Skip to main content

OPINION article

Front. Psychiatry, 30 June 2020
Sec. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Rehabilitation
This article is part of the Research Topic Ethics in Psychiatry and Psychotherapy View all 16 articles

To Overcome Psychiatric Patients’ Mind–Brain Dualism, Reifying the Mind Won’t Help

  • Theory and History of Psychology, Heymans Institute for Psychological Research, Faculty of Behavioral and Social Sciences, University of Groningen, Groningen, Netherlands

Introduction

Glannon (1) summarized recent research in Biological Psychiatry and discussed possible ethical implications of mind–brain dualism in psychiatry in this journal. He particularly addressed the risk that patients might disregard neuroscientific discoveries and subsequently neglect effective biological treatments for psychiatric disorders. In this opinion article, I want to emphasize how some philosophers and scientists still use dualistic language, leading researchers and, to a lesser degree, clinicians into unnecessary and possibly even confused debates on mind–body reductionism; I also briefly address empirical data suggesting that, in contrast to Glannon, patients at large presently don’t seem to eschew biological treatments.

From Soul-Body to Mind–Brain Dualism

René Descartes distinguished a thinking substance (soul) and extended substance (body) and hypothesized, based on his physiological studies, that both interact primarily in humans’ pineal gland (2, 3). Already his contemporaries criticized the lacking explanation of the mechanism of interaction between brain/body and soul, as documented, for example, in the letters between Descartes and Princess Elisabeth of the Palatinate (4). Even centuries later, philosophers and neuroscientists have pointed out that the language use of many scholars remains problematically dualistic, even when they believe to have long overcome mind–brain dualism (5).

Glannon favors a biopsychosocial stance on psychiatric disorders, acknowledging social, psychological, and neural factors. But he frequently mentions “mind–brain interaction”, though, without explaining this concept. This reiterates Descartes’ unsolved problem. Philosophy of Mind has found no clear answer to the question what “the mind” is. One of the major schools of psychology, Behaviorism, actually found the whole concept suspicious and in need of replacement by more scientific terms (6); a similar idea was later formulated by philosophers as Eliminative Materialism (7). Speaking of “the mind” as if it were a thing interacting with the brain/body (1, 8) is thus by no means trivial.

Descriptive Levels

Instead, I propose to speak of processes which are psychological processes if and only if they fall under a psychological description. Similar to Dennett’s Intentional Stance (9), this is a pragmatical proposal that requires no strict commitment about whether psychological descriptions will ever be reducible to neuroscientific (or even more basic: physical) descriptions. This is also reflected in psychological experimentation—as well as clinical or cognitive neuroscience inasmuch as they make use of psychological concepts—where researchers operationalize psychological concepts to explain people’s experience and behavior without necessarily placing them “in the mind” or reducing them to the brain. Reductions are much less common even in the natural sciences than often assumed in that debate, anyway: Biology and chemistry, for example, are obviously necessary, because there are processes in the world (e.g. life) which cannot be described in purely physical language. And it is also not clear what the final, most basic level of a physical description should be (10, 11). That of energy, information, or yet something different? Thus, perhaps not even all physical descriptions might be reducible to the most basic physical level of description, whatever that may be.

The sciences, including human and social sciences like psychology, sociology, and economics, continue to develop in a pluralistic, non-reductive way, informing each other in many respects. And a much more promising alternative to reductive explanations are mechanistic explanations (12, 13). They integrate different levels of description, instead of replacing them. I will use an example to briefly explain what this could mean for psychiatric disorders.

An Example

Imagine Karla hearing that her spouse and children died in a traffic accident. Although that accident involved all kinds of physical and biological processes, described as changes of energy matter, molecules, tissues, and so on, they cannot express the significance for Karla that her beloved ones passed away so suddenly. But we need not assume an independent, reified1 “mind” to state that at the moment she understands (psychology) the message, all kinds of processes will occur in her: Karla might first react with denial (psychology), a severe stress response might happen in her body (physiology), electric activity and molecules may change in her nervous system (neurophysiology) and likely also affect some neural structures permanently (neuroanatomy).

