Skip to main content

GENERAL COMMENTARY article

Front. Psychol., 25 July 2018
Sec. Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology
This article is part of the Research Topic Philosophical and Ethical Aspects of a Science of Consciousness and the Self View all 28 articles

Commentary: The Problem of Mental Action: Predictive Control Without Sensory Sheets

  • Institute of Cognitive Sciences and Technologies, National Research Council, Rome, Italy

A commentary on
The Problem of Mental Action: Predictive Control Without Sensory Sheets

by Metzinger, T. (2017). In Philosophy and Predictive Processing, eds T. Metzinger and W. Wiese (Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group), 1–26.

Action-oriented and pragmatic views of cognition, which propose that the action system is part and parcel of various cognitive functions (e.g., perception, memory, and decision-making), are increasingly popular in philosophy, psychology, neuroscience, and robotics (Engel et al., 2016). Different theories stress distinct aspects of action-directedness, such as for example the importance of sensory-motor regularities or contingencies to steer active perception loops (O'Regan and Noe, 2001; Ahissar and Assa, 2016); the reuse of the brain's motor system for “action simulation,” in the service of action perception, imagery, and planning (Jeannerod, 2006); that the brain may be organized to rapidly specify and select actions (Cisek, 1999; Cisek and Kalaska, 2010; Pezzulo and Cisek, 2016). There is however one aspect of action-directedness that has received less attention so far: the possibility for cognitive agents to perform mental actions.

Unlike physical actions, mental actions do not modify the external environment directly. Yet, some internal cognitive operations can be conceptualized as (mental) actions in virtue of their intentional or purposive structure; or, in other words, because they (are selected to) achieve some form of outcome or goal—even if the goal is not specified in terms of outward behavior. Metzinger proposed to conceptualize mental actions as internal operations that change a cognitive agent's state of knowledge (Metzinger, 2017). Mental actions thus have epistemic goal-states (e.g., knowing what the sum of 2 + 3 is) as opposed to the most usual pragmatic goal-states (e.g., reaching a goal location). According to (Metzinger, 2017, p. 1): “Examples of mental action are the volitional control of endogenous attention […], trying to retrieve a series of images from episodic memory, […] as well as engaging in mental calculation, […].”

The idea that mental actions serve epistemic purposes prompts many questions about their role in the architecture of cognition. Here, I focus on a specific question: when should a cognitive agent select a mental action as opposed to a physical action? I will address this problem by casting the above definition of mental action within Active Inference (Friston, 2010; Friston et al., 2012, 2015; Pezzulo et al., 2015, 2017a, 2018).

A tenet of Active Inference is that the brain encodes statistical regularities at multiple timescales—in the form of internal generative models—to steer top-down predictions that support both perception and action. For example, during action selection, the internal models are used to predict and compare the outcomes of alternative courses of actions (or policies). Importantly, in Active Inference, policy evaluation resolves the exploration-exploitation tradeoff by considering both the pragmatic and the epistemic value of actions. With some simplifications, one can imagine two kinds of actions or policies: those that have mainly pragmatic value (exploitation; e.g., navigating to a reward site) and those that have mainly epistemic value (exploration; e.g., collecting a cue to resolve one's own uncertainty about reward location). Computational simulations of foraging show that, during uncertain choices, an agent often needs to firstly select an epistemic action to resolve its uncertainty (e.g., go to a cue location, to collect information about reward location), before it can commit to a specific choice, i.e., before it can confidently select a pragmatic action that leads to the disambiguated reward location (Friston et al., 2015; Pezzulo et al., 2016).

Interestingly, mental actions may be treated in the same way as overt, exploratory actions (e.g., collecting cues) in these foraging simulations; by considering that both serve the epistemic goal to reduce one's own uncertainty about a variable of interest (e.g., uncertainty about “what the sum of 2 + 3 is” vs. “where the reward location is”). Indeed, the exploration-exploitation tradeoff illustrated in the foraging simulations arises in many other choice situations that may involve both physical and mental actions. Imagine one is checking out an apartment for rent, and has to leave the keys inside. This situation may involve the competition between various policies: a policy that only includes pragmatic actions, and which consists in closing the door immediately; a policy that includes mental epistemic actions, and which consists in carefully double-checking mentally whether one has collected all the necessary luggage, until one is confident enough and can then close the door; and a policy that includes physical epistemic actions, and which consists in visiting once more all the rooms, before closing the door. Clearly, policy selection would involve various kinds of trade-offs, both between pragmatic vs. epistemic actions (e.g., a “mental check” takes time but lowers the risk of forgetting luggage), and between mental vs. physical epistemic actions (e.g., a “mental check” is usually faster but more error-prone compared to physical search).

