Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Phys., 09 December 2022
Sec. Statistical and Computational Physics

General commentary: Is the moon there if nobody looks—Bell inequalities and physical reality

  • 1Mathematical Institute, Leiden University, Leiden, Netherlands
  • 2Facultad de Ciencias Exactas y Naturales, Ruta Mcal. J. F. Estigarribia, , San Lorenzo, Paraguay

A Commentary on
Is the moon there if nobody looks—Bell inequalities and physical reality

by Gill R. D. and Lambare J. P. (2020). Front. Phys. 10:00273. doi: 10.3389/fphy.2020.00273

1 Introduction

Marian Kupczynski (“MK”) is the author of a controversial paper published (2020) in the journal Frontiers in Physics [1]. The work is built around a mathematical claim by MK which is actually false, and MK’s reasoning around this claimed assertion is also false. The proof of that is the main content of our present “Comment”. It is merely a mathematical counter-example to a mathematical claim in [1].

2 Bell’s inequalities do hold for Kupzcynski’s model

Kupczynki [1] incorporates hidden variables, standing for random disturbances arising in the measurement apparatus and dependent on the local measurement setting, as follows. Consider an experiment in which Alice and Bob’s settings will be x and y. To begin with, hidden variables (λ1, λ2) with some arbitrary joint probability mass function p(λ1, λ2), not depending on the local settings x and y chosen by the experimenters, are transmitted from the source to the two measurement stations. At Alice’s station and Bob’s station, independently of one another, and independently of (λ1, λ2), local hidden variables λx and λy are created with probability mass functions px(λx) and py(λy). The measurement outcome on Alice’s side is then Ax(λ1, λx), and similarly on Bob’s side, By(λ1, λy). The functions Ax and By depend in any way whatever on x and y respectively; even the domains of these functions can vary. The sets of possible outcomes of λx and λy may depend on x and y respectively. Now repeat this story with, instead of x, y, settings x, y′, then x′, y, then x′, y′. In this way, Kupczynski has defined the four expectation values E(AxBy), E(AxBy), E(AxBy), E(AxBy) of interest, on four “dedicated” hidden variable spaces, which he moreover states are “disjoint”. Therefore, he is unable to define certain “counterfactual” expectations which are used in his proof in the non-contextual case of the Bell-CHSH inequalities. Does this mean that the inequalities need not hold? His argument that they could be violated is based on the huge number of free parameters which his model allows. However, he does not actually specify any particular instantiation of all those parameters which does the job. He does claim that other authors did already do just that.

MK says about his framework: “counterfactual expectations E(AxAx), E(ByBy), E(AxAxByBy) do not exist and Bell and CHSH inequalities may not be derived”. He hereby refers to the usual CHSH inequalities for the four expectations E(AxBy), E(AxBy), E(AxBy), E(AxBy). The context is a Bell-type experiment in which Alice chooses between settings x and x′, and Bob chooses between settings y and y′. MK talks about four different Kolmogorov probability models for the four sub-experiments (one setting choice for Alice and one for Bob). Here are his expressions for the four expectation values of interest, where we have amplified his already long formulas by inserting part of the definition of the four underlying sample spaces Λxy, Λxy, Λxy, Λxy.

EAxBy=λ1,λ2,λx,λyΛxyAxλ1,λxByλ2,λypxλxpyλypλ1,λ2,
EAxBy=λ1,λ2,λx,λyΛxyAxλ1,λxByλ2,λypxλxpyλypλ1,λ2,
EAxBy=λ1,λ2,λx,λyΛxyAxλ1,λxByλ2,λypxλxpyλypλ1,λ2,
EAxBy=λ1,λ2,λx,λyΛxyAxλ1,λxByλ2,λypxλxpyλypλ1,λ2.

These four equations are a complicated way to say the following: with settings x, y, hidden variables (λ1, λ2) with some arbitrary joint probability mass function p(λ1, λ2) (independent of x and y) are transmitted from the source to the two measurement stations. At Alice’s station and Bob’s station, independently of one another, local hidden variables λx and λy are created with probability mass functions px(λx) and py(λy). The measurement outcome on Alice’s side is Ax(λ1, λx), and similarly on Bob’s side, By(λ1, λy). Now repeat this story with, instead of x, y, settings x, y′, then x′, y, then x′, y′. Kupczynski has defined these expectation values on four “dedicated” hidden variable spaces, which he moreover states are “disjoint”. Therefore, he says, he is unable to defined certain “counterfactual” expectations which his proof in the non-contextual case used, and hence he can’t derive Bell and CHSH inequalities.

But we can do all that! And we can even use his original proof in the non-contextual case to get those inequalities! Here is just one of many ways.

