- University of Paris, Paris, France
All the arguments of a wavefunction are defined at the same instant, implying the notion of simultaneity. In a somewhat related matter, certain phenomena in quantum mechanics seem to have non-local causal relations. Both concepts contradict the special relativity. We propose defining the wavefunction with respect to the invariant proper time of special relativity instead of the standard time. Moreover, we shall adopt the original idea of Schrodinger, suggesting that the wavefunction represents an ontological cloud-like object that we shall call “individual fabric” that has a finite density amplitude vanishing at infinity. Consequently, the action of measurement can be assimilated to the introduction of a confining potential that triggers an inherent nonlocal mechanism within the individual fabric. This mechanism is formalised by multiplying the wavefunction with a localising Gaussian, as in the GRW theory, but in a deterministic manner.
Introduction
As clearly explained by Travis Norsen in his book “Foundations of Quantum Mechanics” [1] there are three main interconnected problems in Quantum Mechanics: measurement, relativity (non-locality and simultaneity) and ontology of a wavefunction.
Quantum measurements can be highlighted by measuring the physical properties of a microscopic system using a measuring instrument. Suppose the quantum mechanical wavefunction describing the microscopic system is in a superposition of the eigenstates of an operator corresponding to the physical property that is being measured. Then, contrary to real observations, the Schrodinger equation evolution implies that the measuring instrument should be in a macroscopic superposition of many distinct states. Standard quantum mechanics (Copenhagen interpretation) solves this problem of macroscopic superposition by introducing Born’s rule. This rule postulates that a wavefunction evolves deterministically in accordance with Schrodinger’s equation, except during measurement when it collapses with a certain probability measure to one particular eigenstate. The measurement problem consists of understanding this paradoxical transition from a deterministically evolving spread-out wavefunction into a sudden probabilistic localisation.
The relativity problem concerns two main interrelated features. The first relates to the relativity of simultaneity which is a consequence of Lorentz invariance, and the second relates to the notion of relativistic locality. In quantum mechanics, all the arguments of a wavefunction are defined at the same instant, thus requiring the notion of absolute simultaneity. For example, a quantum system composed of a pair of entangled particles behaves in such a manner that the quantum state of one particle cannot be described independently of the state of the other. Standard quantum mechanics postulates that neither one of the particles has a determinate state until it is measured. As both particles are correlated, it is necessary that when the state of one particle is measured, the second particle should “simultaneously” acquire a determinate state. However, the laws of physics are invariant under Lorentz transformations. There is no meaning of “simultaneity” independently of any frame of reference, and there should be no preferred frame of Refs. [2, 3]. On the other hand, the nonlocality problem can be resumed by Einstein’s argument that if quantum mechanics is complete, then the collapse of the wave function is a dynamical process that conflicts with relativistic locality. This quantum phenomenon was first introduced as a thought experiment in the EPR paper [4], and it was later discovered that it can be experimentally testable by using Bell’s inequality [5, 6]. Numerous experiments, such as Aspect’s experiment [7], proved the validity of quantum entanglement and hence a certain notion of non-local connections. The notions of non-locality and simultaneity are thus inferred by quantum mechanics while being forbidden by the postulates of relativity. The notions of non-locality, causation, and time in QM are discussed in the papers of L. Felline and K. Thomsen [8, 9].
Finally, the ontological problem concerns the fact that for more than one particle, the wavefunction is defined on a high-dimensional configuration space and not on a physical space, and thus, cannot represent a physically real field. For a physical ontology, the wavefunction should be the representation of a real physical entity.
In addition to the Copenhagen interpretation, there are several candidate theories that propose solutions to at least some of the above problems. Drummond [10] provided a conceptual analysis of these different theories with deep critical insight. The main current theories comprise the Everett many-world theory [11], de Broglie Bohm pilot-wave theory [12, 13], and the GRW spontaneous collapse theory [14]. This study is primarily related to the last two theories.
