. Powers AR, Kelley M, Corlett PR. Hallucinations as top-down effects on perception. Biol Psychiatry Cogn Neurosci Neuroimaging. (2016) 1:393–400. doi: 10.1016/j.bpsc.2016.04.003

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

53. Bosanac P, Patton GC, Castle DJ. Early intervention in psychotic disorders: faith before facts? Psychol Med. (2010) 40:353–8. doi: 10.1017/S0033291709990341

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

54. Ziguras SJ, Stuart GW. A meta-analysis of the effectiveness of mental health case management over 20 years. Psychiatr Serv. (2000) 51:1410–21. doi: 10.1176/appi.ps.51.11.1410

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

55. Vijverberg R, Ferdinand R, Beekman A, van Meijel. B. The effect of youth assertive community treatment: A systematic PRISMA review. BMC Psychiatry. (2017) 17:284. doi: 10.1186/s12888-017-1446-4

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

56. Daley TC, Jones N, George P, Rosenblatt A. First-person accounts of change among young adults enrolled in coordinated specialty care for first-episode psychosis. Psychiatric Services. (2020). doi: 10.1176/appi.ps.202000101

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

57. Heinssen RK, Levendusky PG, Hunter RH. Client as colleague: therapeutic contracting with the seriously mentally ill. Am Psychol. (1995) 50:522–32. doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.50.7.522

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

58. Fenton WS, Blyler CR, Heinssen RK. Determinants of medication compliance in schizophrenia: empirical and clinical findings. Schizophr Bull. (1997) 23:637–51. doi: 10.1093/schbul/23.4.637

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

59. Deegan PE, Drake RE. Shared decision making and medication management in the recovery process. Psychiatr Serv. (2006) 57:1636–9. doi: 10.1176/ps.2006.57.11.1636

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

60. Pettersen H, Ruud T, Ravndal E, Havnes I, Landheim A. Engagement in assertive community treatment as experienced by recovering clients with severe mental illness and concurrent substance use. Int J Ment Health Syst. (2014) 8:40. doi: 10.1186/1752-4458-8-40

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

61. Harris JG, Minassian A, Perry W. Stability of attention deficits in schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. (2007) 91:107–111. doi: 10.1016/j.schres.2006.12.021

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

62. Green MF. What are the functional consequences of neurocognitive deficits in schizophrenia? Am J Psychiatry. (1996) 153:321–30. doi: 10.1176/ajp.153.3.321

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

63. Bell MD, Fiszdon JM, Bryson G. Attention training in schizophrenia: differing responses to similar tasks. J Psychiatr Res. (2009) 43:490–6. doi: 10.1016/j.jpsychires.2008.04.011

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

64. Morrison AK. Cognitive behavior therapy for people with schizophrenia. Psychiatry. (2009) 6:32–39.

PubMed Abstract | Google Scholar

65. Corrigan PW, Green MF. Schizophrenic patients' sensitivity to social cues: The role of abstraction. Am J Psychiatry. (1993) 150:589–94. doi: 10.1176/ajp.150.4.589

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

66. Watts J, Priebe S. A phenomenological account of users' experiences of assertive community treatment. Bioethics. (2002) 16:439–54. doi: 10.1111/1467-8519.00301

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

67. Green MF, Horan WP, Lee J. Social cognition in schizophrenia. Nat Rev Neurosci. (2015) 16:620–31.s. doi: 10.1038/nrn4005

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

68. Fett AKJ, Viechtbauer W, Penn DL, van Os J, Krabbendam L. The relationship between neurocognition and social cognition with functional outcomes in schizophrenia: a meta-analysis. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. (2011) 35:573–88. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2010.07.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

69. Emsley R, Chiliza B, Asmal L, Harvey BH. The nature of relapse in schizophrenia. BMC Psychiatry. (2013) 13:50. doi: 10.1186/1471-244X-13-50

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

70. Manuel JI, Covell NH, Jackson CT, Essock SM. Does assertive community treatment increase medication adherence for people with co-occurring psychotic and substance use disorders? J Am Psychiatr Nurses Assoc. (2011) 17:51–6. doi: 10.1177/1078390310395586