As time proceeds, Karla probably experiences grief and perhaps even depression; serious life events are indeed the strongest known risk factors for distress and Major Depressive Disorder (MDD) (14, 15). Again, this will also involve processes on different levels, as described before, including neuroscientific levels. Glannon actually summarizes much neuroscientific research consistent with such multi-level descriptions. We may ask what is specific about hearing that one’s loved ones died which is causing all these effects; but this does not require us to posit a “mind” entity mysteriously interacting with the brain. Instead, a mechanistic explanation can integrate all levels of description (16), also in line with the biopsychosocial model (17, 18). On the psychological level of description, philosophical concepts like intentional (e.g. what a thought is about) or phenomenal content (e.g. what it feels like) that are considered as unique features of the mental domain can play a role, too (19).

This pluralistic approach has much affinity with the way psychiatric disorders are classified: In the case of MDD, symptoms involve cognitive patterns (e.g. guilt or suicidal ideation), behaviors (e.g. inactivity or a suicide attempt), and physiological changes (e.g. losing weight). Taking the DSM-5 criteria (20), MDD could be expressed by 227 different variants of the symptoms, without even taking their severity into account (21). For attention-deficit-/hyperactivity disorder (ADHD), actually even more than 10,000 variations could be distinguished on the basis of the DSM criteria. This demonstrates a high degree of descriptive heterogeneity of such disorder categories. As Glannon described, Biological Psychiatry found neuroscientific patterns statistically correlated with such instances of MDD and many other disorders. But not a single one of the hundreds of disorders classified in the DSM can generally be described, let alone individually diagnosed, on the neuroscientific level alone (22, 23). Reductionism does not seem to be a successful paradigm in psychiatry, with clinical researchers looking for a brain-based nosology since more than 170 years (24), when psychiatric disorders are not generally classified on the neuroscientific level, cannot be diagnosed on that level in individual cases, and a patient’s treatment response cannot be assessed there alone. It has been discussed elsewhere that this can be partially explained by the limitations of present methodology (22, 25) or the normativity of psychiatric disorders (26, 27).

Implications for Patients’ Treatment Choices

So far, the discussion was primarily relevant to researchers and, to a lesser degree, clinicians. Glannon (1) raised concerns about mind–brain dualism in psychiatry and related patients’ understanding of psychiatric disorders to the risk that they might eschew effective biological treatments when they take a limited psychological stance. Besides the new approaches on brain stimulation described by Glannon, medical consumption patterns indicate, though, that ever more people are taking psychopharmacological drugs. For example, the annual production of ADHD medication in the US is presently higher than during the whole decade of the 1990s (28). The pattern for other psychopharmacological drugs (Figure 1) and in many other countries is similar (30).

FIGURE 1
www.frontiersin.org

Figure 1 Annual production of the schedule II regulated ADHD drugs amphetamine (red) and methylphenidate (blue, left scale, x 1,000 kg) and adult patients annually receiving antidepressant drugs in the United States (yellow, right scale, x 1,000,000). The production of the ADHD drugs has increased more than thirtyfold, the number of MDD patients receiving antidepressants about threefold in the shown period. It must be also noted, though, that in the period shown the criteria for diagnosing ADHD changed, for example, with respect to adult ADHD and the DSM-5 of 2013 (20). Source: updated from (28), US Federal Register; (29).

Humans have actually used substances (e.g. alcohol or other stimulating, relaxing, or hallucinogenic drugs) instrumentally, for their psychological effects, probably as long as we exist (31, 32). The recent neuro-enhancement debate exemplifies a similar trend to improve one’s cognitive performance or feelings pharmacologically (28, 33). It thus seems to be common knowledge in human history that behavior and experience can be affected by consuming certain substances or performing particular rituals (e.g. dance, sports, or prayer). Whether or not many people have dualistic views, believing in the existence of independent “minds” or “souls”, they nevertheless seem to endorse biological means to solve their problems or achieve their aims, perhaps even increasingly so. Many decades ago, Klerman described that people differ in their readiness to take pharmacological drugs, distinguishing the extreme poles of “Psychotropic Hedonism” on the one hand and “Pharmacological Calvinism” on the other, but rather due to their lifestyle choices than philosophical world-views (34, 35). After the “Decade of the Brain” and the Human Genome Project, the analysis of science communication patterns and people’s descriptions of their psychiatric problems rather suggest, in contrast to Glannon’s concern, that patients might presently rather underestimate the value of psychotherapy, not biological treatments (36, 37).