Everett’s many-world theory [11] discards the collapse postulate, and all measurement results exist but in different worlds. In line with this interpretation, it has been claimed [15] that when a measurement is conducted on a particle in a superposition state, a deterministic branching takes place where, on one branch, a first detector detects the particle while a second detector does not, and at the same time, but on the other branch (i.e. another world), the first detector does not detect the particle while the second detector detects it. However, this interpretation pauses probabilistic and ontological problems. In particular, the axioms of quantum mechanics say nothing about the existence of multiple physical worlds [16]. Greaves [17] provided a detailed account of the probabilistic aspects of this theory.
The de Broglie Bohm theory is very promising and is discussed in detail by Jean Bricmont in his book “Making Sense of Quantum Mechanics” [18] and in Norsen [1] as well as in the Symposium Louis de Broglie, and in particular, in the introduction to this symposium [19]. The basic idea behind this theory is that a corpuscle, such as an electron, always has a well-determined position on a definite trajectory through physical space. However, its movement is influenced by an associated wavefunction, giving rise to wave-like properties. Thus, according to this theory, an electron is a particle “and” a wave. The de Broglie Bohm theory solves the measurement problem and accounts for nonlocality. However, this does not seem to solve the problem of simultaneity. For a multi-particle system, the theory explicitly formulates the dependence of a particle’s evolution at a given instant on the positions of all the other particles at the same instant. Moreover, the ontology of the wavefunction which is defined in the configuration space, remains unclear. However, de Broglie tried to develop [20] a version of the theory according to which interactions between quantum systems are not in the configuration space but in the real three-dimensional physical space.
The GRW spontaneous collapse theory [13] was discussed by Norsen [1]. It modifies Schrodinger’s equation with stochastic terms that has the effect of making a wavefunction obeys Schrodinger’s equation most of the time, except for exceedingly rare and random instants when it undergoes a spontaneous collapse. GRW solves the measurement problem, accounts for non-locality, and provides a physical explanation of the wavefunction. Nevertheless, it does not solve the problem of simultaneity and seems to be ad hoc.
Mielnik [21] showed that an apparent paradox is produced when attempting to reconcile the instantaneous collapse of the wavefunction with the requirements of special relativity. What is instantaneous in one Lorentz frame is not necessarily instantaneous in the other.
Helwig and Kraus [22] provided a formal description of the field measurements according to a covariant description of the relativistic measurement process. They consider a formalism in which the field state remains unchanged in the backward light cone of a finite spacetime region and changes in the forward and side light cones. They advocated the idea that collapse should occur along the backward light cone of the measurement. This picture has been criticised by Aharonov and Albert [23, 24].
Finkelstein [25] illustrates the difficulty of reconciling the collapse with special relativity with the following two assumptions:
A1: A quantum system is represented by a state vector which does not depend on the Lorentz from which the system is described.
A2: When the quantum system is measured, the state vector does, in general, collapse; that is, the state vector will not be independent of time.
Finkelstein [25] considers that both assumptions A1 and A2 can be maintained at the cost of allowing the state vector to depend on the position from which it is described. Finkelstein [25] advocated the idea that it is not meaningful to talk about the state (or probability density) at a given time in the absence of the position from which it is described. He outlines a procedure in which collapse occurs along the forward light cone of measurement, such that all observers at a given spacetime point will obtain the same density operator or state vector. Aharonov and Albert [23, 24] seem to consider that the state vector should not depend on the place from which it is described, and that assumption A1 should be abandoned. Mielnik [21], on the other hand, considers collapse as instantaneous and prefers to abandon A2.
In this paper, we point out that assumptions A1 and A2 are compatible for all observers when the state vector is defined with respect to the proper time instead of ordinary time.