However, these are exactly the sort of trade-offs that arise in any instance of Active Inference, which automatically balances pragmatic and epistemic aspects of policies, depending on various factors such as uncertainty, time pressure and the importance of current goals. In other words, the selection of a mental action (e.g., tapping an episodic memory or performing mental arithmetic) that changes one's epistemic state (e.g., reduces uncertainty before a choice) would conform to the usual exploration-exploitation tradeoffs that have been studied in simpler foraging situations (Friston et al., 2015; Pezzulo et al., 2016). Developing a comprehensive theory of mental action within Active Inference would require endowing an agent with internal models of (and epistemic goals about) it's own inference and belief state; for example, models that describe how the agent's belief state would change as an effect of mental actions, and which would permit considering their costs and benefits during policy selection.

This conceptualization casts mental action within a deliberative scheme, as a form of controlled activity, where the controlled variables are epistemic goal states and mental processes—e.g., the control of imagination (Pezzulo and Castelfranchi, 2009) or of spontaneous mental behavior (Pezzulo et al., 2014, 2017b; Metzinger, 2017)—as opposed to external variables. In this perspective, even though mental actions don't directly influence the sensory-motor stream, they may still have a causal role in the architecture of cognition (Metzinger, 2017); for example, by altering levels of certainty or confidence in adaptive ways before a difficult choice.

Author Contributions

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and approved it for publication.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

References

Ahissar, E., and Assa, E. (2016). Perception as a closed-loop convergence process. eLife 5:e12830. doi: 10.7554/eLife.12830

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Cisek, P. (1999). Beyond the computer metaphor: behavior as interaction. J. Conscious. Stud. 6, 125–142.

Google Scholar

Cisek, P., and Kalaska, J. F. (2010). Neural mechanisms for interacting with a world full of action choices. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 33, 269–298. doi: 10.1146/annurev.neuro.051508.135409

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Engel, A. K., Friston, K. J., and Kragic, D. (2016). The Pragmatic Turn: Toward Action-Oriented Views in Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Google Scholar

Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 11, 127–138. doi: 10.1038/nrn2787

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Friston, K., Rigoli, F., Ognibene, D., Mathys, C., Fitzgerald, T., and Pezzulo, G. (2015). Active inference and epistemic value. Cogn. Neurosci. 6, 187–214. doi: 10.1080/17588928.2015.1020053

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Friston, K., Samothrakis, S., and Montague, R. (2012). Active inference and agency: optimal control without cost functions. Biol. Cybernet. 106, 523–541. doi: 10.1007/s00422-012-0512-8

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor Cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Scholar

Metzinger, T. (2017). “The problem of mental action: predictive control without sensory sheets,” in Philosophy and Predictive Processing, eds T. Metzinger and W. Wiese (Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group), 1–26.

O'Regan, J. K., and Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behav. Brain Sci. 24, 883–917. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X01000115

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., and Castelfranchi, C. (2009). Thinking as the control of imagination: a conceptual framework for goal-directed systems. Psychol. Res. 73, 559–577. doi: 10.1007/s00426-009-0237-z

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., and Cisek, P. (2016). Navigating the affordance landscape: feedback control as a process model of behavior and cognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. 20, 414–424. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2016.03.013

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., Cartoni, E., Rigoli, F., Pio-Lopez, L., and Friston, K. (2016). Active inference, epistemic value, and vicarious trial and error. Learn. Mem. 23, 322–338. doi: 10.1101/lm.041780.116

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., Donnarumma, F., Iodice, P., Maisto, D., and Stoianov, I. (2017a). Model-based approaches to active perception and control. Entropy 19:266. doi: 10.3390/e19060266

CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., Kemere, C., and van der Meer, M. (2017b). Internally generated hippocampal sequences as a vantage point to probe future-oriented cognition. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 1396, 144–165. doi: 10.1111/nyas.13329

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., Rigoli, F., and Friston, K. J. (2015). Active Inference, homeostatic regulation and adaptive behavioural control. Prog. Neurobiol. 136, 17–35. doi: 10.1016/j.pneurobio.2015.09.001

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., Rigoli, F., and Friston, K. J. (2018). Hierarchical active inference: a theory of motivated control. Trends Cogn. Sci. 22, 294–306. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2018.01.009

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Pezzulo, G., van der Meer, M. A., Lansink, C. S., and Pennartz, C. M. (2014). Internally generated sequences in learning and executing goal-directed behavior. Trends Cogn. Sci. 18, 647–657. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2014.06.011

PubMed Abstract | CrossRef Full Text | Google Scholar

Keywords: mental action, predictive processing, active inference, control theory, action-oriented cognition

Citation: Pezzulo G (2018) Commentary: The Problem of Mental Action: Predictive Control Without Sensory Sheets. Front. Psychol. 9:1291. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01291

Received: 27 March 2018; Accepted: 05 July 2018;
Published: 25 July 2018.

Edited by:

Wanja Wiese, Johannes Gutenberg-Universität Mainz, Germany

Reviewed by:

Tom McClelland, University of Warwick, United Kingdom
Francesco Marchi, Ruhr-Universität Bochum, Germany

Copyright © 2018 Pezzulo. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) and the copyright owner(s) are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.

*Correspondence: Giovanni Pezzulo, Z2lvdmFubmkucGV6enVsb0BnbWFpbC5jb20=

Disclaimer: All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article or claim that may be made by its manufacturer is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.