Conclusion: Integration Instead of Reduction

Variants of dualism have been discussed in philosophy for centuries. I tried to show here that we neither need to postulate “souls” nor “minds” to describe people’s behaviors or experiences. To overcome dualism, reifying “the mind” won’t help. Using a dualistic language that postulates “mind–brain interactions” reiterates old questions about the nature of the mental entity, its mechanism of interaction with the brain/body, and gives rise to endless discussions on reductionism that neither seems to be fruitful nor relevant to empirical research in psychology or the neurosciences. The biopsychosocial model and mechanistic explanations can take different levels of descriptions into account, without demanding reductions; as colleagues and I explained earlier, neuroscience can also be integrative (38). That people probably always have and are still using different means to change their brain/body and thus facilitate certain behaviors and experiences is also rather compatible with a pluralistic than a dualistic or reductionistic view. Instead of proposing an either-or-account, it goes without saying that many biological treatments have psychological effects (i.e. effects that we can only describe on the psychological level) and that psychological treatments are changing the brain/body. To ensure that psychiatric patients can consent to the best available treatment, it is essential, in my view, that they are informed in a neutral, pluralistic, and comprehensible way about all different options.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and has approved it for publication.

Funding

This publication has been supported by the “History of Neuroethics” grant by the Dutch Research Foundation (NWO), grant number 451-15-042.

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Footnotes

  1. ^ The term reification is derived from the Latin res, thing. Reification means thus to consider something as a thing. Talking about brain–mind-interaction thus assumes that there are two entities, brain and mind, which are interacting in some way.

References

1. Glannon W. Mind-Brain Dualism in Psychiatry: Ethical Implications. Front Psychiatry (2020) 11(85). doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2020.00085

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

2. Descartes R. Meditationes de prima philosophia. Paris: Michael Soly (1641).

Google Scholar

3. Descartes R. Les Passions de l’âme. Paris: Henry Le Gras (1649).

Google Scholar

4. Shapiro L. Elisabeth, Princess of Bohemia. In: Zalta EN, editor. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Winter 2014 Edition (2014).

Google Scholar

5. Bennett MR, Hacker PMS. Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub (2003).

Google Scholar

6. Skinner BF. What Is Man? In: Skinner BF, editor. Beyond Freedom and Dignity. Toronto and New York: Bantam/Vintage (1971). p. 175–206.

Google Scholar

7. Churchland PM. Eliminative Materialism and Propositional Attitudes. J Philos (1981) 78(2):67–90. doi: 10.5840/jphil198178268

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

8. Westphal J. The mind-body problem. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press (2016).

Google Scholar

9. Dennett DC. The intentional stance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press (1987).

Google Scholar

10. Montero B. The Body Problem. Noûs (1999) 33(2):183–200. doi: 10.1111/0029-4624.00149

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

11. Montero B. What Is the Physical? In: McLaughlin B, Beckermann A, Walter S, editors. The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press (2005). p. 173–88.

Google Scholar

12. Craver CF. Explaining the brain: mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press (2007).

Google Scholar

13. Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF. Thinking about Mechanisms. Philos Sci (2000) 67(1):1–25. doi: 10.1086/392759

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

14. Kendler KS, Karkowski LM, Prescott CA. Causal relationship between stressful life events and the onset of major depression. Am J Psychiatry (1999) 156(6):837–41. doi: 10.1176/ajp.156.6.837

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

15. Mirowsky J, Ross CE. Social causes of psychological distress. 2nd ed. New Brunswick (U.S.A.): AldineTransaction (2012).

Google Scholar

16. Kendler KS, Zachar P, Craver C. What kinds of things are psychiatric disorders? Psychol Med (2011) 41(6):1143–50. doi: 10.1017/S0033291710001844

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

17. Engel GL. The need for a new medical model: a challenge for biomedicine. Science (1977) 196(4286):129–36. doi: 10.1126/science.847460

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

18. Kendler KS. The dappled nature of causes of psychiatric illness: replacing the organic-functional/hardware-software dichotomy with empirically based pluralism. Mol Psychiatry (2012) 17(4):377–88. doi: 10.1038/mp.2011.182

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

19. Pernu TK. The Five Marks of the Mental. Front Psychol (2017) 8(1084). doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01084

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

20. American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5. 5th ed. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association (2013).