Invariant Spacetime Structure
We propose to consider the evolution of a particle from the perspective of proper time
The Minkowski spacetime
Given the above defined spacetime
We are henceforth interested in physical systems that follow time-like or null worldlines and do not consider the set of space-like vectors. In the spacetime (ℳ, g), a point
Let
Where
Equation 2.4 is a three-dimensional hyperboloid of the two sheets
The modulus
The sheet
Without any loss of generality, we refer hereafter to the two-dimensional space time. Let
Proper time
Where the “+” sign corresponds to a future-directed proper time and the “−” sign corresponds to a past-directed proper time.
For each proper time
Thus, the rays
The hyperbolic slice
The mapping between a point
The inverse mapping of (2.7) can be expressed as follows:
As each slice
The passage from one slice
We note that the passage from one slice
Wavefunction and its Evolution Through Proper Time
In view of the above, we propose to define the wavefunction with respect to the proper time which is indeed the only real physical time. In general, the notion of proper time is defined with respect to the worldline, followed by a particle. However, in this study, we take advantage of the geometrical representation of the proper time, as described in [3, 27]. Indeed, as all the points on a given hyperboloid or slice
We propose to define a unit state vector
For simplicity, we express a slice
The invariant unit state vector
The right-hand side of Eq. 3.2 is defined by a line integral along the piecewise smooth curve representing slice
The left-hand side
The arguments
Hereafter, we define the evolution of the invariant wavefunction
The differential quantum operator associated with energy
It should be noted that momentum and energy operators are generators of translations in space x and time t, respectively, and they operate on the wavefunction to quantify the rate of change of its states. Thus, even though the momentum and energy operators are defined as functions of differentials in space x and time t, respectively, the corresponding momentum and energy observables should not necessarily depend explicitly on space and/or time variables. For example, the momentum and energy observables are stationary for free particles.
To define the energy operator with respect to proper time, we use Eq. 2.6 to express the differential of proper time
The “+/−” signs designate vectors inside the upper/lower light cones. In the upper light-cone
Using relation (3.5), the differential
However, the term
Injecting Eq. 3.7 into Eq. 3.6, we obtain
By substituting Eq. 3.8 into Eq. 3.4, we obtain the following energy operator with respect to the proper time:
The left-hand term of the above expression (17) is the differential operator with respect to proper time
Thus, to describe the evolution of the invariant wavefunction
The solutions of the above system of equations are:
Where
The above solutions can be considered as invariant plane waves with always positive energies. These solutions show that for example, in the future-directed dynamics, an increase in proper time
Equation 3.11 implies that the proper-time evolution operator on an isolated system can be described by unitary operators
Where the “+” sign (respectively, “−” sign) designates a future-directed (respectively, past-directed) evolution of the invariant wavefunction
Expanding expression (3.10) into a system of two equations, while using the relativistic energy
Expressing the momentum
Eq. 3.14 are related in a simple manner to the proper time evolution. This system (Eq. 3.14) of equations shall be called “invariant equation of motion” describing the evolution of the invariant wavefunction
The system of invariant equations of motion (3.14) can be considered a relativistic Schrodinger equation of motion. Indeed, by introducing Eq. 3.8 into the system of Eq. 3.10 while replacing the invariant wavefunction
The energy
Introducing the approximation of Eq. 3.16 into the above system of Eq. 3.15, we obtain
We note that the term
The first equation corresponds to Schrodinger’s standard equation for a free particle in the future direction, while the second equation corresponds to Schrodinger’s equation in the past direction.
On the other hand, relation (3.9)
Thus, applying the above operator to the invariant wavefunction
Developing Eq. 3.20, we obtain an invariant equation of motion equivalent to the system of Eq. 3.10, as follows:
On the other hand, squaring expression (3.8), one gets:
Then, using the above relation, Eq. 3.21 can be transformed into
Introducing the identity of relativistic energy (3.3) into Eq. 3.23, the latter becomes
Finally, expressing the momentum according to its corresponding operator, Eq. 3.24 becomes Klein–Gordon’s equation:
The above analysis shows that the dynamics of the invariant wavefunction with respect to proper time is, on the one hand, equivalent to Klein–Gordon’s equation, and on the other hand, yields Schrodinger’s equation in the non-relativistic limit. This clearly confirms that the original hypothesis of defining the wavefunction with respect to the proper time is reasonable.