Take as sample space a set of tuples λ = (λ1, λ2, λx, λx, λy, λy). This space is just the Cartesian product of the spaces whose existence Kupczynski already hypothesized. Take as probability mass function on this space the product p(λ1, λ2)px(λx)px(λx)py(λy)py(λy). Finally, define new measurement functions A(λ, x) = Ax(λ1, λx), B(λ, y) = By(λ2, λy) where x can be replaced by x′ and/or y by y′. Now compute E(AxBy), also with x replaced by x′ and/or y by y′. It is immediately clear that the four new expectation values of products have exactly the same values as those just exhibited of Kupczynski’s. We can now go back to Kupczynski’s own earlier traditional derivation of Bell-CHSH. There is no barrier to running through the usual proof since all four expectations of products are defined on the same probability space.

There are more efficient constructions. As one learns in courses on Monte Carlo simulation, one can define a discrete random variable with an arbitrary probability distribution as a function of a single uniformly distributed random variable on the unit interval [0, 1]. Thus one could define λx and λx as functions of a single uniformly distributed random variable U1 and of a second argument x or x′; similarly define λy and λy as functions of a single, independent, uniformly distributed random variable U2 and of a second argument y or y′. We just add to our original (λ1, λ2) two independent random variables U1, U2 and redefine our measurement functions in the obvious way. In this way, we can accomodate any number of setting choices for Alice and Bob without introducing more “contextual” randomness into the two measurement functions. This is an important insight. Contextual randomness does not need randomness dependent on the setting. The setting dependence can be passed into the deterministic part of the model.

3 Discussion

We have proved that MK’s claim that his hidden variables model does not allow Bell’s inequalities to be derived is a false mathematical statement. Furthermore, Mk’s paper also contains an obvious contradiction when he inadvertently validates Bell’s model stating that “Although the expectations calculated using Equations (11–14) and (19–22) have the same values, the two sets of formulas describe different experiments”. Since both systems of equations “have the same values”, MK’s hidden variables model also satisfies the Bell inequality.

Kupcynski’s blunder arises from a literal interpretation of different equivalent mathematical expressions, one of which has a direct physical meaning, while the other, obtained after correct mathematical transformations, does not. Curiously, such confusion, which first appeared in 1972 [2], persists to this day [3]. References [4, 5] explain similar inconsistencies arising from joint probabilities and incompatibility.

Also his criticism of past “loophople-free” Bell experiments is unduly harsh and he seems unaware of methodology already in use which minimalises the problem of apparent violation of “no-signalling”. A more detailed explanation can be found in a longer and earlier version of this paper available on arXiv.org [6].

Data availability statement

The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/supplementary material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding author.

Author contributions

RG initiated this project and wrote an initial draft which he shared with JP. Discussions led to many changes that resulted on a preprint [6]. We decided to summarise our findings in a short “Comment” in Frontiers in Physics. In the meantime, MK published a response [7] to our preprint [6] and a debate ensued on PubPeer.org.

Acknowledgments

RDG is grateful for numerous discussions with Marian Kupczynski on his work.

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

References

1. Kupczynski M. Is the moon there if nobody looks: Bell inequalities and physical reality. Front Phys (2020) 8:13. doi:10.3389/fphy.2020.00273

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

2. de la Peña L, Cetto AM, Brody TA. On hidden-variable theories and Bell’s inequality. Lett Nuovo Cimento (1972) 5:177–81. doi:10.1007/BF02815921

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

3. Lambare JP. On the relevance of Bell’s probabilistic model for spin correlations. Quan Stud : Math Found (2022) 9:211–7. doi:10.1007/s40509-021-00265-7

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

4. Lambare JP, Franco R. A note on Bell’s theorem logical consistency. Found Phys (2021) 51:84. doi:10.1007/s10701-021-00488-z

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

5. Lambare JP. Comment on “Nonlocality claims are inconsistent with Hilbert-space quantum mechanics”. Phys Rev A (Coll Park) (2021) 104:066201. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.104.066201

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

6.Kupczynski’s contextual setting-dependent parameters offer no escape from Bell-CHSH Richard D. Gill, Justo Pastor Lambare (2022), Available at: https://arxiv.org/abs/2208.09930.

Google Scholar

7. Kupczynski M. Is the moon there if nobody looks: A reply to gill and lambare (2020), Available at: https://arXiv.org/abs/2209.07992.

Google Scholar

Keywords: Bell’s theorem, local realism, quantum entanglement, contextuality, Bell-CHSH inequality

Citation: Gill RD and Lambare JP (2022) General commentary: Is the moon there if nobody looks—Bell inequalities and physical reality. Front. Phys. 10:1024718. doi: 10.3389/fphy.2022.1024718

Received: 22 August 2022; Accepted: 21 November 2022;
Published: 09 December 2022.

Edited by:

Jonas Maziero, Federal University of Santa Maria, Brazil

Reviewed by:

Adam Bednorz, University of Warsaw, Poland
Janne Kujala, University of Turku, Finland
Philippe Grangier, UMR8501 Laboratoire Charles Fabry (LCF), France

Copyright © 2022 Gill and Lambare. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Richard D. Gill, gill@math.leidenuniv.nl

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.