Google Scholar

21. Schleim S. Subjective Experience, Heterophenomenology, or Neuroimaging? A Perspective on the Meaning and Application of Mental Disorder Terms, in Particular Major Depressive Disorder. Front Psychol (2018) 9(702). doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00702

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

22. Frisch S. Are Mental Disorders Brain Diseases, and What Does This Mean? A Clinical-Neuropsychological Perspective. Psychopathology (2016) 49(3):135–42. doi: 10.1159/000447359

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

23. Gardner C, Kleinman A. Medicine and the Mind - The Consequences of Psychiatry’s Identity Crisis. N Engl J Med (2019) 381(18):1697–9. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp1910603

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

24. Griesinger W. Die Pathologie und Therapie der psychischen Krankheiten, für Aerzte und Studirende. Stuttgart: Verlag von Adolph Krabbe (1845).

Google Scholar

25. Schleim S, Roiser JP. fMRI in translation: the challenges facing real-world applications. Front Hum Neurosci (2009) 3(63):1–7. doi: 10.3389/neuro.09.063.2009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

26. Frances A. Saving normal: an insider's revolt against out-of-control psychiatric diagnosis, DSM-5, Big Pharma, and the medicalization of ordinary life. 1st ed. New York, NY: William Morrow, an imprint of HarperCollins publishers (2013).

Google Scholar

27. Stier M. Normative preconditions for the assessment of mental disorder. Front Psychol (2013) 4(611). doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00611

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

28. Schleim S, Quednow BB. How Realistic Are the Scientific Assumptions of the Neuroenhancement Debate? Assessing the Pharmacological Optimism and Neuroenhancement Prevalence Hypotheses. Front Pharmacol (2018) 9(3). doi: 10.3389/fphar.2018.00003

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

29. Luo Y, Kataoka Y, Ostinelli EG, Cipriani A, Furukawa TA. National Prescription Patterns of Antidepressants in the Treatment of Adults With Major Depression in the US Between 1996 and 2015: A Population Representative Survey Based Analysis. Front Psychiatry (2020) 11(35). doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2020.00171

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

30. Bachmann CJ, Wijlaars LP, Kalverdijk LJ, Burcu M, Glaeske G, Schuiling-Veninga CCM, et al. Trends in ADHD medication use in children and adolescents in five western countries, 2005-2012. Eur Neuropsychopharmacol (2017) 27(5):484–93. doi: 10.1016/j.euroneuro.2017.03.002

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

31. Müller CP. Drug instrumentalization. Behav Brain Res (2020) 390:112672. doi: 10.1016/j.bbr.2020.112672

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

32. Müller CP, Schumann G. Drugs as instruments: a new framework for non-addictive psychoactive drug use. Behav Brain Sci (2011) 34(6):293–310. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X11000057

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

33. Schleim S. Whose well-being? Common conceptions and misconceptions in the enhancement debate. Front Syst Neurosci (2014) 8. doi: 10.3389/fnsys.2014.00148

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

34. Klerman GL. Psychotropic Hedonism vs. Pharmacological Calvinism. Hastings Center Rep (1972) 2(4):1–3. doi: 10.2307/3561398

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

35. Schleim S, Quednow BB. Debunking the ethical neuroenhancement debate. In: ter Meulen R, Mohamed AD, Hall W, editors. Rethinking cognitive enhancement: A critical appraisal of the neuroscience and ethics of cognitive enhancement. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press (2017). p. 164–75.

Google Scholar

36. O’Connor C, Joffe H. Social Representations of Brain Research:Exploring Public (Dis)engagement With Contemporary Neuroscience. Sci Commun (2014) 36(5):617–45. doi: 10.1177/1075547014549481

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

37. Racine E, Waldman S, Rosenberg J, Illes J. Contemporary neuroscience in the media. Soc Sci Med (2010) 71(4):725–33. doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2010.05.017

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

38. Kotchoubey B, Tretter F, Braun HA, Buchheim T, Draguhn A, Fuchs T, et al. Methodological Problems on the Way to Integrative Human Neuroscience. Front Integr Neurosci (2016) 10(41). doi: 10.3389/fnint.2016.00041

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: dualism, psychiatric disorders, reductionism, biopsychosocial model, mechanistic explanations

Citation: Schleim S (2020) To Overcome Psychiatric Patients’ Mind–Brain Dualism, Reifying the Mind Won’t Help. Front. Psychiatry 11:605. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2020.00605

Received: 07 April 2020; Accepted: 11 June 2020;
Published: 30 June 2020.

Edited by:

Helen Killaspy, University College London, United Kingdom

Reviewed by:

Oleg Papsuev, Moscow Research Institute of Psychiatry, Russia

Copyright © 2020 Schleim. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Stephan Schleim, cy5zY2hsZWltQHJ1Zy5ubA==

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.