On the other hand, the first and second Eqs 3.18 are not mirror images of each other. However, flipping the direction of time
Nevertheless, each equation is invariant under the standard quantum mechanics time-reversal operator [28] within its corresponding light cone. That is, a time-reversal anti-unitary operator consisting of changing the sign of time
Ontology of the Invariant Wavefunction
To gain insight into the ontology of the invariant wavefunction, it would be appropriate to derive the continuity equation from the invariant system of equations of motion (3.14). Hereafter, the continuity equation is considered only in the future-directed upper cone. Multiplying the first equation by the conjugate invariant wavefunction
Subtracting Eq. 4.2 from the first Eq. 4.1 yields the following result:
The above Eq. 4.3 can be simplified, as follows:
Equation 4.4 can be written as a continuity equation:
Where the current
More generally, in a three-dimensional space
Then, the three-dimensional continuity equation becomes:
Integrating the continuity equation over the volume of the entire space:
In the last equality, Gauss’s theorem is used to transform the volume integral into a surface integral over
Therefore, the integral of
It can be outlined from the preceding sections that an invariant wavefunction
Moreover, as explained by Tim Maudlin in his book “Philosophy of Physics: Quantum Theory [32], the wavefunction accounts faithfully for the interference pattern (for example, in a two-slit experiment), and it is reasonable to consider that it represents some real physical features of a physical system. The characteristics and behaviour of the wavefunction should reflect those of the physical system.
Indeed, Schrodinger originally suggested that a particle can be assimilated to a “cloud” that continuously fills the entire space and whose density is given by the square of the wavefunction. This idea has been abandoned by Schrodinger mainly because the cloud continues to diffuse and does not seem to correspond to the relatively sharp macroscopic world [1]. Moreover, all the points of the cloud are defined at the same instant of time, thus contradicting the relative simultaneity principle of special relativity.
Nevertheless, this idea was reintroduced in GRW theory [1, 14]. Hereafter, we adopt this concept in relation to the invariant wavefunction whose points are defined at the same proper time instant which is invariant for all observers and thus, does not contradict the principles of special relativity. The diffusion of Schrodinger’s cloud is highlighted by the continuity Eq. 4.9.
The physical system may thus be considered as a type of continuously spread cloud that we shall call “individual fabric”, which makes part of the spacetime fabric itself. Each individual fabric has its proper identity (or individuality) and has a finite “density amplitude” that vanishes at infinity, reflecting the effects and properties of the corresponding invariant wavefunction. In particular, the density
The dispersion and probabilities of the invariant wavefunction reflect the real density distribution within the corresponding individual fabric. For example, an invariant wavefunction whose density amplitude is defined by a normal distribution would be the result of a normal distribution of the density of the individual fabric. In particular, the dispersion of the invariant wavefunction represents the width of the central region where the density of the individual fabric is concentrated, and the median is the centre of density of the individual fabric, while the tails would represent rarefied peripheral density regions. The region where the density is concentrated interacts the most with its environment and is called the “useful part” of the individual fabric, whereas the rarefied density regions have little or no interactions with their environment.