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

71. Dixon L, Weiden P, Torres M, Lehman A. (1997) Assertive community treatment and medication compliance in the homeless mentally ill. Am J Psychiatry. (1997) 154:1302–4. doi: 10.1176/ajp.154.9.1302

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

72. Huz S, Thorning H, White CN, Fang L, Smith BT, Radigan M, et al. Time in assertive community treatment: a statewide quality improvement initiative to reduce length of participation. Psychiatr Serv. (2017) 68:539–41. doi: 10.1176/appi.ps.201700127

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

73. Albert N, Weibell MA. The outcome of early intervention in first episode psychosis. Int Rev Psychiatry. (2019) 31:413–24. doi: 10.1080/09540261.2019.1643703

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

74. Chan SKW, Chan HYV, Devlin J, Bastiampillai T, Mohan T, Hui CLM, et al. A systematic review of long-term outcomes of patients with psychosis who received early intervention services. Int Rev Psychiatry. (2019) 31:425–40. doi: 10.1080/09540261.2019.1643704

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

75. Powers AR, McGlashan TH, Woods SW. Clinical phenomenology of the prodrome for psychosis. In: Psychotic Disorders. Cary, NC: Oxford University Press (2021). p. 105–112.

Google Scholar

76. Jung WH, Kim JS, Jang JH, Choi J.-S., Jung MH, et al. Cortical thickness reduction in individuals at ultra-high-risk for psychosis. Schizophr Bull. (2011) 37:839–49. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbp151

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

77. Ziermans TB, Schothorst PF, Schnack HG, Koolschijn P. C. M. P., Kahn RS, et al. Progressive structural brain changes during development of psychosis. Schizophr Bull. (2012) 38:519–30. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbq113

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

78. Kay SR, Opler LA, Lindenmayer J.-P. The positive and negative syndrome scale (PANSS): rationale and standardisation. Br J Psychiatry. (1989) 155:59–65. doi: 10.1192/S0007125000291514

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

79. Freeman D, Reeve S, Robinson A, Ehlers A, Clark D, Spanlang B, et al. Virtual reality in the assessment, understanding, and treatment of mental health disorders. Psychol Med. (2017) 47:2393–400. doi: 10.1017/S003329171700040X

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

80. Rus-Calafell M, Garety P, Sason E, Craig TJ, Valmaggia LR. Virtual reality in the assessment and treatment of psychosis: a systematic review of its utility, acceptability and effectiveness. Psychol Med. (2018) 48:362. doi: 10.1017/S0033291717001945

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

81. Brannan SK, Sawchak S, Miller AC, Lieberman JA, Paul SM, Breier A. Muscarinic cholinergic receptor agonist and peripheral antagonist for schizophrenia. N Engl J Med. (2021) 384:717–26. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa2017015

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

82. Fryer SL, Roach BJ, Hamilton HK, Bachman P, Belger A, Carrión RE, et al. Deficits in auditory predictive coding in individuals with the psychosis risk syndrome: prediction of conversion to psychosis. J Abnorm Psychol. (2020) 129:599–611. doi: 10.1037/abn0000513

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

83. Perez VB, Woods SW, Roach BJ, Ford JM, McGlashan TH, Srihari VH, et al. Automatic auditory processing deficits in schizophrenia and clinical high-risk patients: forecasting psychosis risk with mismatch negativity. Biol Psychiatry. (2014) 75:459–69. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2013.07.038

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: schizophrenia, computational modeling, assertive community treatment, coordinated speciality care, hallucination, positive symptoms

Citation: Benrimoh D, Sheldon A, Sibarium E and Powers AR (2021) Computational Mechanism for the Effect of Psychosis Community Treatment: A Conceptual Review From Neurobiology to Social Interaction. Front. Psychiatry 12:685390. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2021.685390

Received: 25 March 2021; Accepted: 18 June 2021;
Published: 27 July 2021.

Edited by:

Massoud Stephane, Oregon Health and Science University, United States

Reviewed by:

Elisabetta Filomena Buonaguro, Università di Medicina e Chirurgia Federico II Napoli, Italy

Copyright © 2021 Benrimoh, Sheldon, Sibarium and Powers. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: David Benrimoh, david.benrimoh@mail.mcgill.ca

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.