The idea that the invariant wavefunction
We consider an individual fabric represented by an invariant wavefunction
To express the notion of velocity, we introduce the above formulation into the current Eq. 4.8:
The current
The gradient of the phase
The difference with de Broglie Bohm’s theorem is that here, the parameter
For a free particle, the centre of density
In general, the invariant wavefunction
Analogous to the expression disclosed in Norsen [1], the density distribution
The above expression gives the density distribution
Then, the global density
Where each individual density
This extrapolates Schrodinger’s original idea by first defining the individual density for each particle separately, and then by constructing the global density as the “sum” of all individual densities. Thus, each particle corresponds to an individual fabric whose points
Consequently, the multi-particle invariant wavefunction
However, the global density distribution
The amplitude is expressed as a function of the global density distribution
Generalising the above velocity expression, the velocity
Where each
The gradient of the phase
Indeed, if the particles are correlated, then any change
However, if the particles are not correlated, the wavefunction
The above relation (4.21) can also be expressed in polar form:
Such that;
In this case, for any
In view of the above, it can be concluded that the global fabric should be represented by the multi-particle invariant wavefunction
Moreover, as seen above, the multi-particle invariant wavefunction
A non-factorable invariant wavefunction means that the individual fabrics are “combined” together; that is, they are intermingled or entangled with each other as if formed of a single fabric (having a common global identity) representing a single quantum event. On the other hand, a factorable invariant wavefunction means that the individual fabrics are only “juxtaposed” to each other without being entangled, representing simultaneous quantum events with respect to the proper time.
Contracting Function
The invariant wavefunction
However, the introduction of an external potential such as a confining potential
The abrupt redistribution of the individual fabric’s density due to the abrupt introduction of the external potential may be formalised by multiplying the invariant wavefunction by a contracting function
Where
Equation 5.1 implies that at a proper time instant
In general, the contracting function
However, in accordance with the uncertainty principle, the density of the individual fabric cannot be concentrated beyond an infinitesimally small minimal localised region. In the latter case, the contracting Gaussian
Application: Evolution of a Particle Through a Slit
Let a particle exit from a source, travel towards a barrier with a slit, and pass through the slit before impacting the screen. Let the source be at the origin
A family of slices
The evolution of the particle through the proper time
First Period From the Source to the Barrier
Suppose that initially, at
At a later proper time instant
Where
Second Period at the Barrier and Through the Slit
Suppose that the invariant wavefunction of the free particle interacts with the barrier at a certain proper time instant
Where
The slit potential acts as a contracting function
On the other hand, to avoid the discontinuity at the sharp edges (i.e. at
Suppose that the useful part (i.e. dense region) of the individual fabric comes into contact with the slit barrier at an instant
The interaction of the individual fabric with the slit barrier instantaneously transforms the normalised Gaussian
Where
The multiplication of the invariant wavefunction
However, it should be noted that the entire individual fabric represented by the invariant wavefunction crosses the slit barrier. The useful part of the individual fabric passes through the slit, while the remaining part is so rarified that it does not interact with its environment; thus, it passes through the barrier itself.
Third Period From the Slit to the Screen
Downstream from the slit, the invariant wavefunction starts at a proper time instant
It evolves by spreading out according to the invariant Schrodinger’s equation such that its dispersion increases which, at any instant
Suppose that at a proper time instant
The screen is a barrier that can be assimilated to a constant potential
In particular, the transverse profile of the contracting function at the transverse point
Where the dispersion
The localising Gaussian instantaneously reduces the dispersion of the invariant wavefunction to
Thus, the impact of the useful part of the invariant wavefunction on the screen contracts this useful region to a localised condensed extension
The impact of the useful part of the individual fabric with the screen produces a complete transition of the density of the wavefunction from a stretched state to a localised state. This is similar to the localising function in the GRW theory, except that it is not a random spontaneous collapse but rather a response to the interaction between the wavefunction and the screen.
To estimate the localised condensed extension
Where
Therefore, the radius of the well or the dispersion
We note that the uncertainty in momentum is
By injecting the parameters relative to an electron having, for example, an energy E of 600 eV in Equation (50), we obtain a dispersion
It should be noted that if the barrier in the second period had two slits centred at
Measurement
In view of the above, measurement may not be the right term to use because the outcome of a measurement is not a pre-existing value. In particular, the measurement of the position of a physical system is a transformation like all others; the only special thing is that it transforms a pre-existing fabric having a stretched density into a fabric that has a highly localised density. This transformation is triggered by the introduction of a confining potential. Measurement can thus be formalised by multiplying the wavefunction
Consequently, the individual fabric exhibits a wave-like behaviour when most of its density is in a stretched state and a particle-like behaviour when most of its density is in a minimally contracted or localised state.
Moreover, the invariant Schrodinger’s equation is always applicable, and discontinuity arises only because the process of interaction or measurement modifies the potential in the equation.
In general, the wavefunction
Similar to the GRW theorem [14] and as explained in detail for a two-particle system in [1], if the wavefunction is in the non-entangled (i.e. factorizable) state, the localisation of a particular dense region of an individual fabric does not affect the other dense regions. A localising Gaussian
In a macroscopic object, each particle’s individual fabric is subject to a confining potential corresponding to a resultant action created by all the other individual fabrics. Indeed, the interaction between the different particles confines the dense part of each fabric (represented by its wavefunction) within the confining potential; thus, a macroscopic object is always in a localised state.
Discussion
Each individual fabric extends throughout the entire space; thus, all the individual fabrics in the universe may be represented by a single universal wavefunction
Each individual fabric may be considered as a cosmological continuum, such that the global fabric represents the universe with all its constituents (matter, energy, dark matter, dark energy, and vacuum). The book edited by Valeri Dvoeglazov [34] gives particular attention to the concept of vacuum or ether, and hints at an obvious relation between the ether and dark matter or dark energy. Indeed, as the density distribution of free particles continues to stretch, it may be speculated that dark matter is composed of completely free individual fabrics (i.e. free particles) such that the density distribution of each individual fabric is so rarefied that it does not interact with its environment, while the global distribution of all the individual fabrics still has a gravitational effect.
We note that there is a different promising approach based on process algebra. Sulis [35, 36] proposed a descriptive theory by assuming a generated reality following Whitehead’s process theory [37]. Whitehead [37] considered a process to be a sequence of events having a coherent temporal structure in which relations between events are more fundamental than the events themselves. The process algebra model posits a fundamental level of finite, discrete events upon which the usual entities of quantum mechanics supervene. It is argued that information and information flow provide an ontology of this fundamental level. Higher level constructs such as energy, momentum, mass, and spacetime are all emergent from this fundamental level. The model is compatible with both quantum mechanics and special relativity. It produces the results of quantum mechanics while still maintaining causally local realism.
However, in this study, we adhere to a more classical approach where the wavefunction is considered to represent the real physical features of a physical system.
Conclusion
The quantum state of a physical system can be described by an invariant wavefunction
Quantum measurement of the position of a physical system is a transformation caused by the introduction of a confining potential that triggers an instantaneous contraction of the dense region of the individual (or global) fabric. It is an inherent non-local transformation within the fabric itself, whereas the movement of the fabric relative to all others (i.e. with respect to the spacetime fabric) is local.
The author has declared that no competing interests exist.
All relevant data are within the paper.
This research did not receive any specific grant from funding agencies in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.
Data Availability Statement
The original contributions presented in the study are included in the article/Supplementary Material, further inquiries can be directed to the corresponding authors.
Author Contributions
I am the unique author (SY).
Conflict of Interest
The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Publisher’s Note
All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.
Acknowledgments
I wish to thank Jérôme Lacaille, Jean Bricmont, Maurice Courbage and Eric Augard for many valuable, very helpful and fruitful discussions. I also wish to thank the reviewers who provided helpful commentary and additional references.
References
2.Albert Einstein. Zur Elektrodynamik Bewegter Körper (On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies). Annalen der Physik (1905) 17:891. doi:10.1002/andp.19053221004
3. Maudlin T. Philosophy of Physics: Space and Time. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press (2012).
4. Einstein A, Podolsky B, Rosen N. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? Phys Rev (1935) 47(10):777–80. doi:10.1103/physrev.47.777
5. Bell JS. On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox. Physics (1964) 1(3):195–200. doi:10.1103/physicsphysiquefizika.1.195
6. Bell JS. On the Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics. Rev Mod Phys (1966) 38:447–52. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.38.447
7. Aspect A, Grangier P, Roger G. Experimental Realization of Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-BohmGedankenexperiment: A New Violation of Bell's Inequalities. Phys Rev Lett (1982) 49(2):91–4. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.49.91
8. Felline L. On Explaining Quantum Correlations: Causal vs. Non-causal. Entropy (2021) 23:589. doi:10.3390/e23050589
9. Thomsen K. Timelessness Strictly Inside the Quantum Realm. Entropy (2021) 23:772. doi:10.3390/e23060772
10. Drummond B. Understanding Quantum Mechanics: A Review and Synthesis in Precise Language. Open Phys (2019) 17:390–437. doi:10.1515/phys-2019-0045
11. Everett H. The Theory of the Universal Wave Function. Thesis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University (1956).
13. Bohm D. A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of "Hidden" Variables. I. Phys Rev (1952) 85:166–79. doi:10.1103/physrev.85.166
14. Ghirardi GC, Rimini A, Weber T. Unified Dynamics for Microscopic and Macroscopic Systems. Phys Rev D (1986) 34:470–91. doi:10.1103/physrevd.34.470
16. Kent A. One World vs. Many: The Inadequacy of Everettian Accounts of Evolution, Probability, and Scientific Confirmation. arXiv: quant-ph/0905.0624v3 (2013).
17. Greaves H. Understanding Deutsch’s Probability in a Deterministic Multiverse. Stud Hist Philos Sci B: Stud Hist Philos Mod Phys (2004) 35:423–56. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2004.04.006
19. Durt T, Fargue D, Matzkin A, Robert J. Symposium Louis de Broglie. Ann de la Fondation Louis de Broglie (2021) 46(1).
20. Colin S, Durt T, Willox R, de L. Broglie’s Double Solution Program: 90 Years Later. Ann de la Fondation Louis de Broglie (2017) 42:19.
21. Mielnik B. The Paradox of Two Bottles in Quantum Mechanics. Found Phys (1990) 20:745–55. doi:10.1007/bf01889459
22. Helwig KE, Kraus K. Formal Description of Measurements in Local Quantum Field Theory. Phs Rev (1970) D1:566. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.1.566
23. Aharonov Y, Albert DZ. States and Observables in Relativistic Quantum Field Theories. Phys Rev D (1980) 21:3316–24. doi:10.1103/physrevd.21.3316
24. Aharonov Y, Albert DZ. Can We Make Sense Out of the Measurement Process in Relativistic Quantum Mechanics? Phys Rev D (1981) 24:359–70. doi:10.1103/physrevd.24.359
25. Finkelstein J. Covariant Collapse of the State Vector and Realism. Found Phys Lett (1992) 5(4):383. doi:10.1007/bf00690595
28. Wigner E. Group Theory and its Application to the Quantum Mechanics of Atomic Spectra. New York, NY: Academic Press (1959).
29. Loprez C. Seeking for a Fundamental Quantum Arrow of Time. Front Phys (2018) 6:104. doi:10.3389/fphy.2018.00104
32. Maudlin T. Philosophy of Physics: Quantum Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press (2019).
35. Sulis W. Locality Is Dead! Long Live Locality!. Front Phys (2020) 8:360. doi:10.3389/fphy.2020.00360
36. Sulis W. An Information Ontology for the Process Algebra Model of Non-relativistic Quantum Mechanics. Entropy (Basel) (2020) 22(2):136. doi:10.3390/e22020136
Keywords: proper time, non-locality, simultaneity, wavefunction, measurement
Citation: Yasmineh S (2021) Ontology of a Wavefunction from the Perspective of an Invariant Proper Time. Front. Phys. 9:770764. doi: 10.3389/fphy.2021.770764
Received: 04 September 2021; Accepted: 19 November 2021;
Published: 22 December 2021.
Edited by:
Jinjin Li, Shanghai Jiao Tong University, ChinaCopyright © 2021 Yasmineh. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
*Correspondence: Salim Yasmineh, sayasmineh@gmail.com